Skip to main content
Log in

Quantum Superpositions and the Representation of Physical Reality Beyond Measurement Outcomes and Mathematical Structures

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we intend to discuss the importance of providing a physical representation of quantum superpositions which goes beyond the mere reference to mathematical structures and measurement outcomes. This proposal goes in the opposite direction to the project present in orthodox contemporary philosophy of physics which attempts to “bridge the gap” between the quantum formalism and common sense “classical reality”—precluding, right from the start, the possibility of interpreting quantum superpositions through non-classical notions. We will argue that in order to restate the problem of interpretation of quantum mechanics in truly ontological terms we require a radical revision of the problems and definitions addressed within the orthodox literature. On the one hand, we will discuss the need of providing a formal redefinition of superpositions which captures explicitly their contextual character. On the other hand, we will attempt to replace the focus on the measurement problem, which concentrates on the justification of measurement outcomes from “weird” superposed states, and introduce the superposition problem which focuses instead on the conceptual representation of superpositions themselves. In this respect, after presenting three necessary conditions for objective physical representation, we will provide arguments which show why the classical (actualist) representation of physics faces severe difficulties to solve the superposition problem. Finally, we will also argue that, if we are willing to abandon the (metaphysical) presupposition according to which ‘Actuality = Reality’, then there is plenty of room to construct a conceptual representation for quantum superpositions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for example, in this same respect, the detailed analysis of the concept of space in the history of physics provided by Max Jammer in his excellent book: The Concepts of Space. The History of Theories of Space in Physics (Jammer 1993).

  2. For a detailed discussion of the closed theory approach see Bokulich (2004) and de Ronde (2016).

  3. See Howard (1993, 2010).

  4. See de Ronde et al. (2014) for discussion and definition of this notion in the context of classical physics.

  5. According to Bohr (Wheeler and Zurek 1983, p. 7): “[...] the unambiguous interpretation of any measurement must be essentially framed in terms of classical physical theories, and we may say that in this sense the language of Newton and Maxwell will remain the language of physicists for all time.” In this respect, he aso added [Op. cit., p. 7] that, “it would be a misconception to believe that the difficulties of the atomic theory may be evaded by eventually replacing the concepts of classical physics by new conceptual forms.”

  6. I am grateful to Bob Coecke for this linguistic insight. Cagliari, July 2014.

  7. Given a quantum system represented by a superposition of more than one term, \(\sum c_i | \alpha _i \rangle\), when in contact with an apparatus ready to measure, \(|R_0 \rangle\), QM predicts that system and apparatus will become “entangled” in such a way that the final ‘system + apparatus’ will be described by \(\sum c_i | \alpha _i \rangle |R_i \rangle\). Thus, as a consequence of the quantum evolution, the pointers have also become—like the original quantum system—a superposition of pointers \(\sum c_i |R_i \rangle\). This is why the measurement problem can be stated as a problem only in the case the original quantum state is described by a superposition of more than one term.

  8. See for a detailed discussion of the paraconsistent character of quantum superpositions: Costa and de Ronde (2013). Also, for a debate regarding the paraconsistent aspect of superpositions: Arenhart and Krause (2016), Arenhart and Krause (2015) and de Ronde (2015).

  9. [Op. cit., p. 156].

  10. The Born rule provides the probability of finding a certain observable via the numbers that accompany the kets within quantum superpositions.

  11. There is in our neo-Spinozist account an implicit ontological pluralism of multiple representations which can be related to one reality through a univocity principle. This is understood in analogous manner to how Spinoza considers in his immanent metaphysics the multiple attributes as being expressions of the same one single substance, namely, nature (see de Ronde 2014, 2016). Our non-reductionistic answer to the problem of inter-theory relation escapes in this way the requirement present in almost all interpretations of QM which implicitly or explicitly attempt to explain the formalism in substantialist atomistic terms. We believe there might be an interesting connection between our neo-Spinozist approach and the ‘multiplex realism’ recently proposed by Aerts and Sassoli de Bianchi (2015). Due to the limited space of this paper we leave this particular analysis and comparison for a future work.

  12. It is true that QBism does provide a subjectivist interpretation of probability following the Bayesian viewpoint, however, this is done so at the price of denying the very need of an interpretation for QM. See for a detailed analysis: de Ronde (2016), de Ronde (2016). Also the hidden measurement approach by Aerts provides an epistemic interpretation of quantum probability but in this case, instead of considering the quantum system alone, the approach focuses on the measurement interaction between system and apparatus (Aerts and Sassoli di Bianchi 2015, 2017).

  13. For a more detailed discussion of the notion of immanent cause we refer to (Melamed 2013, Chapter 2).

References

  • Aerts, D. (2009a). Quantum particles as conceptual entities: A possible explanatory framework for quantum theory. Foundations of Science, 14, 361–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aerts, D. (2009b). Quantum structure in cognition. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53, 314–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aerts, D. (2009c). Interpreting quantum particles as conceptual entities. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 49, 2950–2970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aerts, D. (2010). A Potentiality and conceptuality interpretation of quantum mechancis. Philosophica, 83, 15–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aerts, D., & Aerts, S. (1994). Applications of quantum statistics in psychological studies of decision processes. Foundations of Science, 1, 85–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aerts, D., & D’Hooghe, B. (2009). Classical logical versus quantum conceptual thought: Examples in economics, decision theory and concept theory. In Proceedings of QI 2009-third international symposium on quantum interaction, Lecture Notes in Computer Science (pp. 128–142). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Aerts, D., & D’Hooghe, B. (2010). A Potentiality and conceptuality interpretation of quantum mechancis. Philosophica, 83, 15–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aerts, D., & Sassoli di Bianchi, M. (2015). Many-measurements or many-worlds? A dialogue. Foundations of Science, 20, 399–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aerts, D., & Sassoli di Bianchi, M. (2017). Do spins have directions? Soft Computing, 21, 1483–1504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albert, D. Z., & Loewer, B. (1988). Interpreting the many worlds interpretation. Synthese, 77, 195–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arenhart, J. R., & Krause, D. (2015). Potentiality and contradiction in quantum mechanics. In A. Koslow & A. Buchsbaum (Eds.), The road to universal logic (Vol. II, pp. 201–211). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Arenhart, J. R., & Krause, D. (2016). Contradiction, Quantum mechanics, and the square of opposition. Logique et Analyse, 59, 273–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacciagaluppi, G. (1996). Topics in the modal interpretation of quantum mechanics. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Cambridge, Cambridge.

  • Blatter, G. (2000). Schrodinger’s cat is now fat. Nature, 406, 25–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2004). Open or llosed? Dirac, Heisenberg, and the relation between classical and quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 35, 377–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bub, J. (1997). Interpreting the quantum world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curd, M., & Cover, J. A. (1998). Philosophy of science. The central issues. In Norton and Company (Eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • da Costa, N., & de Ronde, C. (2016). Revisiting the applicability of metaphysical identity in quantum mechanics. Preprint. arXiv:1609.05361

  • da Costa, N., & de Ronde, C. (2013). The paraconsistent logic of quantum superpositions. Foundations of Physics, 43, 845–858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Ariano, M. G., & Perinotti, P. (2016). Quantum theory is an information theory. The operational framework and the axioms. Foundations of Physics, 46, 269–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawin, R., & Thébault, K. (2015). Many worlds: Incoherent or decoherent? Synthese, 192, 1559–1580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Ronde, C. (2014). The problem of representation and experience in quantum mechanics. In D. Aerts, S. Aerts, & C. de Ronde (Eds.), Probing the meaning of quantum mechanics: Physical, philosophical and logical perspectives (pp. 91–111). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • de Ronde, C. (2015). Modality, potentiality and contradiction in quantum mechanics. In J.-Y. Beziau, M. Chakraborty, & S. Dutta (Eds.), New directions in paraconsistent logic (pp. 249–265). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • de Ronde, C. (2016a). Probabilistic knowledge as objective knowledge in quantum mechanics: Potential powers instead of actual properties. In D. Aerts, C. de Ronde, H. Freytes, & R. Giuntini (Eds.), Probing the meaning and structure of quantum mechanics: Superpositions, semantics, dynamics and identity (pp. 141–178). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • de Ronde, C. (2016b). Representational realism, closed theories and the quantum to classical limit. In R. E. Kastner, J. Jeknic-Dugic, & G. Jaroszkiewicz (Eds.), Quantum structural studies (pp. 105–136). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Ronde, C. (2017a). Causality and the modeling of the measurement process in quantum theory. Disputatio (forthcoming).

  • de Ronde, C. (2017b). Hilbert space quantum mechanics is contextual. (Reply to R. B. Griffiths). Cadernos de Filosofia (forthcoming). arXiv:1502.05396

  • de Ronde, C., Freytes, H., & Domenech, G. (2014). Interpreting the modal Kochen–Specker theorem: Possibility and many worlds in quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 45, 11–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, D. (1999). Quantum theory of probability and decisions. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, A455, 3129–3137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeWitt, B., & Graham, N. (1973). The many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D. (1988). The formalism of quantum theory: An objective description of reality. Annalen der Physik, 7, 174–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D. (2007). Probability in the modal interpretation of quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38, 292–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D. (2010). Quantum mechanics, chance and modality. Philosophica, 83, 117–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1974). The principles of quantum mechanics (4th ed.). London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2006). Properties and dispositions: Some metaphysical remarks on quantum ontology. Proceedings of the AIP, 844, 139–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2015). Events and the ontology of quantum mechanics. Topoi, 34, 369–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1916). Ernst Mach. Physikalische Zeitschrift, 17, 101–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., & Rosen, N. (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description be considered complete? Physical Review, 47, 777–780.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everett, H. (1973). The theory of the universal wave function (Ph.D. Thesis, 1956). In Dewitt, B., & Graham, N. (Eds.), The many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics (pp. 3–140). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Fuchs, C., Mermin, N., & Schack, R. (2014). An introduction to QBism with an application to the locality of quantum mechanics. American Journal of Physics, 82, 749.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, C., & Peres, A. (2000). Quantum theory needs no interpretation. Physics Today, 53, 70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2015). What does it feel like to be in a quantum superposition? (preprint). http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/11811/

  • Griffiths, R. B. (2002). Consistent quantum theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, R. B. (2013). Hilbert space quantum mechanics is non contextual. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 174–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartle, J. (2015). Living in a quantum superposition (preprint). arXiv:1511.01550

  • Heisenberg, W. (1958). Physics and philosophy, world perspectives. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1971). Physics and beyond. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1973). Development of concepts in the history of quantum theory. In J. Mehra (Ed.), The physicist’s conception of nature (pp. 264–275). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. (1993). Was Einstein really a realist? Perspectives on Science, 1, 204–251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. (2010). Einstein’s philosophy of science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2010 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/einstein-philscience/.

  • Jammer, M. (1993). Concepts of space. The history of theories of space in physics. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansson, L. (2016). Everettian quantum mechanics and physical probability: Against the principle of ‘State Supervenience’. Studies in history and philosophy of modern physics, 53, 45–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kastner, R. (2012). The transactional interpretation of quantum mechanics: The reality of possibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kastner, R. (2014). Einselection’ of pointer observables: The new H-theorem? Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 48, 56–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kastner, R. (2015). Understanding our unseen reality: Solving quantum riddles. London: Imperial College Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kochen, S., & Specker, E. (1967). On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics, 17, 59–87. (Reprinted in Hooker, 1975, 293–328).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kovachy, T., Asenbaum, P., Overstreet, C., Donnelly, C. A., Dickerson, S. M., Sugarbaker, A., et al. (2015). Quantum superposition at the half-metre scale. Nature, 528, 530–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laplace, P.S. (1951). A philosophical essay on probabilities. Translated into English from the original French 6th ed. In F. W. Truscott, & F. L. Emory. New York: Dover Publications.

  • Melamed, Y. (2013). Spinoza’s metaphysics and thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mermin, D. (2015). Why QBism is not the Copenhagen interpretation and what John Bell might have thought of it (preprint). arXiv:1409.2454

  • Nimmrichter, S., & Hornberger, K. (2013). Macroscopicity of mechanical quantum superposition states. Physical Review Letters, 110, 160403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Omnès, R. (1994). Interpretation of quantum mechanics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piron, C. (1983). Le realisme en physique quantique: une approche selon Aristote. In The concept of physical reality. Proceedings of a conference organized by the Interdisciplinary Research Group, University of Athens.

  • Rédei, M. (2012). Some historical and philosophical aspects of quantum probability theory and its interpretation. In D. Dieks, et al. (Eds.), Probabilities, laws, and structures (pp. 497–506). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, S., Barrett, J., Kent, A., & Wallace, D. (Eds.). (2012). Many worlds? Everett, quantum theory, & reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1935). The present situation in quantum mechanics. Naturwiss, 23, 807–812. Translated to English In J. A. Wheeler, W. H. Zurek (Eds.) Quantum Theory and Measurement, 1983, Princeton University Press, Princeton.

  • Sudbery, T. (2016). Time, chance and quantum theroy. In D. Aerts, C. de Ronde, H. Freytes, & R. Giuntini (Eds.), Probing the meaning and structure of quantum mechanics: Superpositions, semantics, dynamics and identity (pp. 324–339). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Verelst, K., & Coecke, B. (1999). Early Greek thought and perspectives for the interpretation of quantum mechanics: Preliminaries to an ontological approach. In D. Aerts (Ed.), The Blue Book of Einstein meets Magritte (pp. 163–196). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2007). Quantum probability from subjective likelihood: Improving on Deutsch’s proof of the probability rule. Studies in the history and philosophy of modern physics, 38, 311–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2012). The emergent multiverse: Quantum theory according to the everett interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A., & Zurek, W. H. (Eds.). (1983). Theory and measurement. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank two anonymous reviewers for their careful reading of my manuscript and their many insightful comments and suggestions. This work was partially supported by the following grants: FWO project G.0405.08 and FWO-research community W0.030.06. CONICET RES. 4541-12 and the Project PIO-CONICET-UNAJ (15520150100008CO) “Quantum Superpositions in Quantum Information Processing”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian de Ronde.

Additional information

Fellow Researcher of the Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas and Adjoint Professor of the National University Arturo Jaurteche, Buenos Aires, Argentina.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

de Ronde, C. Quantum Superpositions and the Representation of Physical Reality Beyond Measurement Outcomes and Mathematical Structures. Found Sci 23, 621–648 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-017-9541-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-017-9541-z

Keywords

Navigation