Skip to main content

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Economics ((BRIEFSECONOMICS))

  • 362 Accesses

Abstract

We discuss the findings of the preceding chapters aiming at an overall judgement of the relative merits of the 18 procedures in the light of their (in)vulnerability to various voting paradoxes. No procedure is invulnerable to all the analyzed voting paradoxes, but there are differences in the variety of paradoxes that various procedures are vulnerable to. It turns out that for those emphasizing that a Condorcet Winner ought to be elected when s/he exists, the most plausible voting procedures are associated with the names of Copeland and Kemeny, while for those stressing the need to preserve the basic rationale of voting, viz., the participation condition, the most appealing system is the Borda count.

This chapter is partly based on Felsenthal (2012) and partly on Nurmi (2012).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Campbell and Kelly (2002) devised a non–monotonic voting rule that does not exhibit the No–Show Paradox. However, as this method violates the anonymity and neutrality conditions and hence has not been considered seriously for actual use, we ignore it. The suggested method is bizarre in other respects as well, e.g. if all voters rank x last, it will be elected.

  2. 2.

    Although all Condorcet–consistent procedures are also susceptible to the Reinforcement Paradox, there is no logical connection between this Paradox and the No–Show Paradox. As mentioned by Moulin (1988, pp. 54–55), when there are no more than three candidates there exist Condorcet–consistent procedures which are immune to both the No–Show and Twin Paradoxes, e.g., the Minimax procedure which elects the candidate to whom the smallest majority objects.

  3. 3.

    However, in order to be able to state conclusively which of several voting procedures that are susceptible to the same paradox is more likely to display this paradox, one must know what are the necessary and/or sufficient conditions for this paradox to occur under the various compared procedures. Such knowledge is still lacking with respect to most voting procedures and paradoxes.

  4. 4.

    When there are n candidates each of whom can be ranked by each of the v voters as either 1, 2, …, n, then the maximal average rank a candidate can obtain under Borda’s procedure is 1 (if all voters rank the same candidate at the top of their preference ordering) and the lowest average rank a candidate can obtain is n (if all voters rank the same candidate at the bottom of their preference ordering). It is of course possible that the Condorcet Winner and the Borda winner will have the same average rank.

References

  • Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams, S. J., & Fishburn, P. C. (1991). Alternative voting systems. In L. Sandy Maisel (Ed.), Political parties and elections in the United States: An encyclopedia, vol. 1. New York: Garland, pp. 23–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, F., Conitzer, V., Endriss, U., Lang, J., & Procaccia, A. D. (Eds.). (2016). Handbook of computational social choice. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. E., & Kelly, J. S. (2002). Non–monotonicity does not imply the No–Show paradox. Social Choice and Welfare, 19, 513–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, A. H. (1951). A ‘reasonable’ social welfare function, mimeographed. University of Michigan, Department of Mathematics, Seminar on Applications of Mathematics to the Social Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenthal, D. S. (2012). Review of paradoxes afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate. In D. S. Felsenthal & M. Machover (Eds.), Electoral systems: Paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Berlin Heidelberg: Springer, Ch. 3, pp. 19–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenthal, D. S., & Nurmi, H. (2017). Monotonicity failures afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1973). The theory of social choice. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1974). Paradoxes of voting. American Political Science Review, 68, 537–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemeny, J. G. (1959). Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus, 88, 577–591.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagerspetz, E. (2004). Evaluating voting systems. In M. Wiberg (Ed.), Reasoned choices (pp. 201–222). Helsinki: The Finnish Political Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwin, W. G. (1978). Strategic voting and the Borda method. Public Choice, 33, 85–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H. (1988). Condorcet’s principle implies the No–Show paradox. Journal of Economic Theory, 45, 53–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (1983). Voting procedures: A summary analysis. British Journal of Political Science, 13(2), 181–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (1999). Voting paradoxes and how to deal with them. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (2012). On the relevance of theoretical results to voting system choice. In D. S. Felsenthal & M. Machover (Eds.), Electoral systems: Paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Berlin Heidelberg: Springer, Ch. 10, pp. 255–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pérez, J. (2001). The strong no show paradoxes are common flaw in Condorcet voting correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 18, 601–616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (1995). Basic Geometry of Voting. New York: Springer Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (2008). Disposing dictators, demystifying voting paradoxes: Social choice analysis. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. H. (1973). Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica, 41, 1027–1041.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, H. P. (1995). Optimal voting rules. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9(1), 51–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dan S. Felsenthal .

Appendices

Exercises

Problem 7.1

Are trivial or dictatorial voting procedures manipulable?

Problem 7.2

Show that the Plurality with Runoff procedure is manipulable.

Problem 7.3

Show that there are profiles where the agenda–controller can bring about any outcome when the Successive Elimination procedure is used under the assumption that the voters are sincere.

Answers to Exercises

Problem 7.1

Trivial procedures result in a fixed outcome regardless of preferences. Misrepresenting one’s preference cannot, therefore, improve the outcome. Dictatorial procedures always result in the outcome most preferred by the dictator. Hence, no non–dictatorial voter can improve upon the outcome that the dictator determines. The dictator, on the other hand, has no incentive to misrepresent his/her preference.

Problem 7.2

Consider the following profile:

No. of voters

Preference orderings

2

a ≻ b ≻ c

1

b ≻ a ≻ c

2

c ≻ b ≻ a

With sincere voting a wins. With one voter of the last group voting as if his/her preference is b ≻ a ≻ c, ceteris paribus, the outcome is b, i.e. better than a for this voter.

Problem 7.3

The Condorcet Paradox profile is perhaps the simplest example:

No. of voters

Preference ordering

1

a ≻ b ≻ c

1

b ≻ c ≻ a

1

c ≻ a ≻ b

If the agenda–controller wants a to win, he/she sets the agenda: (i) b versus c, (ii) the winner of (i) versus a. If he/she wants b to win, he/she sets the agenda: (i) a versus c, (ii) the winner of (i) versus b. If he/she wants c to win, his/her agenda is: (i) a versus b, (ii) the winner of (i) versus c.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Felsenthal, D.S., Nurmi, H. (2018). Summary. In: Voting Procedures for Electing a Single Candidate. SpringerBriefs in Economics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-74033-1_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics