Skip to main content
Log in

Depersonalization Disorder, Affective Processing and Predictive Coding

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A flood of new multidisciplinary work on the causes of depersonalization disorder (DPD) provides a new way to think about the feeling that experiences “belong” to the self. In this paper I argue that this feeling, baptized “mineness”(Billon 2013, 2018a, b) or “subjective presence” (Seth, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 17(11): 565–573, 2013) emerges from a multilevel interaction between emotional, affective and cognitive processing. The “self” to which experience is attributed is a predictive model made by the mind to explain the modulation of affect as the organism progresses through the world. When the world no longer produces predicted affect the organism needs to explain this unpredicted absence of feeling. It is important to this account that cognition and perception are otherwise intact. Consequently the mind’s representation of the world and its emotionally salient properties are unchanged, leading the mind to predict a characteristic affective response. When that prediction is not fulfilled the organisms feels as if she is no longer present in experience. This is reported at the as feeling of depersonalization.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am distinguishing affective from emotional processing on the basis that affects are felt. Affective processes are involved in the generation of such feelings. Emotional processes coordinate the components of an emotional episode (including feelings) by representing the goal-relevance of information.

  2. This idea is inconsistent with some conceptual theses about the nature of pain (that it is a form of immediate unstructured self awareness) that suggest that it is impossible to have pain without motivation or ownership. But apparently simple experiences have complex internal structure that can decompose under the conditions characteristic of certain pathologies.

  3. Such disorders are characteristic of problems with appraisal

  4. See e.g. Craig’s (2009a) explanation of the role of AIC “it generates an image of ‘the material me’ (or the sentient self) at one moment in time”

  5. the quotation is from an interview, his written work is far more complicated and subtle on the question, so Metzinger* refers to his interview persona).

References

  • Adams, R.A., S. Shipp, and K.J. Friston. 2013. Predictions not commands: active inference in the motor system. Brain Structure and Function 218 (3): 611–643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. 2013. Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (DSM-5®). American Psychiatric Pub.

  • Baker, D., E. Hunter, E. Lawrence, N. Medford, M. Patel, C. Senior, M. Sierra, M.V. Lambert, M.L. Phillips, and A.S. David. 2003. Depersonalisation disorder: Clinical features of 204 cases. The British Journal of Psychiatry 182 (5): 428–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L.F., and W.K. Simmons. 2015. Interoceptive predictions in the brain. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 16 (7): 419–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, C.M., and A.A. Baird. 2009. The processing of internally-generated interoceptive sensation. Neuroimage 47 (1): S84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Billon, Alexandre. 2013. Does consciousness entail subjectivity? The puzzle of thought insertion. Philosophical Psychology 26 (2): 291–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Billon, A. (2018a). Making sense of the Cotard syndrome. Insights from the study of depersonalization. Mind and Language.

  • Billon, A. (2018b). "What is it like to lack "mineness". Depersonalisation as a probe for the scope, nature and role of mineness."

  • Brighetti, G., P. Bonifacci, et al. 2007. ‘Far from the heart far from the eye’: Evidence from the Capgras delusion. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry 12 (3): 189–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brosch, T., G. Pourtois, and D. Sander. 2010. The perception and categorisation of emotional stimuli: A review. Cognition and Emotion 24 (3): 377–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christodoulou, G.N. 1986. Role of depersonalization-derealization phenomena in the delusional misidentification syndromes. Bibliotheca Psychiatrica 164: 99–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2013. Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (03): 181–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A. 2009a. How do you feel—Now? The anterior insula and human awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 10 (1).

  • Craig, A.D. 2009b. Emotional moments across time: A possible neural basis for time perception in the anterior insula. Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences 364 (1525): 1933–1942.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A. 2010. The sentient self. Brain Structure and Function: 1–15.

  • Critchley, H.D. 2005. Neural mechanisms of autonomic, affective, and cognitive integration. Journal of Comparative Neurology 493 (1): 154–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R. (2006). Descartes' error. Random House.

  • Dugas, L. and F. Moutier (1911). La Dépersonnalisation, Félix Alcan.

  • Dunn, B.D., T. Dalgleish, and A.D. Lawrence. 2006. The somatic marker hypothesis: A critical evaluation. Neuroscience and Biobehavioural Reviews 30: 239–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, B.D., H.C. Galton, et al. 2010. Listening to your heart: How interoception shapes emotion experience and intuitive decision making. Psychological Science 21 (12): 1835–1844.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, H.D., and M.B. Lewis. 2001. Capgras delusion: A window on face recognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5 (4): 149–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinstein, J.S., D. Rudrauf, S.S. Khalsa, M.D. Cassell, J. Bruss, T.J. Grabowski, and D. Tranel. 2010. Bilateral limbic system destruction in man. Journal of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology 32 (1): 88–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinstein, J.S., S.S. Khalsa, T.V. Salomons, K.M. Prkachin, L.A. Frey-Law, J.E. Lee, et al. 2016. Preserved emotional awareness of pain in a patient with extensive bilateral damage to the insula, anterior cingulate, and amygdala. Brain Structure and Function 221 (3): 1499–1511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Füstös, J.R., K. Gramann, et al. 2013. On the embodiment of emotion regulation: Interoceptive awareness facilitates reappraisal. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 8 (8): 911–917.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, S.N., and H.D. Critchley. 2013. Interoception, emotion and brain: New insights link internal physiology to social behaviour. Commentary on “anterior insular cortex mediates bodily sensibility and social anxiety” by Terasawa et al. (2012). Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 8 (3): 231–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garland, E.L. 2012. Pain processing in the human nervous system: A selective review of nociceptive and biobehavioral pathways. Primary Care: Clinics in Office Practice 39 (3): 561–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerrans, P. 2014. The measure of madness: Philosophy, cognitive neuroscience, and delusional thought. Cambridge: Mass, MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., A. Roepstorff, and K. Friston. 2008. Predictive coding explains binocular rivalry: An epistemological review. Cognition 108 (3): 687–701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. 2012. Attention and conscious perception in the hypothesis testing brain. Frontiers in Psychology 3.

  • Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind, Oxford University Press.

  • Hohwy, J., and J. Michael. 2017. Why should any body have a self? In The Subject’s matter: Self-consciousness and the body, ed. F. Vignemont and A. Alsmith. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalisch, R. 2009. The functional neuroanatomy of reappraisal: Time matters. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews 33 (8): 1215–1226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kircher, T., and A. David, eds. 2003. The self in neuroscience and psychiatry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. 2015. What Pain Asymbolia Really Shows. Mind 124 (494): 493–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medford, N. 2012. Emotion and the unreal self: Depersonalization disorder and de-affectualization. Emotion Review 4 (2): 139–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2004). Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. MIT Press.

  • Metzinger, T. 2011. The no-self alternative. In The Oxford handbook of the self, ed. S. Gallagher, 279–296. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T. 2016. All about the ego tunnel. Interview 3ammagazine. http://www.3ammagazine.com/3am/all-about-the-ego-tunnel/

  • Michal, M., A. Koechel, et al. 2013. Depersonalization disorder: Disconnection of cognitive evaluation from autonomic responses to emotional stimuli. PLoS One 8 (9): e74331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michal, M., B. Reuchlein, et al. 2014. Striking discrepancy of anomalous body experiences with normal interoceptive accuracy in depersonalization-derealization disorder. PLoS One 9 (2): e89823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moutoussis, M., P. Fearon, et al. 2014. Bayesian inferences about the self (and others): A review. Consciousness and Cognition 25: 67–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ochsner, K.N., and J.J. Gross. 2005. The cognitive control of emotion. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (5): 242–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paulus, M.P., and M.B. Stein. 2010. Interoception in anxiety and depression. Brain Structure and Function 214 (5–6): 451–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, Mary L., et al. 2001. Depersonalization disorder: thinking without feeling. Psychiatry Research: Neuroimaging 108 (3): 145–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Philippi, C.L., J.S. Feinstein, S.S. Khalsa, A. Damasio, D. Tranel, G. Landini, et al. 2012. Preserved self-awareness following extensive bilateral brain damage to the insula, anterior cingulate, and medial prefrontal cortices. PloS one 7 (8): e38413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. 2004. Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion. New York: Oxford Universty Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J. A., and L. Feldman Barrett. (2009) Core affect. The Oxford companion to emotion and the affective sciences:104.

  • Sander, D., et al. 2005. A systems approach to appraisal mechamisms in emotion. Neural Networks 18: 317–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sander, D., D. Grandjean, and K.R. Scherer. 2005. A systems approach to appraisal mechanisms in emotion. Neural Networks 18 (4): 317–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, Marya. 2011. "The narrative self."

  • Scherer, K. 2004. Feelings integrate the central representation of appraisal-drive response organisation in emotion. In Feelings and emotions: The Amsterdam symposium, ed. A.S. Manstead, N. Frijda, and A. Fischer, 136–157. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Sedeño, L., B. Couto, M. Melloni, A. Canales-Johnson, A. Yoris, S. Baez, et al. 2014. How do you feel when you can't feel your body? Interoception, functional connectivity and emotional processing in depersonalization-derealization disorder. PloS one 9 (6): e98769.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A.K. 2013. Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 17 (11): 565–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A.K., K. Suzuki, et al. 2012. An interoceptive predictive coding model of conscious presence. Frontiers in Psychology 2.

  • Sierra, M. 2008. Depersonalization disorder: Pharmacological approaches. Expert Review of Neurotherapeutics 8 (1): 19–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sierra, M., and A.S. David. 2011. Depersonalization: a selective impairment of self-awareness. Consciousness and Cognition 20 (1): 99–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simeon, D., D.S. Kozin, K. Segal, B. Lerch, R. Dujour, and T. Giesbrecht. 2008. De-constructing depersonalization: further evidence for symptom clusters. Psychiatry Research 157 (1-3): 303–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiech, K., and I. Tracey. 2013. Pain, decisions, and actions: A motivational perspective. Frontiers in Neuroscience 7: 46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philip Gerrans.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gerrans, P. Depersonalization Disorder, Affective Processing and Predictive Coding. Rev.Phil.Psych. 10, 401–418 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0415-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0415-2

Navigation