Skip to main content
Log in

Definitions of life as epistemic tools that reflect and foster the advance of biological knowledge

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

During the last decades the question of defining life has gained increased interest but, at the same time, the difficulty in reaching consensus on a possible answer has led many to skeptical positions. This, in turn, has raised a wider debate about why defining life is so hard and controversial. Such a debate (or ‘meta-debate’) introduces additional aspects to be considered, like the role and nature of a definition of life itself. In this paper, we will focus on those aspects, arguing that progress can be made (and has, indeed, been made) if we conceive definitions of life as open heuristic tools that contribute(d) to develop specific research strategies in the biological sciences and, more generally, to increase our understanding of life’s complexity. In contrast with pragmatic or operationalist approaches, we will defend that definitions of life comprise a set of ontological assumptions, together with an inherent unifying vocation, so they should be subject to comparison and critical assessment, closely related to the success or failure of the corresponding research programs, but also to the success or failure in establishing well-grounded interconnections among the latter. We consider that the search for a more coherent, integrated and generalized theory of biology cannot be pursued without keeping an empirical standpoint, and the exercise of defining life should not be taken as an obstacle but as a valuable (and, of course, evaluable) instrument to achieve that goal.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. According to the Cambridge Dictionary a definition is a description of the features and limits of something, trying to specify the criteria through which we can uniquely identify it. Cleland and Chyba (2002), following another entry of the same dictionary (Audi 1995), go further and state that a definition, in a logician’s sense, should specify necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of the term being defined. Anyhow, it is clear that definitions are more demanding than conceptions (which could remain rather vague or implicit), precisely because they are attempts to make those characteristic aspects/features of a phenomenon as apparent and clear as possible, avoiding circularities, overlaps, etc. For a more thorough account about the requisites that definitions of life, in particular, should meet, see: (Emmeche 1998; Ruiz-Mirazo et al. 2004).

  2. To be fair, Cleland, Chyba and Machery also argue that definitions or conceptions of life may play a role in terms of directing or articulating research lines (cf. Cleland and Chyba 2002, p. 387; Machery 2012, p. 7).

  3. For the purpose of our argument, we do not need to endorse here all the ingredients of the Lakatosian theory of science. For instance, we do not consider that all scientists in a particular research program should share all the claims of the corresponding ‘hard core’ (instead, they could sometimes disagree on certain aspects, like Robert Richards (1987) correctly pointed out). Similarly, we do not subscribe the way in which Lakatos explains the “progressivity” of a research program (Laudan 1977).

  4. This, of course, is the result of a historical process (which could be termed as the “pre-history” of a given scientific discipline) during which that community becomes constituted. Most historians of biology agree that the birth of this discipline could be dated back to, approximately, 1800.

  5. There are some similarities between the process described here and what Hasok Chang calls ‘epistemic iteration’, i.e., a process « in which successive stages of knowledge, each building on the preceding one, are created in order to enhance the achievement of certain epistemic goals » (Chang 2004, p. 45), and where a succession of approximations, corrections, changes and revisions during this process increases the degree of accuracy, explanatory power, consistency (and other epistemic values) of scientific outcomes and knowledge.

  6. For instance, the community of computational ‘a-lifers’ (Langton 1989, 1992; Boden 1996) failed in this regard. They posed a number of very interesting questions for biology, but they did not manage to include their domain of research into that of the standard life sciences. Basically, most biologists did not accept as common to them the new empirical referents that ‘a-lifers’ introduced for their research.

  7. A similar view is defended by Tirard et al. (2010) when they say that « research in the origin and nature of life is doomed to remain, at best, as a work in progress. It is difficult to find a definition of life accepted by all, but the history of biology has shown that some efforts are much more fruitful than others » (p. 1008). See also (Smith 2016).

  8. This is not to say that the quest for definitions of life should not be guided by the goal to find, so to speak, successful definitions -- by which we mean meta-stable points in this dynamic scenario. To express it in simple terms, we could use the motto: ‘revise data, given explanation; revise explanation, given data; until some (transient) equilibrium is reached’ (which includes definitions, why shouldn’t it?).

  9. For instance, those between mechanicists and organicists; between physiology-centered and evolutionary-centered research programs; between analytic and integrative strategies…. We should remark here that our use of the term ‘paradigmatic’ is not in a strict Kuhnian sense: it does not imply the incommensurability of different scientific research programs, organized around a central conceptual core, but just conveys the idea that we can indirectly evaluate and compare this conceptual core—and even make progress towards the integration between different research programs and outcomes, as we have argued.

  10. Bare lists of properties, for instance, have not proved fruitful over the years, so they should be regarded with skepticism, if not utterly discarded (Ruiz-Mirazo et al 2004). Among other problems, they do not provide a suitable platform to elaborate an explanatory account around them, like any definition of life should do—showing (with as much precision and clarity as possible) how the different concepts, properties and processes involved relate to each other. Recent arguments in favor of interpreting life as a ‘homeostatic property cluster kind’ (‘HPC-kind’, as opposed to traditional notion of ‘natural kind’ (Diéguez 2013; Ferreira and Umerez 2018)) do not overcome this severe difficulty of ‘list definitions’, in our view.

References

  • Abouheif, E., Favé, M.-J., Ibarrarán-Viniegra, A. S., Lesoway, M. P., Rafiqi, A. M., & Rajakumar, R. (2014). Eco-Evo-Devo: The time has come. In C. R. Landry & N. Aubin-Horth (Eds.), Ecological genomics: Ecology and the evolution of genes and genomes (pp. 107–125). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (Ed.). (1995). The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. A., & Cleland, C. E. (2010). The nature of life: Classical and contemporary perspectives from philosophy and science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Benner, S. A., & Sismour, A. M. (2005). Synthetic biology. Nature Reviews Genetics, 6(7), 533–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., & Green, S. (2018). Is defining life pointless? operational definitions at the frontiers of biology. Synthese, 195, 3919–3946.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boden, M. (1996). The philosophy of artificial life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2004). Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. E. (2012). Life without definitions. Synthese, 185(1), 125–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. E., & Chyba, C. F. (2002). Defining ‘life’. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 32(4), 387–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. E., & Chyba, C. F. (2007). Does “life” have a definition? In W. T. Sullivan & J. A. Baross (Eds.), Planets and life: The emerging science of astrobiology (pp. 119–131). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Diéguez, A. (2013). Life as a homeostatic property cluster. Biological Theory, 7(2), 180–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C. (1998). Defining Life, Explaining Emergence (A web version of a paper published later as C. Emmeche & Charbel Niño El-Hani (1999). Definindo vida, explicando emergencia, Série Ciência e Memória, No. 02/99 (CNPq, Observatório Nacional, Rio de Janeiro).

  • Ferreira, M., & Umerez, J. (2018). Dealing with the changeable and blurry edges of living things: A modified version of property-cluster kinds. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8, 493–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J., Malaterre, C., & Morange, M. (2010). Defining life: Conference proceedings. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40, 119–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, C. (1995). Reason, regulation and realism: Toward a naturalistic, regulatory systems theory of reason. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1976). Are species really individuals? Systematic Biology, 25(2), 174–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F. (1974). The logic of life. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (2002). The century beyond the gene. Journal of Biosciences, 30, 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (2005). Making sense of life: Explaining biological development with models, metaphors, and machines. New York: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitano, H. (2002). Systems biology: A brief overview. Science, 295(5560), 1662–1664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In Lakatos (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Republished as chapter 1 of Lakatos (1978) The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes (Philosophical Papers: Volume 1) Worrall J and Currie G (Eds.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Cited pages from this version).

  • Laland, K. N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, J., Hoppitt, W., & Uller, T. (2011). Cause and effect in biology revisited: Is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science, 334(6062), 1512–1516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, C. G. (1989). Artificial Life: Proceedings of an Interdisciplinary Workshop on the Synthesis and Simulation of Living Systems. Boston: Addison-Wesley Longman Publishing Co., Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, C. G. (1992). Life at the edge of Chaos. In C. G. Langton, C. Taylor, J. D. Farmer, & S. Rasmussen (Eds.), Artificial life, Santa Fe Institute Studies in the sciences of complexity, proceedings (Vol. X). Redwood City: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte, J. (2003). Natural kinds and conceptual change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2012). Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life and why you should as well. Synthese, 185(1), 145–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mariscal, C., & Doolittle, W. F. (2018). Life and life only: A radical alternative to life definitionism. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1852-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J. (1986). The problems of biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1982). The growth of biological thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morange, M. (2010). The resurrection of life. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40, 179–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morange, M., & Falk, R. (2012). The recent evolution of the question ‘what is life?’. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 34(3), 425–438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., & Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (1999). Metabolism and the problem of its universalization. BioSystems, 49(1), 45–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G. B. (2007). Evo-devo: Extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nature Reviews Genetics, 8, 943–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neveu, M., Linsay, E. H., Mary, A. V., Michael, H. N., & Mitchell, D. S. (2018). The ladder of life detection. Astrobiology, 218(11), 1375–1402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pályi, G., Zucchi, C., & Caglioti, L. (Eds.). (2002). Fundamentals of life. Paris: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popa, R. (2004). Between necessity and probability: Searching for the definition and origin of life. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. (1987). Darwinism and the emergence of evolutionary theories of mind and behavior. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K., & Moreno, A. (2013). Synthetic Biology: Challenging life in order to grasp, use or extend it. Biological Theory, 8, 376–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Peretó, J., & Moreno, A. (2004). A universal definition of life: Autonomy and open-ended evolution. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 34(3), 323–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Peretó, J., & Moreno, A. (2010). Defining life or bringing biology to life. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40, 203–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrodinger, E. (1944). What is life?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, K. C. (2016). Life is hard: Countering definitional pessimism concerning the definition of life. International Journal of Astrobiology, 15, 277–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szostak, J. W. (2012). Attempts to define life do not help to understand the origin of life. Journal of Biomolecular Structure and Dynamics, 29(4), 599–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tirard, S., Morange, M., & Lazcano, A. (2010). The definition of life: A brief history of an elusive scientific. Endeavor Special collection of essays: What is life? Astrobiology, 10(10), 1003–1009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M. (2015). Organisms, agency, and evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Westerhoff, H. V., & Palsson, B. O. (2004). The evolution of molecular biology into systems biology. Nature Biotechnology, 22(10), 1249–1252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

All authors acknowledge support from two research projects, one from the Basque Government (IT 1228-19), and one from MINECO (FFI2014-52173-P). AM also held the Salvador de Madariaga Fellowship PRX17/00379, and would like to thank the IHPST (Paris) for hosting his research stay during the first semester of 2018. KR-M got support from the European Commission (Marie Curie ITN Program: ‘ProtoMet’—Grant Agreement no. 813873—Horizon 2020) and was part of COST Action TD 1308 (‘Origins and evolution of life on Earth and in the Universe’) during the elaboration of this article. Leonardo Bich’s careful reading and valuable comments on a previous manuscript are also highly appreciated.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kepa Ruiz-Mirazo.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Amilburu, A., Moreno, Á. & Ruiz-Mirazo, K. Definitions of life as epistemic tools that reflect and foster the advance of biological knowledge. Synthese 198, 10565–10585 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02736-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02736-7

Keywords

Navigation