1 Introduction

A minimum wage is used in many countries as a redistributive tool for the benefit of unskilled workers.Footnote 1 However, its normative justification is highly controversial due to its adverse effect on employment and the possibility of redistribution through the tax-and-transfer system.

Beginning with the seminal contribution of Mirrlees (1971), the major concern of the optimal income-tax literature has been with the government’s role in pursuing distributional goals in the presence of asymmetric information about workers’ characteristics. The canonical framework stipulates a competitive labor-market setting, which would lead to a Pareto-efficient allocation in the absence of government intervention. However, due to redistributive concerns and informational constraints, the government faces a non-trivial tradeoff between equity and efficiency. Hence, the government will generally choose an allocation that is not Pareto optimal, and the optimal income-tax literature primarily focuses on how expanding the set of policy tools available to the government beyond the tax-and-transfer system may improve this tradeoff.

One strand of this literature investigates whether a minimum wage could be such additional policy tool in a competitive labor-market environment. The focus is mainly on the intensive-margin setting where the choice is confined to working hours, and the key insight is that a minimum wage is in general not a desirable supplement to the tax-and-transfer system (Allen 1987; Guesnerie and Roberts 1987). A notable exception is Boadway and Cuff (2001) who demonstrate that if unemployment benefits are denied from workers who turn down wage offers exceeding the minimum wage, then a minimum wage can serve as a warranted supplement to an optimal tax-and-transfer system. The reason is that a minimum wage can then serve to distinguish between voluntarily (skilled) and involuntarily (unskilled) unemployed workers and thereby effectively target unemployment benefits to the latter. More recently, Danziger and Danziger (2015, 2018) show that a graduated (rather than a constant) minimum wage combined with an optimal tax-and-transfer system can be instrumental in achieving a Pareto improvement and study its welfare properties.Footnote 2

Lee and Saez (2012) instead focus on the extensive margin and examine the desirability of a minimum wage in an occupational-choice model with fixed working hours. They show that if rationing is efficient, namely, the involuntary unemployment triggered by a minimum wage will primarily hit the workers with the highest disutility of work, a minimum wage can be desirable.

The normative justification for a minimum wage in the occupational-choice extensive-margin model of Lee and Saez (2012) hinges on a restrictive assumption about the tax system. In particular, Lee and Saez consider an occupation tax which imposes a fixed levy on each occupation (high-skilled and low-skilled) independently of the earned income. If the production function exhibits perfect substitutability between skilled and unskilled labor inputs (i.e., a linear production function as in Saez 2002), this assumption would not be restrictive as the income level in each occupation would be given exogenously. An occupation tax would then be equivalent to an income tax. However, with complementarity between the various skill inputs, this assumption becomes restrictive as it rules out the tax being conditional on the endogenously determined income earned in each occupation. In particular, a more general income tax would allow, for each occupation, to set the tax liability for any income other than that realized in equilibrium. With an extensive-margin adjustment of labor, if the tax could be conditioned on income, a minimum wage could be fully replicated by a confiscatory 100% income tax on any income level below a minimal threshold coinciding with the realized income level in the low-skill sector in equilibrium. A minimum wage would then be redundant, as the allocation attained under the augmented income tax system would be equivalent to the one attained under the restrictive income tax system supplemented by a minimum wage.

The above literature assumes that the skill distribution is given. However, the tax-and-transfer system and the minimum wage may of course affect the human-capital formation and thereby the skill distribution. In a recent paper, Gerritsen and Jacobs (2016) consider an occupational choice model with competitive labor markets and endogenous human capital formation and address the question of whether income redistribution is more efficiently achieved through an increase in the minimum wage or through changes in the income tax. The threat of involuntary unemployment associated with an increase in the minimum wage may induce some low-skilled individuals to upgrade their skills to avoid unemployment. Provided that taxes rise with income, this results in revenue gains from increased high-skill employment offsetting the revenue losses from increased low-skill unemployment. Gerritsen and Jacobs show that for a minimum wage increase to dominate a distributional-equivalent tax change, revenue gains from higher skill formation should outweigh revenue losses from inefficient low-skilled labor rationing.Footnote 3

In this paper, we offer an alternative normative justification for the use of a minimum wage to supplement an optimal tax-and-transfer system. We consider the intensive-margin setting that captures the difference between wage and income and therefore provides a natural framework for examining the social desirability of a minimum wage as a supplement to the tax-and-transfer system.Footnote 4 Central to our argument is the distinction between the deserving and the undeserving poor, where deservedness refers to the society’s willingness to provide public support as reflected in the relative weights in the social welfare function. We capture this distinction by assuming that unskilled workers differ in their disutility from work, where those incurring a low disutility from work are referred to as deserving, while those incurring a high disutility from work are referred to as undeserving.

The association between incurring a high disutility from work and being perceived as undeserving can be interpreted in several manners. A high disutility from work may reflect laziness, so that society has some bias in favor of the poor workers who are more willing to work hard (long hours) relative to those poor workers who are less willing to do so. Incurring a high disutility from work may alternatively reflect family circumstances, such as being a teenager or a secondary earner of a household. In both cases, the worker is likely to have a higher reservation wage and typically opts for a part-time job. For instance, teenage workers are less constrained by long-term financial obligations (e.g., mortgages), have more attractive outside opportunities (e.g., schooling), and may receive their parents’ support; likewise, secondary earners may rely on their spouses’ income and therefore already enjoy a high level of consumption.

Of course, incurring a high disutility from work could well be associated with social circumstances such as disability and single parenthood that warrant public support. Individuals in these categories may to some extent be identified and targeted by specialized welfare programs that address their particular needs (e.g., Temporary Assistance to Needy Families and Social Security Disability Insurance). However, in many cases, distinguishing between more and less deserving within the pool of low-skilled workers exhibiting a high disutility from work may be a daunting challenge for the government. For instance, according to the US Census Bureau Data (see Weisbach 2009 and the references therein), among the top ten disabilities, back/spinal problems (excluding spinal cord injuries and paralysis) are by far the most prevalent. Another common source of claimed disability is mental problems (excluding retardation). However, both back pains and mental problems are difficult to verify compared with disabilities such as blindness, heart/artery problems, and diabetes which are readily verifiable.

Due to the problem of verification faced by the government, incurring a high-disutility from work is imperfectly correlated with welfare deservedness. That being said, our model assumes that the correlation is sufficiently large to warrant assigning a lower welfare weight to low-skilled workers with a high disutility from work.

In our model, the government maximizes a social welfare function that favors the deserving poor. However, as the disutility from work is unobservable, the government cannot directly identify the deserving poor and is faced with a screening problem. We demonstrate that a minimum wage can help the government overcome this challenge.

When working hours are rationed in a manner which is sufficiently close to being constrained efficient (precisely defined below in the formal model) in the sense that most of the involuntary underemployment triggered by the imposition of a minimum wage falls on the undeserving poor, extra transfers offered by the government to unskilled workers can be targeted toward the deserving poor rather than being accorded to all poor across the board.Footnote 5 We demonstrate that by relying on the screening of workers through the rationing of working hours, the government may overcome its inability to identify the deserving poor directly. Consequently, a minimum wage may become a desirable supplement to an optimal tax-and-transfer system.Footnote 6

The notion of welfare deservedness has attracted much attention in recent years and has become a key issue in the public discourse about the role of the welfare system. Abundant evidence shows that society is generally sympathetic toward supporting the poor but that generosity is often conditioned on the recipients either working hard or being disabled. For instance, Gilens (1999) reports that people are more concerned about the conditions determining which recipients should benefit from social security programs than about the cost of the programs, the main question for taxpayers being not so much “who gets what?” but rather “who deserves what?”. In other words, it is not the government support for the truly needy that sparks considerable public resentment, but rather the perception that many individuals receiving welfare are undeserving.Footnote 7 These trends are reflected in the 1996 welfare reform in the USA and the shift from the Aid to Families with Dependent Children program to the Temporary Assistance for Needy Families program with its emphasis on the work requirement, as well as the significant expansion in recent years of the Earned Income Tax Credit program that conditions welfare on labor market participation.

Several previous studies have distinguished between the deserving and undeserving poor in order to provide a normative foundation for commonly used policy tools such as the Earned Income Tax Credit program and Workfare to target benefits to the deserving poor. For instance, Besley and Coate (1992, 1995) assume that the government objective is to alleviate poverty rather than to maximize social welfare. Effectively, this eliminates disutility from work from the government objective and may be interpreted to reflect the view that high disutility from work indicates a socially unacceptable trait. They show that workfare can then be an effective screening tool that supplements means testing. Relatedly, Kanbur et al. (1994) establish the case for levying a negative marginal tax rate on the working poor when the government aims to minimize an income-based poverty index. Cuff (2000) employs a framework where individuals differ along the skill dimension and in their disutility from work. She demonstrates that work requirements can be desirable if the government objective is to maximize the well-being of the unskilled workers incurring a low disutility from work (the deserving poor). Saez (2002) discusses the possibility of assigning a relatively low marginal social weight to unemployed unskilled workers and shows that this would reinforce the case for an Earned Income Tax Credit. Finally, Blumkin et al. (2015) demonstrate that statistical stigma can be an effective welfare ordeal mechanism to sort out those claimants considered undeserving.

2 The model

We consider a simple setup with just the key ingredients necessary to demonstrate our point. The economy is comprised of skilled and unskilled workers that produce a single consumption good the price of which is unity. The mass of each skill group is unity. The output X is given by

$$ X=F\left({N}^u,{N}^s\right), $$
(1)

where Nu and Ns denote the total working hours of the unskilled and skilled workers, respectively. The function F is increasing has constant returns to scale, and exhibits diminishing marginal productivity in the input of each skill level.Footnote 8

Let c denote consumption, n working hours, and g(n) the disutility of work, where g(0) = 0,  g > 0, g′′ > 0 and \( \underset{n\to 0}{\lim }{g}^{\prime }(n)=0 \). The utility of the skilled workers (indexed by superscript s) is given by us ≡ cs − g(ns). Unskilled workers differ in their disutility from work. For a fraction α ∈ (0, 1) of the unskilled workers (indexed by superscript d) the utility is given by ud ≡ cd − g(nd). For the remaining fraction 1 − α of the unskilled workers (indexed by superscript l), the utility is given by ul ≡ cl − kg(nl), where k > 1. That is, type-l unskilled workers incur a higher disutility (both total and marginal) from work relative to their type-d unskilled counterparts for the same working hours supplied. We will henceforth refer to type-d workers as deserving poor and to type-l workers as undeserving poor. That is, we interpret the choice to work fewer hours in the labor market (stemming from the higher disutility from work) as reflecting a socially undesirable trait.

The total labor supply of the skilled workers is given by Ns = ns, and the total labor supply of the unskilled workers by Nu = αnd + (1 − α)nl. Assuming a competitive labor market, each worker is paid the value of his marginal product. Therefore, ws ≡ ∂F(Nu, Ns)/∂Ns is the wage of skilled workers and wu ≡ ∂F(Nu, Ns)/∂Nu is the wage of unskilled workers. We assume that ws > wu.

The government’s social welfare is given by a weighted average of the utilities,

$$ W\equiv {\sum}_i{\beta}^i{u}^i, $$
(2)

where ∑iβi = 1 and i = s, d, l. We assume that the social welfare weight assigned to type-s workers is less than their fraction in the population, i.e., 0 ≤ βs < 1/2. This represents society’s egalitarian preferences and is fairly standard.Footnote 9 We also assume that the social welfare weight assigned to type-l workers is lower than their fraction in the population, i.e., 0 ≤ βl < (1 − α)/2. This reflects the public’s perception that individuals whose preferences induce them to work relatively fewer hours are less deserving of government support (see our elaborate discussion in the introduction).Footnote 10

3 The benchmark regime: no minimum wage

We start by analyzing the benchmark case with no minimum wage so that a non-linear tax-and-transfer system is the only available redistributive policy tool. The government maximizes the social welfare given in (2) by choosing a triplet of consumption-work bundles (ci, ni),  i = s, d, l, satisfying the revenue constraint

$$ F\left({N}^u,{N}^s\right)\ge {c}^s+{\alpha c}^d+\left(1-\alpha \right){c}^l $$
(3)

and the six incentive-compatibility constraints denoted by ICiji, j = s, d, l where i ≠ j, which express that a worker of type i has no incentive to mimic a worker of type j, i.e., that

$$ {c}^i-{k}^ig\left({n}^i\right)\ge {c}^j-{k}^ig\left(\frac{n^j{w}^j}{w^i}\right), $$
(4)

where ks = kd = 1, kl = k and wd = wl = wu.

The following lemma summarizes important properties of the optimal solution.Footnote 11

Lemma: In a social welfare optimum without a minimum wage:

  1. (i)

    IC sd and IC ld are the only binding incentive-compatibility constraints;

  2. (ii)

    nd > nl.

Proof: See Appendix A.

Part (i) of the lemma states that the downward incentive-compatibility constraint ICsd is binding. This accords with the standard optimal-tax model where the direction of redistribution goes from the high to the low earners. The fact that the downward incentive-compatibility constraint ICsd binds implies that the skilled workers are indifferent between choosing their intended bundle and mimicking the deserving unskilled workers. Part (i) of the lemma also states that the upward incentive-compatibility constraint ICld is binding even though, as shown by part (ii) of the lemma, the undeserving poor work less and hence earn less than the deserving poor. This feature derives from the government’s lower valuation of the undeserving poor and implies that the latter are indifferent between choosing their intended bundle and working more in order to mimic their deserving counterparts.

Figure 1 illustrates the government optimal solution under the benchmark regime in the income-consumption space. The three upward-sloping curves, denoted by us, ud, and ul, represent the indifference curves associated with the skilled, deserving unskilled, and undeserving unskilled workers, respectively. Notice that the single-crossing property holds, namely, the indifference curve of the undeserving unskilled is steeper than that of the deserving unskilled, which in turn is steeper than that of the skilled. The equilibrium income-consumption bundles associated with the skilled, deserving unskilled, and undeserving unskilled workers are given by E, F, and G, correspondingly. As stated in part (i) of the lemma, the incentive-compatibility constraint ICsd, associated the skilled workers, and the incentive-compatibility constraint, ICld, associated with the undeserving unskilled workers, are binding. That is, the bundles E and F lie on the same indifference curve, us, associated with the skilled workers, whereas the bundles F and G lie on the same indifference curve, ul, associated with the undeserving unskilled workers. As both types of unskilled workers earn the same wage, the fact that the income level associated with bundle F exceeds that associated with bundle G indicates that the deserving unskilled workers work more hours than their undeserving counterparts, as stated in part (ii) of the lemma.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Benchmark equilibrium

4 The welfare-enhancing role of a minimum wage

A binding minimum wage sets a lower bound for the wage that can be paid to the unskilled workers and thus effectively determines a binding upper bound for their working hours. The ensuing excess supply of unskilled workers necessitates some form of rationing. Rationing rules may be characterized by the extent to which they are efficient. Rationing is defined as efficient when the total hours of work are shared in a manner that maximizes the aggregate surplus of the workers whose workload is being allocated (put differently, the allocation of a given number of working hours minimizes the total disutility of labor).

We focus on a rationing rule which is constrained efficient in the sense that the working hours of the unskilled labor are allocated so as to maximize the aggregate surplus of the unskilled workers given the tax-and-transfer system in place. In our context, as will be formally shown in Appendix B (Part I), constrained efficient rationing entails that the entire incidence of the involuntary underemployment falls on the undeserving poor (as they derive the least surplus from working).Footnote 12

With random rationing, all the unskilled workers would be equally likely to be employed less than they desire. Realistically, rationing would lie somewhere in between these two extremes and we will focus on the case where the rationing is sufficiently close to being constrained efficient, henceforth called nearly constrained efficient, in that a sufficiently large share of the incidence of involuntary underemployment falls on the undeserving poor.Footnote 13 As we will show, in such a case, supplementing an optimal tax-and-transfer system with a binding minimum wage can enhance welfare:

Proposition: If rationing of employment hours is nearly constrained efficient , supplementing an optimal tax-and-transfer system with a binding minimum wage enhances welfare.

Proof: See Appendix B.

5 Discussion

The rationale for the desirability of the minimum wage is as follows. Part (i) of the lemma shows that in the absence of a minimum wage, the incentive-compatibility constraint ICld associated with the undeserving poor would be binding. This limits the government’s redistributive capacity as increasing the transfer to the deserving poor would induce the undeserving poor to mimic their deserving counterparts, thereby violating ICld. However, with constrained efficient rationing (and the case of nearly constrained efficient rationing follows by continuity considerations) a minimum wage would block this undesirable supply-side response, causing the entire incidence of the induced involuntary underemployment to fall on the undeserving poor. Namely, the undeserving poor will be forced to work less than they would prefer given the tax-and-transfer schedule. With the mimicking possibilities of the undeserving poor being blocked, the government is able to offer more generous transfers to the deserving poor. Effectively, the minimum wage plays a screening role that ensures that the extra transfers are targeted to those deserving, rather than being accorded to all unskilled workers.

Figure 2 illustrates the proposition in the income-consumption space. The solid indifference curves represent the benchmark equilibrium in the absence of a minimum wage, as depicted in Fig. 1, whereas the dashed indifference curves represent the equilibrium in the presence of a minimum wage. The bundles E’, F’, and G’ reflect a revenue-neutral perturbation to the benchmark allocation given by the bundles E, F, and G. Under the perturbed regime, working hours and hence income levels remain unchanged. The consumption levels associated with the skilled and the deserving unskilled workers are increased in a manner that maintains the skilled workers’ incentive-compatibility constraint, ICsd, binding. Namely, the bundles E’ and F’ lie on the same dashed indifference curve associated with the skilled workers. The consumption level associated with the undeserving unskilled workers is decreased to maintain the government’s budget balanced. The latter violates the undeserving unskilled workers’ incentive-compatibility constraint, ICld. These now prefer to mimic their deserving unskilled counterparts. Namely, the bundle F’ lies above the dashed indifference curve going through the bundle G’. Mimicking, however, is rendered infeasible by the binding minimum wage due to the constrained efficient rationing that prevents the undeserving unskilled workers from working longer hours to replicate the deserving unskilled workers’ income.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Equilibrium with minimum wage

It is important to clarify the rationale underlying the difference between our finding that a minimum wage is desirable and the earlier negative result in Allen (1987) and Guesnerie and Roberts (1987) that a minimum wage cannot be a useful supplement to an optimal tax-and-transfer system. In these two studies, the government’s redistributive policy is constrained by the skilled workers’ binding downward incentive-compatibility constraint, which makes them indifferent between whether or not to mimic the unskilled workers. In such a case, imposing a minimum wage is useless since it does not make mimicking harder for the skilled workers. In contrast, in our setting, the government’s redistributive policy is constrained by the undeserving poor’s binding upward incentive-compatibility constraint, which makes them indifferent between whether or not to mimic the deserving poor. As the undeserving poor would have to increase their working hours in order to mimic the deserving poor, an effective upper bound on the undeserving poor’s working hours is desirable. This is achieved by the minimum wage, which sets an upper bound on the working hours of all unskilled workers. With constrained efficient rationing of employment hours, the latter is translated into an upper bound on only the working hours of the undeserving poor.Footnote 14

A minimum wage is clearly not the only policy tool that could serve to screen between the deserving and undeserving poor. Two notable policy tools that could serve the same purpose are wage subsidies (e.g., the Earned Income Tax Credit in the USA) and work/training requirements for welfare eligibility (Workfare). Both of these widely used policy tools would induce an increase in the labor supply of the deserving poor, rendering it less attractive for the undeserving poor to mimic their deserving counterparts, thereby enhancing the screening efficiency of the tax-and-transfer system. Indeed, in a working paper version (Blumkin and Danziger 2014), we have examined the desirability of levying a negative marginal tax rate on the deserving poor. We first show that in the absence of a minimum wage, a negative marginal tax rate may be optimal. We then demonstrate that by supplementing the tax-and-transfer system with a binding minimum wage, assuming that employment hours are efficiently rationed, the undeserving poor cannot mimic the deserving poor. This would, therefore, obviate the need to distort the labor supply of the deserving poor upward in order to mitigate the mimicking incentive of the undeserving poor. Thus, the minimum wage is more efficient than a negative marginal tax rate in targeting benefits to the deserving poor. While a formal analysis of workfare is beyond the scope of this paper, a minimum wage appears to have similar efficiency advantages over a workfare program, which entails labor supply distortions resembling those associated with a negative marginal tax rate.

6 Conclusion

In this paper, we offer a normative justification for the use of a minimum wage to promote redistributive goals in a competitive labor market. Motivated by the ample empirical evidence showing that the general public is reluctant to support those poor perceived to be undeserving, we assume that unskilled workers differ in their disutility of work and further postulate that the unskilled workers with high disutility from work are those considered to be less deserving of receiving government support. This is reflected in their relatively low weight in the social welfare function. We demonstrate that a minimum wage is a desirable supplement to an optimal tax-and-transfer system when the rationing of employment hours is nearly constrained efficient. The reason is that a minimum wage can be used as a screening device to distinguish between deserving and undeserving poor and thereby to enhance the government capacity to direct transfers toward those considered more deserving of support.