Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Ambiguous life expectancy and the demand for annuities

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, ambiguity aversion to uncertain survival probabilities is introduced in a static life-cycle model with a bequest motive to study the optimal demand for annuities. Provided that annuities’ return is sufficiently large, and notably when it is fair, positive annuitization is known to be the optimal strategy of ambiguity neutral individuals. Conversely, we show that the demand for annuities decreases with ambiguity aversion and that there exists a finite degree of aversion above which the demand is non-positive: the optimal strategy is then to either sell annuities short or to hold zero annuities if the former option is not available. To conclude, ambiguity aversion appears to be a relevant candidate for explaining the annuity puzzle.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Most notably, Brown et al. (2008) use the framing hypothesis and show that in an investment frame, individuals prefer non-annuitized products. This idea is developed by Benartzi et al. (2011) who demonstrate the importance of the availability and framing of annuity options in the demand for annuity.

  2. This idea was formalized and developed by Manski (2009).

  3. Gollier (2011) has applied this framework to a standard portfolio problem and shown that ambiguity aversion does not necessarily reinforce risk aversion.

  4. Moreover, our results could also be derived within the framework proposed by Gajdos et al. (2008).

  5. The function u is strictly concave if and only if the Hessian of u is negative definite, or equivalently, if and only if \(u^{\prime \prime }_{11}<0\) and \(u^{\prime \prime }_{11}u^{\prime \prime }_{22}-u^{\prime \prime \ 2}_{12}>0\) [see Theorems M.C.2 and M.D.2 in Mass-Colell et al. (1995)].

  6. Assuming the normality of c and x means assuming \(u^{\prime \prime }_{12}-Ru^{\prime \prime }_{22} >0\) and \(R u^{\prime \prime }_{12} - u^{\prime \prime }_{11}>0\) (see Appendix A).

  7. Reichling and Smettters (2015) show that a negative demand for annuities can emerge by allowing for the survival probabilities to be stochastic due to changes in health status and by including their concomitant costs.

  8. See Proposition 3 page 1867 in Klibanoff et al. (2005).

  9. See Theorem 2 page 1865 in Klibanoff et al. (2005).

References

  • Benartzi, S., Previtero, A., & Thaler, R. H. (2011). Annuitization puzzles. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 25, 143–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B. D. (1991). How strong are bequest motives? Evidence based on estimates of the demand for live insurance and annuities. Journal of Political Economy, 99, 899–927.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bommier, A., & Le Grand, F. (2014). Too risk averse to purchase insurance? A theoretical glance at the annuity puzzle. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 48, 135–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (2007). Rational and behavioral perspectives on the role of annuities in retirement planning. NBER Working Paper 13537.

  • Brown, J. R., Kling, J. R., Mullainathan, S., & Wrobel, M. V. (2008). Why don’t people insure late-life consumption? A framing explanation of the under-annuitization puzzle. American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings, 98, 304–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • d’Albis, H., & Thibault, E. (2012). Optimal annuitization, uncertain survival probabilities and maxmin preferences. Economics Letters, 115, 295–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidoff, T., Brown, J. R., & Diamond, P. A. (2005). Annuities and individual welfare. American Economic Review, 95, 1573–1590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drouhin, N. (2015). A rank-dependent utility model of uncertain lifetime. Journal of Economic Dynamics & Control, 53, 208–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, R., & Tuljapurkar, S. (2005). Inequality in life spans and a new perspective on mortality convergence across industrialized countries. Population and Development Review, 31, 645–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eeckhoudt, L., & Jeleva, M. (2004). Décision mé dicale et probabilities imprécises. Revue Economique, 55, 869–882.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L. G., & Zin, S. E. (1989). Substitution, risk aversion and the temporal behavior of consumption and asset returns: a theoretical framework. Econometrica, 57, 937–969.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gajdos, T., Tallon, J. M., Hayashi, T., & Vergnaud, J. C. (2008). Attitude toward imprecise information. Journal of Economic Theory, 140, 23–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (1989). Maxmin expected utility with non-unique prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 18, 141–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gollier, C. (2001). The Economics of risk and time. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gollier, C. (2011). Portfolio choices and asset prices: the comparative statics of ambiguity aversion. Review of Economic Studies, 78, 1329–1344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groneck, M., Ludwig, A., & Zimper, A. (2016). A life-cycle consumption model with ambiguous survival beliefs. Journal of Economic Theory, 162, 137–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Han, P., Kobrin, S., Klein, W., Davis, W., Stefanek, M., & Taplin, S. (2007). Perceived ambiguity about screening mammography recommendations: association with future mammography uptake and perceptions. Cancer Epidemiology, Biomarkers and Prevention, 16, 458–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Han, P., Moser, R., & Klein, W. (2006). Perceived ambiguity about cancer prevention recommendations: relationship to perceptions of cancer preventability, risk, and worry. Journal of Health Communication, 11, 51–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horneff, W. J., Maurer, R. H., & Stamos, M. Z. (2008). Life-cycle asset allocation with annuity markets. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 32, 3590–3612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, H., Milevsky, M. A., & Salisbury, T. S. (2012). Optimal retirement consumption with a stochastic force of mortality. Insurance: Mathematics and Economics, 51, 282–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inkmann, J., Lopes, P., & Michaelides, A. (2011). How deep is the annuity market participation puzzle? Review of Financial Studies, 24, 279–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • International Monetary Fund (2012). The financial impact of longevity risk. Global Financial Stability Report, Chapter 4.

  • Keynes, J. M. (1921). A Treatise on probability, London, UK: Macmillan and Co.

  • Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M., & Mukerji, S. (2005). A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica, 73, 1849–1892.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M., & Mukerji, S. (2009). Recursive smooth ambiguity preferences. Journal of Economic Theory, 144, 930–976.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D., & Porteus, E. (1978). Temporal resolution of uncertainty and dynamic choice theory. Econometrica, 46, 185–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lockwood, L. M. (2012). Bequest motives and the annuity puzzle. Review of Economic Dynamics, 15, 226–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, A., & Zimper, A. (2013). A parsimonious model of subjective life expectancy. Theory Decision, 75, 519–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manski, C. (2009). The 2009 Lawrence R. Klein Lecture: diversified treatment under ambiguity. International Economic Review, 50, 1013–1041.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mass-Colell, A., Whinston, M., & Green, J. (1995). Microeconomic theory. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meszaros, J. R., Asch, D. A., Baron, J., Hershey, J. C., Kunreuther, H., & Schwartz-Buzaglo, J. (1996). Cognitive processes and the decisions of some parents to forego pertussis vaccination for their children. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology, 49, 697–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oeppen, J., & Vaupel, J. W. (2002). Broken limits to life expectancy. Science, 296, 1029–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peijnenburg, K. (2016). Life-cycle asset allocation with ambiguity aversion and learning. Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1785321.

  • Peijnenburg, K., Nijman, T., & Werker, B. (2016). The annuity puzzle remains a puzzle. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 70, 18–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ponzetto, G. A. (2003). Risk aversion and the utility of annuities. CeRP Working Paper No. 31/03.

  • Post, T. (2012). Individual welfare gains from deferred life-annuities under stochastic mortality. Asia-Pacific Journal of Risk and Insurance, 6(2), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Post, T., & Hanewald, K. (2013). Longevity risk, subjective survival expectations, and individual saving behavior. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 86, 200–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Previtero, A. (2014). Stock market returns and annuitization. Journal of Financial Economics, 113, 202–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichling, F., & Smettters, K. (2015). Optimal annuitization with stochastic mortality and correlated medical costs. American Economic Review, 105, 3273–3320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riddel, M., & Shaw, W. D. (2006). A theoretically-consistent empirical model of non-expected utility: an application to nuclear-waste transport. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 32, 131–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheshinski, E. (2008). The economic theory of annuities. Princeton, USA: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treich, N. (2010). The value of a statistical life under ambiguity aversion. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 59, 15–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. K., & Aldy, J. E. (2003). The value of a statistical life: a critical review of market estimates throughout the world. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 27, 5–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. K., Magat, W. A., & Huber, J. (1991). Communication of ambiguous risk information. Theory and Decision, 31, 159–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yaari, M. E. (1965). Uncertain lifetime, life insurance, and the theory of the consumer. Review of Economic Studies, 32, 137–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hippolyte d’Albis.

Additional information

We are grateful to a referee of this Journal and to Fabrice Collard, Firouz Gahvari, Johannes Gierlinger, Jérôme Glachant, Christian Gollier, André Masson, Svetlana Pashchenko, Pierre Pestieau, Jean-Marc Tallon and Nicolas Treich for their excellent suggestions and comments. We also thank the participants of seminars and conferences where earlier versions of this paper were presented. H. d’Albis thanks the European Research Council (ERC Starting Grant DU 283953) and E. Thibault thanks the Chair Fondation du Risque/SCOR “Marché du risque et création de valeurs” for their financial support.

Appendices

Appendix

Appendix A: Proof of Proposition 1.

As a preliminary, let us establish that \(u^{\prime \prime }_{11}+R^2u^{\prime \prime }_{22}-2Ru^{\prime \prime }_{12}<0\), \(u^{\prime \prime }_{12}-Ru^{\prime \prime }_{22} >0\) and \(R u^{\prime \prime }_{12} - u^{\prime \prime }_{11}>0\).

First, as the Hessian of u is negative definiteness, it is straightforward that \(u^{\prime \prime }_{11}+R^2u^{\prime \prime }_{22}-2Ru^{\prime \prime }_{12}<0\). Second, consider the static program \(\max _{c,x} u[c,xR]\) subject to the constraint \(\Omega = c+x\) where \(\Omega \) is the life-cycle income of an agent. This program is equivalent to \(\max _{c}u[c,(\Omega -c)R]\) or \(\max _{x}u[\Omega -x,xR]\). Then, using the FOC of these programs and the implicit function theorem, there exist two functions A and B such that \(c=A(\Omega )\) and \(x=B(\Omega )\). It is straightforward that \(A'(\Omega )\) has the sign of \(u^{\prime \prime }_{12}-Ru^{\prime \prime }_{22} \) while \(B'(\Omega )\) has the one of \(R u^{\prime \prime }_{12} - u^{\prime \prime }_{11}\). By definition, c and x are normal goods if and only if \(\partial c / \partial \Omega \) and \(\partial x / \partial \Omega \) are positive. Then, Assumption 1 implies \(u^{\prime \prime }_{12}-Ru^{\prime \prime }_{22} >0\) and \(R u^{\prime \prime }_{12} - u^{\prime \prime }_{11}>0\).

A.1: Proof of statement (i).

Using (4), let us define \(F(a,x)=-u^{\prime }_1[c (a,x),x R] +Ru^{\prime }_2[c(a,x),x R]=0\). Under Assumption 1, \(F'_1(a,x)=(R_a-R)(Ru^{\prime \prime }_{12}-u^{\prime \prime }_{11})\) is non-negative whereas \(F'_2(a,x)=u^{\prime \prime }_{11}+R^2u^{\prime \prime }_{22}-2Ru^{\prime \prime }_{12}\) is negative. Then, there exists a continuous and differentiable function f such that \(x=f(a)\) and, under Assumption 1, \(0\le f'(a)=-F'_1(a,x)/F'_2(a,x)\le R_a-R\). Replacing \(x=f(a)\) and (4) in (3) allows us to define the solution \(({\bar{a}},f({\bar{a}}))\) as a pair satisfying:

$$\begin{aligned} G(a,R_a,p)=p(R_{a}-R) u^{\prime }_2[{\widehat{c}}(a), f(a)R] -(1-p)R v^{\prime }[( w-a) R^{2}] =0. \end{aligned}$$

Then, an optimal demand for annuities \({\bar{a}}\) is a real root of \(G(a,R_a,p)=(R_a-R)p\varphi (a)-R(1-p)\psi (a)\) where \(\varphi (a)=u^{\prime }_2[{\widehat{c}}(a), f(a)R]\) and \(\psi (a)=v^{\prime }[( w-a) R^{2}]\). After computations, \(\varphi '(a)=-R(R_a-R)(u^{\prime \prime \ 2}_{12} - u^{\prime \prime }_{11}u^{\prime \prime }_{22})/F'_2(a,x)\) and \(\psi '(a)=-R^2v^{\prime \prime }[( w-a) R^{2}]\). Then, under Assumption 1, \(\varphi \) is a decreasing function whereas \(\psi \) is an increasing one, implying \(G'_1(a,R_a,p)<0\). Moreover, \(\varphi (-Rw/(R_a-R))=+\infty \), \(0<\varphi (w)<+\infty \), \(0<\psi (-Rw/(R_a-R))<+\infty \) and \(\psi (w)=+\infty \). Then, as \(G'_1(a,R_a,p)<0\), \(G(-Rw/(R_a-R),R_a,p)>0\) and \(G(w,R_a,p)<0\), there exists a unique optimal pair \(({\bar{a}},{\bar{x}})\). This pair is such that \({\bar{a}}\in (-Rw/(R_a-R),w)\) and \(0<{\bar{x}}=f({\bar{a}})<w\).

A.2: Proof of statement (ii).

Since \(G({\bar{a}},R_a,p)=0\) and \(G'_1(a,R_a,p)<0\), \({\bar{a}}\) is positive if and only if \(G(0,R_a,p)\) is positive. Importantly, f(0) is independent of \(R_a\) because (4) is independent of \(R_a\) when \(a=0\). Consequently, \(\varphi (0)=u'_2[Rw-f(0),f(0)R]\) and \(\psi (0)=v'[wR^2]\) are independent of \(R_a\) and we have \(G'_2(0,R_a,p)=p\varphi (0)>0\). Note that \(G(0,R/p,p)=R(1-p)(u'_2[Rw-f(0),f(0)R]-v'[wR^2])\). As \(f(0)<wR\) and \(u'_2[c,y]\ge v'[y]\), we have \(G(0,R/p,p)>0\). Since \(G(0,R,p)<0\) and \(G'_2(0,R_a,p)>0\), there exists a unique \(\widehat{R}_a\in (R,R/p)\) such that \(G(0,\widehat{R}_a,p)=0\). Consequently, \({\bar{a}}\) is positive if and only if \(R_a\) is larger than \(\widehat{R}_a\). \(\square \)

A.3: Proof of statement (iii).

According to Appendix A.2, \({\bar{a}}\ge 0\) if and only if \(G(0,R_a,p)\ge 0\). As \(G'_3(0,R_a,p)>0\), \(G(0,R_a,0)=-Rv'[wR^2]<0\) and \(G(0,R_a,1)=(R_a-R)u'_2[{\widehat{c}}(0),f(0)R]>0\), there exists a unique \({\widehat{p}}\in (0,1)\) such that \({\bar{a}}\) is positive if and only if p is larger than \({\widehat{p}}\). \(\square \)

Appendix B: Proof of Proposition 2.

As a preliminary, it would be useful to establish the following lemma:

Lemma 1

If (4) is satisfied (i.e., if \({\bar{x}}=f({\bar{a}})\)) then the difference between u[.] the utility if alive and v[.] the utility if not is positive if and only if p is larger than a threshold \(\check{p}\in (0,{\widehat{p}})\). Moreover, the demand for annuities \({\underline{a}}\) equalizing the utilities in the two states of nature is unique and negative.

Proof

Let \(\tau (a)=u[{\widehat{c}}(a),f(a)R]\) be the utility if alive. As \(0\le f'(a)\le R_a-R\) and \(\tau '(a)=[(R_a-R)-f'(a)]u'_1[{\widehat{c}}(a),f(a)R]+Rf'(a)u'_2[{\widehat{c}}(a),f(a)R]\), the utility if alive increases with the demand for annuity while the utility if not, namely \(v[(w-a)R^2]\), decreases with a. Hence, the difference between u[.] the utility if alive and v[.] the utility if not:

$$\begin{aligned} \xi (a)=u[{\widehat{c}}(a),f(a)R]-v[(w-a)R^2] \end{aligned}$$

increases with respect to a.

Let us define \({\underline{a}}\), the demand for annuities equalizing the utilities in the two states of nature (i.e., such that \(\xi ({\underline{a}})=0\)). Under Assumption 2 \(\xi (-wR/(R_a-R))=u[0,0]-v[R^2R_aw/(R_a-R)]<0\) and \(\xi (0)=u[{\widehat{c}}(0),f(0)R]-v[wR^2]>0\). As \(\xi '(a)>0\), the demand for annuities \({\underline{a}}\) is unique and negative.

As \(\xi ({\underline{a}})=0\) and \(\xi '(a)>0\), \(\xi ({\bar{a}})>0\) if and only if \({\bar{a}}>{\underline{a}}\), i.e., if and only if \(G({\underline{a}},R_a,p)>0\). As \(G'_3({\underline{a}},R_a,p)>0\), \(G({\underline{a}},R_a,0)=-Rv'[(w-{\underline{a}})R^2]<0\) and \(G({\underline{a}},R_a,1)=(R_a-R)u'_2[{\widehat{c}}({\underline{a}}),f({\underline{a}})R]>0\), there exists a unique \(\check{p}\in (0,1)\) such that \(\xi ({\bar{a}})\) is positive if and only if p is larger than \(\check{p}\). As \(G({\underline{a}},R_a,\check{p})=G({\bar{a}},R_a,{\widehat{p}})=0\), \({\underline{a}}<0\), \(G'_1(a,R_a,p)<0\) and \(G'_3({\underline{a}},R_a,p)>0\), we have \(\check{p}<{\widehat{p}}\). \(\square \)

We now consider the problem (\({\mathcal {P}}_\phi \)) and denote by \((a^{\star },x^{\star })\) its solution which is the solution of (10) and (11).

B.1: Proof of statement (i).

We first show that \(a^\star \) is lower than \({\bar{a}}\). Let us define the random variable \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,{\widetilde{p}})={\mathcal {U}}(a,f(a),{\widetilde{p}})\) where the application \(x=f(a)\) is derived from (11). Then, \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,{\widetilde{p}})\) represents the expected utility when the budget constraint (1) and the consumption-bequest optimal allocation (11) are satisfied. It is a function of the random variable \({\widetilde{p}}\). Moreover, let \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,p_\varepsilon )\) denote the expected utility associated to \(p_\varepsilon \), a realization of \( {\widetilde{p}}\). Then, the system of equations (10) and (11) rewrites as a single equation in a:

$$\begin{aligned} \eta _{_\phi }(a)= & {} E(\phi ^{\prime }(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,{\widetilde{p}}))\{{\widetilde{p}}(R_{a}-R) u_1^{\prime }[{\widehat{c}}(a),f(a)R] \\&-\,( 1-{\widetilde{p}}) R^{2}v^{\prime }[(w-a) R^{2}]\}) =0. \end{aligned}$$

We are going to prove that \(\eta _{_\phi }({\underline{a}})>0\), \(\eta _{_\phi }({\bar{a}})<0\) and \(\eta '_{_\phi }(a)<0\) for \(a\in [{\underline{a}},{\bar{a}}]\).

As \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}({\underline{a}},{\widetilde{p}})\) is independent of \({\widetilde{p}}\), \(\eta _{_\phi }({\underline{a}})\) has the sign of:

$$\begin{aligned} E\left( {\widetilde{p}}(R_{a}-R) u_1^{\prime }[{\widehat{c}}({\underline{a}}),f({\underline{a}})R] -( 1-{\widetilde{p}}) R^{2}v^{\prime }[(w-{\underline{a}}) R^{2}]\right) , \end{aligned}$$

i.e., since \(E{\widetilde{p}}=p\) and (11), the one of \(G({\underline{a}},R_a,p)\). Under Assumption 3 and according to Lemma 1 we have \(G({\underline{a}},R_a,p)>0\) and, consequently, \(\eta _{_\phi }({\underline{a}})>0\). Since \(G({\bar{a}},R_a,p)=0\), using (11) we have \(\eta _{_\phi }({\bar{a}})=E(\phi ^{\prime }(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}({\bar{a}},{\widetilde{p}}))RG({\bar{a}},R_a,{\widetilde{p}}))=Cov(\phi '(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}({\bar{a}},{\widetilde{p}})),\) \(RG({\bar{a}},R_a,{\widetilde{p}}))<0\). Since \(\phi \) is concave and \(G'_1(a,R_a,{\widetilde{p}})<0\), \(\eta '_{_\phi }(a)<0\). Consequently, \(\eta _{_\phi }\) has a unique real root that shall be denoted \(a^{\star }\) and that belongs to \(({\underline{a}},{\bar{a}})\).

Importantly, the derivative of function \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,p_\varepsilon )\) with respect to a realization \(p_\varepsilon \) is:

$$\begin{aligned} \widehat{\mathcal {U}}_2^{\prime }(a,p_\varepsilon )=u[{\widehat{c}}(a),f(a)R] -v[(w -a) R^{2}]\equiv \xi (a). \end{aligned}$$

Then, \(\xi (a)=\widehat{\mathcal {U}}_2^{\prime }(a,p_\varepsilon )\) is independent of any realizations of \({\widetilde{p}}\). Since \(\xi ^{\prime }(a) >0\), \(\xi ({\underline{a}})=0\) and \(a^\star >{\underline{a}}\), we have \(\xi (a^{\star })\ge 0\).

We now show that \(a^\star \) decreases with ambiguity aversion. The strategy is to consider two independent DMs. The problem of the first DM is given by (\({\mathcal {P}}_\phi \)) and her optimal demand for annuities is denoted \(a^{\star }\). The second DM faces the similar problem \(({\mathcal {P}}_\psi )\) with \(\psi \equiv T\circ \phi \) and where T is an increasing and concave function. Her optimal demand, denoted \(a^{\star \star }\), is a solution of:

$$\begin{aligned} \eta _{_{T\circ \phi }}(a)= & {} E(\psi ^{\prime } (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,{\widetilde{p}}))\{{\widetilde{p}}(R_{a}-R) u_1^{\prime }[{\widehat{c}}(a),f(a)R]\\&-\,( 1-{\widetilde{p}}) R^{2}v^{\prime }[(w-a) R^{2}]\}) =0, \end{aligned}$$

where \(\psi ^{\prime }(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,{\widetilde{p}}))=T^{\prime }(\phi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,{\widetilde{p}})))\phi ^{\prime }(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,{\widetilde{p}}))\). Note that \(\eta _{_{T\circ \phi }}(a)\) is a decreasing function of a.

From Step 1 to Step 4 it is supposed that \({\widetilde{p}}\) has only two realizations, \(p_{1}\) and \(p_{2} \), satisfying \(1\ge p_{1}>p_{2}\ge 0\), and whose occurrence probabilities are, respectively, q and \(1-q\). The result obtained is generalized in Step 5 for any distribution of \({\widetilde{p}}\).

\(\underline{Step\; 1 -- \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1})\ge \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2}) \;and \; \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1}) \ge \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2}).}\)

Let \(a^\sharp \) an optimum (i.e., \(a^\sharp =a^\star \) or \(a^{\star \star }\)). Then, we have \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^\sharp ,p_1)-\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^\sharp ,p_2)=(p_1-p_2)\xi (a^\sharp )\). As we have proved that \(\xi (a^\sharp )\ge 0\), we have \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^\sharp ,p_1)\ge \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^\sharp ,p_2)\) for \(a^\sharp =a^\star \) and \(a^\sharp =a^{\star \star }\).

\(\underline{Step \, 2 -- \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1})-\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1}) \, and \,\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2}) -\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2}) \; have \; opposite} \underline{signs.}\)

Proceed by contradiction. Suppose first they are both positive. This implies that \(E(\psi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },{\widetilde{p}}))) >E(\psi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },{\widetilde{p}})) )\), which is not possible since \(E(\psi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },{\widetilde{p}})))\) is a maximum. Similarly, they cannot be both negative because this would imply that \(E(\phi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star }, {\widetilde{p}})))\) is not a maximum.

\(\underline{Step \; 3 -- \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1})>\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1}) \;and \;\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2})<\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2}).}\)

As a preliminary, the definition of a maximum yields \(E(\phi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },{\widetilde{p}})))>E(\phi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },{\widetilde{p}})))\), which rewrites:

$$\begin{aligned} q[\phi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1})) -\phi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1}))]<(1-q) [\phi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2}))-\phi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2}))]. \end{aligned}$$
(13)

Equivalently, \(E(\psi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },{\widetilde{p}})))>E(\psi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },{\widetilde{p}}) ))\) rewrites:

$$\begin{aligned} q[\psi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1}))-\psi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1}))] >(1-q)[\psi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2}))-\psi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2}))]. \end{aligned}$$
(14)

Now proceed by contradiction by supposing that \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1})<\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1})\). Using Steps 1 and 2, this implies that \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2})<\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2})<\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1}) <\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1})\). Since \(\phi \) and \(\psi \) are both increasing, dividing (14) by (13) yields the following inequalities:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\psi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1}) ) -\psi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1}) ) }{\phi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1}) ) -\phi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1}) ) }> \frac{\psi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2}) ) -\psi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2}) ) }{\phi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2}) ) -\phi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2}) ) }>0. \end{aligned}$$
(15)

Denote \(y_{1}=\phi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2}) ) ,\) \( y_{2}=\phi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2}) ) ,\) \(y_{3}=\phi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1}) ) ,\) and \(y_{4}=\phi ( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1}) ) \). Hence, \( y_{1}<y_{2}<y_{3}<y_{4} \) and (15) rewrites as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{T( y_{4}) -T( y_{3}) }{y_{4}-y_{3}}>\frac{ T( y_{2}) -T( y_{1}) }{y_{2}-y_{1}}. \end{aligned}$$
(16)

This latter inequality is true if and only if T is convex. Since T is concave, conclude that \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1}) >\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1}) \) and, using Step 2, that \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2}) <\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2})\).

\(\underline{Step \; 4 -- a^{\star }>a^{\star \star }\; for\; a\; binary\; distribution.}\)

For an optimum a, we have \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,p_{1}) -\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,p_{2})=(p_1-p_2)\xi (a)\) where \(\xi (a)>0\) and \(\xi '(a)>0\). Then, \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,p_{1}) -\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a,p_{2})\) is an increasing function of a. According to Steps 1 and 2, \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{1}) -\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },p_{2}) >\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{1}) -\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star \star },p_{2}) \ge 0\). Consequently, \(a^{\star }>a^{\star \star }\).

\(\underline{Step \; 5 -- a^{\star }>a^{\star \star } \; for \;any\; distribution\; of \; {\widetilde{p}}.}\)

We have previously shown that \(\eta _{_\phi }(a)\) and \(\eta _{_{T\circ \phi }}(a)\) are decreasing functions of a. Consequently, \((a^{\star }>a^{\star \star })\) if and only if \((E(g({\widetilde{p}} )) =0\Rightarrow E(h({\widetilde{p}})) <0)\) where \(g({\widetilde{p}}) =\phi ^{\prime }(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },{\widetilde{p}} ))\{{\widetilde{p}}(R_{a}-R) u_1^{\prime }[{\widehat{c}}(a^\star ),f(a^\star )R] -( 1-{\widetilde{p}}) R^{2}v^{\prime }[(w-a^\star ) R^{2}]\}\) and \(h({\widetilde{p}}) =T^{\prime }(\phi (\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star },\) \( {\widetilde{p}}) ) )\phi ^{\prime }( \widehat{\mathcal {U}}(a^{\star }, {\widetilde{p}}) )\{{\widetilde{p}}(R_{a}-R) u_1^{\prime }[{\widehat{c}}(a^\star ),f(a^\star )R] -(1-{\widetilde{p}}) R^{2}v^{\prime }[(w-a^\star ) R^{2}]\}\).

The diffidence theorem then applies [see Lemma 1 page 84 in Gollier (2001)] and, thus, the result \(a^{\star }>a^{\star \star }\) holds for any distribution of \({\widetilde{p}}\). Then, the demand for annuities decreases with ambiguity aversion.

B.2: Proof of statement (ii).

According to (9) the following maxmin problem, denoted, is obtained when the absolute ambiguity aversion, given by \(-\phi ^{\prime \prime }/\phi ^{\prime }\), is infinite: (\({\mathcal {P}}_{\infty }\))

figure c

First observe that the optimum \((a^\sharp ,x^\sharp )\) is such that \(x^\sharp =f(a^\sharp )\). Indeed, for any optimal value \(p_\varepsilon ^\sharp \), \((a^\sharp ,x^\sharp )\) is determined by maximizing \({\mathcal {U}}(a,x,p_\varepsilon ^\sharp )\) subject to (1) and (2). The FOC (4) of the expected utility problem (\({\mathcal {P}}_{0}\)) (where \(p=p_\varepsilon ^\sharp \)) is independent of \(p_\varepsilon ^\sharp \) and implies that \(x^\sharp =f(a^\sharp )\).

Consequently, there are only three candidates for the optimum \(a^\sharp \) according to the sign of \(\xi (a^\sharp )\).

The first candidate corresponds to the case where \(\xi (a^\sharp )=0\). Then it corresponds to the (unique) pair (\({\underline{a}},f({\underline{a}})\)) exhibited in Lemma 1. The maxmin utility attainable is then \(v[(w-{\underline{a}})R^2]\).

The second candidate \(\breve{a}\) corresponds to the case where \(\xi (a^\sharp )<0\). As \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}(\breve{a},p_\varepsilon )=p_\varepsilon \xi (\breve{a}) +v[(w-\breve{a})R^2]<v[(w-\breve{a})R^2]\), the maxmin utility attainable is lower than \(v[(w-\breve{a})R^2]\). Importantly, \(\breve{a}\) is obviously the solution of the expected utility problem (\({\mathcal {P}}_{0}\)) where \(p=p_{M}\) is the upper bound of Supp\(({\widetilde{p}})\), the support of \( {\widetilde{p}}.\) Then, according to Assumption 3 and Lemma 1, we have \({\underline{a}}<\breve{a}\) and, consequently, \(v[(w-\breve{a})R^2]< v[(w-{\underline{a}})R^2]\). Since the maxmin utility attainable with \(\breve{a}\) is strictly lower than the one attainable with \({\underline{a}}\), we have necessarily \(\xi (a^\sharp )\ge 0\) at the optimum.

The third candidate \({\check{a}}\) corresponds to the case where \(\xi (a^\sharp )>0\). Importantly, \({\check{a}}\) is the solution of the expected utility problem (\({\mathcal {P}}_{0}\)) where \(p=p_{m}\) is the lower bound of Supp\(({\widetilde{p}})\). Then, according to Assumption 3 and Lemma 1, we have \({\underline{a}}<{\check{a}}\). We now show that this third candidate cannot solve the problem (\({\mathcal {P}}_{\infty }\)) because if \({\check{a}}\) solves the problem (\({\mathcal {P}}_{\infty }\)) we have necessarily \({\underline{a}}\ge {\check{a}}\). Indeed, assume that \({\check{a}}\) solves the problem (\({\mathcal {P}}_{\infty }\)). Then we have \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}({\underline{a}},p_{m})\le \widehat{\mathcal {U}}({\check{a}},p_{m})\). As \(0=\xi ({\underline{a}})=\widehat{\mathcal {U}}^{\prime }_2({\underline{a}},p_\varepsilon )<\xi ({\check{a}})=\widehat{\mathcal {U}}^{\prime }_2({\check{a}},p_\varepsilon )\), we obtain \(\widehat{\mathcal {U}}({\underline{a}},1)\le \widehat{\mathcal {U}}({\check{a}},1)\), i.e., \(u[{\widehat{c}}({\underline{a}}),f({\underline{a}})R]\le u[{\widehat{c}}({\check{a}}),f({\check{a}})R]\). As, \(u[{\widehat{c}}(a),f(a)R]\) is increasing function of a, we have \({\underline{a}}\ge {\check{a}}\).

Consequently, we have \(\xi (a^\sharp )=0\) at the optimum and the optimal pair \((a^\sharp ,x^\sharp )\) which solves the problem (\({\mathcal {P}}_{\infty }\)) is the pair \(({\underline{a}},f({\underline{a}}))\) exhibited Lemma 1. Then, according to Lemma 1, the demand for annuities is always negative when ambiguity aversion is infinite. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

d’Albis, H., Thibault, E. Ambiguous life expectancy and the demand for annuities. Theory Decis 85, 303–319 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-018-9658-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-018-9658-8

Keywords

Navigation