Skip to main content

Carnap’s Machist “Phase”

  • Chapter
Ernst Mach’s Vienna 1895–1930

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 218))

  • 276 Accesses

Abstract

Rudolf Carnap was born in 1891 in Ronsdorf near Barmen in Northwest Germany. He was the 14th and last child of Johann Sebulon Carnap (1826–1898). The father was a self-made man in the weaving business who became wealthy late in life, which after the death of his first two wives allowed him to marry (1887) into a well-educated familyl which included a prominent educator and archaeologist.2 After his death, Anna née Dörpfeld, his third wife, a poet, teacher, and writer, tutored young Rudolf for three years. In Gymnasium his favorite subjects seem to have been Latin and mathematics.3 He studied at the universities of Jena and Freiburg from 1910 to 1914.4 He remembered that Bruno Bauch at Jena had taught him Kant’s philosophy and Hermann Nohl had discussed Hegel’s views, but it was Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) who impresed him most.5 He told Carnap about a new kind of formal logic which “could serve for the construction of the whole of mathematics”. 6

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Baldwin, J.M. (ed.) Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology. Vol. II. New York: Macmillan. 1925.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Blackmore, John. Ernst Mach. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Blackmore, John. Ludwig Boltzmann - His Later Life and Philosophy 1900–1906. two volumes. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Blackmore, John. (ed.) “Ludwig Boltzmann - Troubled Genius as Philosopher”. Synthese,119 numbers 1 and 2, pp. 1–232.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Boltzmann, Ludwig. Theoretical Physics and Philosophical Problems. edited by B. McGuinness. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1974.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. Burtt, Edwin Arthur. “The Subjectivity of Secondary qualities”. in The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Science.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Garden City: Doubleday, 1954. (earlier editions in 1924, 1930, and 1952) Carnap, Rudolf. “Der Raum. Ein Beitrag zur Wissenschaftslehre”. Kant-Studien–Erganzungshefte #56,1921. (Jena doctoral dissertation, 1920. 87 pages.)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Carnap, Rudolf. “Drei Dimensionalität des Raumes und Kausalität: Eine Untersuchung über den logischen Zusammenhang zweier Fiktionen”. Annalen der Philosophie und philosophischen Kritik (Leipzig). 4 (1924) Heft 3, pp. 105–130.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Carnap, Rudolf. Der Logische Aufbau der Welt. Berlin: Schlachtensee, 1928. 2nd edition, Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Carnap, Rudolf. Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1956 (1947).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Carnap, Rudolf. “Carnap’s Intellectual Autobiography” in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp. La Salle: Open Court, 1991 (1963), p. 3–84.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Carnap, Rudolf. “The Development of my Thinking”. in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by P.A. Schilpp. La Salle: Open Court, 1991, pp. 3–39.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Carnap, Rudolf. The Logical Structure iof the World and Pseudo Problems in Philosophy. translated by Rolf A. George. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1969. (original German edition, 1928 )

    Google Scholar 

  14. Dingier, Hugo. Die Grundgedanken der Modischen Philosophie. Leipzig: 1924.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Frank, Philipp. “Das Kausalgesetz und Erfahrung”. Annalen der Naturphilosophie. volume 6, 1907.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Frank, Philipp. Das Kausalgesetz und seine Grenzen. Wien: Julius Springer Verlag, 1932.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ganot, Adolphe. Cours de physique purement expérimentale. Paris: 1859.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Göbel, Klaus. “Die Wuppertaler Familie Carnap”. Romerike Berge. Zeitschrift für Heimatpflege, 20 (1970–71) 9–14.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Göbel, Klaus. “Johann Sebulon Carnap 1826–1898”. Romerike Berge. Zeitschrift für Heimatpflege, 21 (1971) 112–121.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Hahn, Hans. “Superfluous Entities or Occam’s Razor (1930)”. in Hans Hahn - Empiricism, Logic, and Mathematics. edited by Brian McGuinness. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Hamilton, Sir William. Lectures on Metaphysics and Logic. edited by H.L. Mansel and John Veitch. volume I, Edinburgh and Boston: 1859.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  22. Lovejoy, Arthur. The Revolt Against Dualism. New Brunswick and London: Transaction Publishers, 19%. (Ist edition 1930. Second Edition 1960 )

    Google Scholar 

  23. Mach, Ernst. Popular Scientific Lectures. La Salle: Open Court, 1943 (1895).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Mach, Ernst. Analysis of Sensations. New York: Dover, 1959 (1st Genpan edition, 1886 ).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Mason, James F. A History of the Sciences. New York: Collier, 1975. (9 printings from 1962 to 1975 )

    Google Scholar 

  26. Poincaré, I-Ienri. Science and Method. New York: Dover, 1958 (1905). 1st French edition, 1903.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Reese. W.L. Dictionary of Philosophy and Religion. New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1980. Rungaldier, Edmund. Carnaps Early Conventionalism. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Sepp, I fans Reiner. Edmund Husserl und die phänomenologische Bewegung. FreiburgiMünchen: Verlag Karl Alber, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Vaihinger, I Ians. Die Philosophic des Als Ob. Berlin: 1911. (8th edition, 1922 )

    Google Scholar 

  30. Volpi. Franco and Julian Nida-Rtimelin (eds.). Lexikon der Philosophischen Werke. Stuttgart: Alfred Kroner, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Wolters, Gereon. “Früher Konventionalismus. Der Carnap-Dingler Briefwechsel”. in Peter Janich (ed.) Methodische Philosophie. Beiträge zum Begründungsproblem der Exakten Wissenschaften in Auseinandersetzung mit Hugo Digler. Mannheim: 1984, pp. 60–76.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Wood, Ledger. “Dualistic or Representative Realism”. in A History of Philosophical Systems. edited by V. Perm. New York: The Philosophical Library, 1950, pp. 525–527.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See Klaus Göbel, “Die Wuppertaler Familie Carnap”, Romerike Berge. Zeitschrift Für Heimatpflege,20 (1970–71) 9–14. See also “Johann Sebulon Carnap 1826–1898, Ibid. 21 (1971) 112–121.

    Google Scholar 

  34. The educator was Friedrich Wilhelm Dörpfeld (1824–1893) whose complete works were published in 1913, and the prominent archaeologist who discovered much about Ancient Greece, particularly Athens, was Wilhelm Dörpfeld (1853–1940).

    Google Scholar 

  35. Rudolf Carnap, “Carnap’s Intellectual Autobiography” in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap,edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, Open Court: La Salle, 1991 (1963), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., pp. 3–7.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., pp. 4–6 and 11–13.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid., p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  39. See 19th century physics textbooks starting with Adolphe Ganot, Cours de physique purement expérimentale, ’a l’usage des personnes étrangères aux connaisances mathématiques… [published by the author himself], Paris, 1859. Ganot’s physics textbooks were translated into the languages of many countries including England, Australia, The Netherlands, The United States, India, Japan, and Russia and seem to have been the most popular and widely used introductory textbooks in physics until the end of the century and in some coutries well beyond.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ernst Mach, Popular Scientific Lectures,Open Court: La Salle, 1943 (1895), pp. 241–242.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Carnap 1991, op. cit., p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Carnap 1956, op. cit., p. 43

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ludwig Boltzmann, Theoretical Physics and Philosophical Problems, edited by B. McGuinness, Reidel: Dordrecht, 1974, p. 275.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  44. Like many mathematicians and physicists, Carnap seems to have rejected the notion of efficient causes as powers or forces. This is understandable given the imprecise number of variables as relevant causal factors which has to be taken into account in order to set up constant or necessary relations between them, but given the indispensable role of efficient causes in non-idealized science and in practical life, such an attitude seems to be very short-sighted. It is too informative a notion to ignore or treat as “unscientific”.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Epistemological phenomenalism is the position that we can only know sensations. Ontological phenomenalism is the view that only sensations are real. Mach supported both positions. See his book Analysis of Sensations,Dover: New York, 1959, p. 12. But on page 363 in the same book Mach also accepts the reality of relations, a concession which Carnap as we shall see will eagerly accept and develop further.

    Google Scholar 

  46. For a discussion of “economy of thought” see J. Blackmore, Ernst Mach,University of California Press: Berkeley, 1972, pp. 169–174.

    Google Scholar 

  47. The allegation was that phenomenalism was neutral between realism and idealism, but epistemologically, phenomenalism has been considered part of idealism ever since Bishop Berkeley identified the physical world with sensations which he called “ideas”.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Rudolf Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, Weltkreis: Berlin-Schlachtensee, 1928.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Rudolf Carnap, Der Raum. Ein Beitrag zur Wissenschaftslehre. Inaugural Dissertation zur Erlangung der Doktorwürde… Universität Jena, 1921. 87 pages. [This work was published the following year in Kant-Studien as Ergänzungshefte # 56.]

    Google Scholar 

  50. Rudolf Carnap, “Drei Dimensionalität des Raumes und Kausalittät: Eine Untersuchung über den logischen Zusamenhang zweier Fiktionen” in Annalen der Philosophie und philosophischen Kritik (Leipzig), 4 (1924) Heft 3, pp. [105]-130.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Edmund Runggaldier, Carnap’s Early Conventionalism - An Inquiry into the Historical Background of the Vienna Circle, Rodopi: Amsterdam, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Ibid., p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ibid. p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid. p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Hans Reiner Sepp Edmund Husserl und die phänomenologische BewegungVerlag Karl Alber: Freiburg/München, 1988, p. 425.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Hugo Dingier, Die Grundgedanken der Machschen Philosophie, Leipzig, 1924. See also Gereon Wolters, “Früher Konventionalismus. Der Carnap-Dingler Briefwechsel”, in Peter Janich (ed.), Methodische Philosophie. Beiträge zum Begründungsproblem der exakten Wissenschaften in Auseinandersetzung mit Hugo Dingier, Mannheim, 1984, pp. 60–76.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Rudolf Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt (1928), 2nd edition, Felix Meiner Verlag: Hamburg, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Kantstudien,28 (1923) 90–107.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Runggaldier 1984, op. cit., p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Henri Poincaré, Science and Method,New York, 1958, pp. 15–24.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Philipp Frank, “Das Kausalgesetz und Erfahrung”, Annalen der Naturphilosophie, Volume 6, 1907. See also his book: Das Kausalgesetz und seine Grenzen, Julius Springer Verlag, Wien, 1932. Many years ago, Gerald Holton once mentioned to this author that Philipp Frank’s Nachlass was located in a Boston bank, but neither this author nor anyone elese has apparently seen fit to follow up this lead.

    Google Scholar 

  62. See Hans Hahn, “Superfluous Entities or Occam’s Razor [1930]”, in Hans Hahn - Empiricism, Logic, and Mathematics, edited by Brian McGuinness, Kluwer: Dordrecht, 1980. While Hahn who died in 1934 seems at least from his blunt philosophical writings to have been severe and humorless in his personality, his wife Lili (or Lily), who was still alive in 1968 when interviewed by this writer, had also studied mathematics and subsequently would become well-known in Vienna for her humor and ability to remember anecdotes about Viennese celebrities, especially her professor in physics, Ludwig Boltzmann. Several of her stories can be found in Blackmore’s 1.995 books on Boltzmann. For more recent material by and about Boltzmann see: John Blackmore (ed.) “Ludwig Boltzmann - Troubled Genius as Philosopher ”, Synthese, 119 (1999) nos. 1–2, pp. 1–232.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Runggalder 1984, op. cit., p. 38. By “causality” (“Kausalität”) Carnap and Ruggaldier mean “law-determined regularity” not cause and effect activity as in normal English. The usual word for “cause” in German is “Ursache”.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Hans Vaihinger, Die Philosophie des Als Ob, Berlin, 1911. (The first two parts of the book were apparently written from 1876 to 1878. Vaihinger alleges that illness made it difficult to finish the book earlier. Mach corresponded with Vaihinger. Iie also seems to have given quite diverse opinions about “As If philosophy”. )

    Google Scholar 

  65. Franco Volpi and Julian Nida-Rümelin (eds.), Lexikon der Philosophischen Werke, Alfred Kröner Verlag: Stuttgart, 1988, pp. 549–550. (Carnap lists Vaihinger’s book [8th edition, 1922] in his bibliography to Der logische Aufbau der Welt in 1928, but it is not clear if or how much he may have been influenced by it.)

    Google Scholar 

  66. W.L. Reese in Dictionary of Philosophy and Religion, Humanities Press: New Jersey, 1980, pp. 602–603 maintains that Vaihinger and Schmidt founded the journal Annalen der Philosophie in 1919 in order to help spread Vaihinger’s As If philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Edmund Runggaldier, “The Secondary World as Fiction, and the Failure of its reduction to the primary World”, Carnap’s Early Conventionalism, Rodopi: Amsterdam, 1984, pp. 38–43.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Rudolf Carnap, The Logical Structure of the World [1928] and Pseudo Problems in Philosophy [1928], translated by Rolf A. George, University of California Press: Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1969, p. vii.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Rudolf Carnap, “The Development of my Thinking”, in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, Open Court: La Salle, 1991, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Ibid., p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Ibid., p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Runggaldier 1984, op. cit., p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Ibid., p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Carnap 1969, op. cit., p. viii.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Rudolf Carnap, The Logical Structure of the World and Pseudoproblems in Philosophy,Translated by Rolf A. George, University of California Press: Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1969 (1967), pp. 281287.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Edwin Arthur Burtt, “The Subjectivity of Secondary Qualities”, in The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Science,A Doubleday Anchor Book: Garden City, 1954 (1924), pp. 83–90. This selection also includes a translation of Galileo’s own words from The Assayer (1624) as found in Opere IV,pp. 335–336.

    Google Scholar 

  77. The Metaphysics of Newton“, ibid., pp. 207–302.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Rudolf Carnap, The Logical Structure of the World…, University of California Press: Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1969, p. 281.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Arthur Lovejoy was perhaps the deepest American epistemologist. Unfortunately, his major work, The Rrevolt Against Dualism (1930), is not easy to read.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Like Rudolf Carnap, Burtt opposed representism, and also like Carnap he used the term “metaphysics” to describe it, but first, the English term was not as opprobrious as in German at that time, and second, having studied the history of science he was well aware that most of the main contributors to the Scientific Revolution were representists about the external physical world as were many or most later physicists, something which Rudolf Carnap seems not to have realized, or at least did not admit. A broad education is important for a philosopher and Carnap seems to have been lightly read in works outside of formal and systematic disciplines. His understanding of history of science seems to have been especially weak

    Google Scholar 

  81. Ernst Mach, The Science of Mechanics,Open Court, La Salle, 1960, pp. 151–190. Mach also seems to criticize Galileo for his interest in the atomic theory as if that were merely a relic of “ancient and mediaeval influences”. p. 187.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Carnap 1969, op. cit., p. 282.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Not to be confused with the mathematician of the same name and era. The philosopher Sir William Hamilton (1788–1856) distinguished between knowledge about what is presented and reasonable probability or belief about what is represented. Hamilton’s value here is evidence that even presentists are capable of employing reasonably inclusive and fair terminology and definitions. (James Ferrier is normally thought to have introduced the term “Epistemology” into English during the 1850’s and in time it replaced Hamilton’s earlier expression “gnosiology”.)

    Google Scholar 

  84. The term was apparently introduced by Hamilton in 1836–37 in a lecture which was later published in Lectures on Metaphysics and Logic edited by H.L. Mansel and John Veitch, volume I, Edinburgh and Boston, 1859, pp. vii and 122.

    Google Scholar 

  85. The word “presentative” has a long history but seems to have first made its debut as a philosophical term in 1842 with the sense of immediate or intuitive and was included in The Works of Thomas Reid,two volumes, which I-Iamilton edited, and which first came out in Edinburgh in 1846, p. 804. It was used later by Herbert Spencer.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Carnap 1969, op. cit., pp. 284–285.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Ibid., p. 282–284.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Ledger Wood, “Dualistic or Representative Realism” in A History of Philosophical Systems, edited by V. Ferm, The Philosophical Library, New York, 1950, pp. 525–527.

    Google Scholar 

  89. bid. See also J.M. Baldwin (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology,Volume II, Mac- millan: New York, 1925, p. 464: “Hamilton (Lectures on Metaphysics) classifies theories of knowledge as immediate and representative.”

    Google Scholar 

  90. Ibid (Wood).

    Google Scholar 

  91. Carnap 1969, op. cit., p. 282.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Ibid., p. 286.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Ibid., pp. 282–284.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Ibid., p. 281.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Ibid., p. 288.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Ibid., pp. 282–284.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Ibid., pp. 284–287.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Perhaps the most widely read book on history of science during the last half of the 20th century has been James F. Mason’s work A History of the Sciences,Collier Books: New York. (The editor’s copy went through nine printings between 1962 and 1975 alone.) See pp. 500–502. There have also been many translations into other languages.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Ibid. This is certainly Mason’s opinion.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, Open Court, La Salle, 1991, pp. 1018–1056.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Blackmore, J., Itagaki, R., Tanaka, S. (2001). Carnap’s Machist “Phase”. In: Blackmore, J., Itagaki, R., Tanaka, S. (eds) Ernst Mach’s Vienna 1895–1930. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 218. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9690-9_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9690-9_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5752-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9690-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics