Skip to main content
Log in

Defeasible normative reasoning

  • S.I.: LogPerSciCog
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper is motivated by the need of accounting for the practical syllogism as a piece of defeasible reasoning. To meet the need, the paper first refers to ranking theory as an account of defeasible descriptive reasoning. It then argues that two kinds of ought need to be distinguished, purely normative and fact-regarding obligations (in analogy to intrinsic and extrinsic utilities). It continues arguing that both kinds of ought can be iteratively revised and should hence be represented by ranking functions, too, just as iteratively revisable beliefs. Its central proposal will then be that the fact-regarding normative ranking function must be conceived as the sum of a purely normative ranking function and an epistemic ranking function (as suggested in qualitative decision theory). The distinctions defends this proposal with a comparative discussion of some critical examples and some other distinctions made in the literature. It gives a more rigorous justification of this proposal. Finally, it starts developing the logic of purely normative and of fact-regarding normative defeasible reasoning, points to the difficulties of completing the logic of the fact-regarding side, but reaches the initial aim of accounting for the defeasible nature of the practical syllogism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Aristotle actually takes the conclusion of a practical syllogism to be the action itself and not a sentence saying that that action ought to be performed. Many interpreters take this to be significant. Here, however, I neglect this point in order to treat the practical syllogism as an ordinary inference between sentences.

  2. Pigden (2010) is an up-to-date collection of papers on Hume’s Thesis, in which, however, defeasibility issues play no significant role.

  3. See, however, the criticism of Fuhrmann (2017).

  4. In the present context it is particularly noteworthy that Cohen’s theory of Baconian probability, as he called it, is an important predecessor of ranking theory; cf. Spohn (2012, sect. 11.1). In Cohen (1977) he unfolds in book length that his theory is especially tailored to legal reasoning.

  5. A short note about the history of this paper: In my master thesis 1973 I presented a sound and complete calculus for Hansson’s (1969) semantics of conditional deontic logic, unaware of the fact that Lewis (1973) had contemporaneously and more elegantly done the very same. My result is published in Spohn (1975). At that time I felt the strong urge that conditional deontic logic needs to be extended to an alethic-deontic logic, e.g., in order to represent the practical syllogism. I did not see, though, how this could be done; the only way to account for the interaction of norms and facts, or rather of beliefs and desires, seemed to be to turn to quantitative decision theory. That’s what I did then in my dissertation. However, I never made whole peace with this move. Reading Schurz (1997), which is still the most thorough-going investigation into Hume’s thesis and into alethic-deontic logic, inspired me to think again about this issue and to find a way to fill the old lacuna with ranking theoretic means (whence this paper is well placed in this collection in honor of Gerhard Schurz). The defeasible aspect is not well belabored in his book (as he would be the first to agree). That’s where I hope to make progress.

  6. Well, perhaps not in the form originally found in Aristotle, but in a form as it is discussed today.

  7. The following material is much more extensively explained in Spohn (2009, 2012, ch. 5).

  8. This point is fully elaborated in Huber (2007). There are various other justifications of ranking theory.

  9. Goldszmidt and Pearl (1991) develop system Z into system Z+, which allows default rules to have varying strength. This is similar to endowing arguments with varying strength, as done by Mogdil and Prakken (2013). Kern-Isberner (2004) has proposed an alternative algorithm applying a different notion of minimality.

  10. See Lewis (1976) and Gärdenfors (1988, ch. 7). I take Rott (2011) to be the relatively best that can be done.

  11. The latter condition makes conditionals with impossible antecedents vacuously true. For a full treatment of those exceptional antecedents see Raidl (2018).

  12. Carmo and Jones (2002), e.g., try to avoid deductive closure, although they accept substitutivity of logical equivalents. Concerning moral dilemmas, see the excellent overview of Goble (2013), who discusses in Sects. 5 and 6 how revisions of standard deontic logic might encompass normative conflicts. In Sect. 4, however, he explains how normative conflicts may be treated without such revisions—a line of thought which I definitely prefer and will take up again in Sect. 6.

  13. See Jones and Pörn (1985) for an early implementation of this diagnosis, which can be found in several variants, e.g., in Carmo and Jones (2002, pp. 299ff.).

  14. See the references in the previous footnote. We find this idea also in Schurz (1997, p. 41, footnote 31).

  15. At this point I may add a remark on my own behalf. In formal epistemology, Bayesianism is the dominating conception. Bayesians think that other conceptions of epistemic states must be reducible to the basic conception of subjective probabilities. I have always argued that ranking functions are not so reducible; prima facie, at least, we should accept ranking theory as an independent epistemological theory. I think the above ranking-theoretic construal of normative conceptions strengthens my case. In the case of epistemology, Bayesianism is quite plausible, no doubt. However, its normative counterpart has no plausibility at all. Probabilities should then be interpreted as degrees of obligation or prohibition or value. But how? I don’t see how a normative reinterpretation of Bayesianism could make sense. For an opposing view see, however, Merin (1996, ch. 4), who gives Aristotle’s endoxastic conception of probability a normative twist by interpreting endoxastic probability as ‘approvability’. Bayesians must judge whether they welcome this support.

  16. That’s the so-called Harper identity translated into our present context. Cf. Gärdenfors (1988, p. 70).

  17. These are the familiar contraction postulates (K-7) and (K-(8) translated into our context. Cf. Gärdenfors (1988, p. 64).

  18. I am grateful to two reviewers demanding that clarification.

  19. Instead of conditional and unconditional obligations (whether in the pure or the fact-regarding sense) I am tempted to speak of hypothetical and categorical imperatives. These terms should be released from their Kantian grip.

  20. This formal translation works almost perfectly. However, I should emphasize that it does not help interpreting ranking theory. Its interpretation as an account of belief stands by its own and is orthogonal to that of probability theory.

  21. In July 2015, Franz Huber has suggested essentially the same formula to me in personal communication. His term for νκ(A) is ‘anticipated regret’—‘regret’ because ν expresses only negative utilities, as it were, and ‘anticipated’ because he thinks that ‘expected’ is too firmly associated with probability.

  22. Observe that Definition 3 of epistemic conditionalization essentially refers to the arithmetics of ranks.

  23. This distinction was introduced already by Ross (1930). It has become common to speak of pro tanto duties instead of prima facie duties (or moral reasons, etc.).

  24. This point also reflects my above remarks about facts and beliefs. In our context, “all facts considered” can only mean “all beliefs considered”.

  25. Hence, all-things-considered obligations may conform to standard deontic logic. Normative ranking functions do so as well, and hence they must be understood in this way, too.

  26. See also my extensive ranking-theoretic account of ceteris paribus conditions in Spohn (2014).

  27. There may even be a direct relation between facts and norms blurring their distinction. (I am grateful to a reviewer for raising this issue.) We expect people to conform to the norms. That is, we expect that only permissible things happen; and the more strictly something is forbidden, the more firmly we disbelieve that it takes place. In the dogs example, e.g., the condition that there is a dog seems epistemically deviant only because it is normatively deviant and hence unexpected. The inference may be even reversed. When something occurs, it was presumably admissible, and when something doesn’t occur, maybe that is so because it is inadmissible. Now, the latter is dangerously close to a rejection of Hume’s Thesis and to Leibniz’ claim that the actual world is the best of all worlds (according to God’s proper standards). I admit that both inferences have some justification. However, they clearly are defeasible inferences, and the second is much weaker than the first. And they are relatively plausible only with respect to human actions, and the less plausible, the farther we move away from human influence. If it ought to rain, there is no way to infer that it will rain; the reverse would be even worse. There is a general simple explanation why the inference is sometimes plausible. We simply expect our fellows to respect the norms (at least if the norms are publicly known and not my idiosyncratic ones), and reversely, if we observe a behavioral regularity within our community without natural explanation, then it is presumably a normative rule. However, this does not reflect a general logical point, as we pursue it here. It is rather based on a special empirical claim, namely the human receptivity for norms. Therefore, the issue is besides our present interests, even though it would deserve getting developed.

  28. Note that the fact that ψ is a necessary condition of φ could as well be formalized by ¬ψ ⊳d ¬φ. As is well known, the two formalizations are not equivalent. Only our choice yields a promising inference.

References

  • Alchourrón, C. E., & Bulygin, E. (1971). Normative systems. Wien: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón, C. E., & Makinson, D. (1981). Hierarchies of regulations and their logic. In R. Hilpinen (Ed.), New studies on deontic logic (pp. 123–148). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beltrán, J. F., & Ratti, G. B. (Eds.). (2012). The logic of legal requirements. Essays on defeasibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carmo, J., & Jones, Andrew J. L. (2002). Deontic logic and contrary-to-duties. In D. Gabbay & P. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 8, pp. 265–343). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1963). Contrary-to-duty imperatives and deontic logic. Analysis,24, 33–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. Jonathan. (1977). The probable and the provable. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwiche, A., & Pearl, J. (1997). On the logic of iterated belief revision. Artificial Intelligence,89, 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuhrmann, A. (2017). Deontic modals: Why abandon the default approach. Erkenntnis,82, 1351–1365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux. Modeling the dynamics of epistemic states. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giang, P. H., & Shenoy, P. P. (2000). A qualitative linear utility theory for Spohn’s theory of epistemic beliefs. In C. Boutilier & M. Goldszmidt (Eds.), Uncertainty in artificial intelligence (Vol. 16, pp. 220–229). San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goble, L. (2013). Prima facie norms, normative conflicts, and dilemmas. In D. Gabbay, et al. (Eds.), Handbook of deontic logic and normative systems (pp. 241–351). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldszmidt, M., & Pearl, J. (1991). System Z+: A formalism for reasoning with variable strength defaults. In Proceedings of AAAI-91, Anaheim, CA (pp. 394–404).

  • Hansson, B. (1969). An analysis of some deontic logics. Noûs 3, 373–398, reprinted in: R. Hilpinen (ed.) (1971), Deontic logic: introductory and systematic readings, Dordrecht (pp. 121–147).

  • Hansson, S. O. (1999). A textbook of belief dynamics. Theory change and database updating. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hild, M., & Spohn, W. (2008). The measurement of ranks and the laws of iterated contraction. Artificial Intelligence,172, 1195–1218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. F. (2012). Reasons as defaults. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2007). The consistency argument for ranking functions. Studia Logica,86, 299–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2014). New foundations for conditionals. Synthese,191, 2167–2193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1965). The logic of decision (2nd ed. 1983). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Jones, A. J. I., & Pörn, I. (1985). Ideality, sub-ideality and deontic logic. Synthese,65, 275–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kern-Isberner, G. (2004). A thorough axiomatization of a principle of conditional preservation in belief revision. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence,40, 127–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. The Philosophical Review,85, 297–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B., & Belzer, M. (1983). Dyadic deontic detachment. Synthese,54, 295–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. Duncan, & Raiffa, H. (1957). Games and decisions. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merin, A. (1996). Die Relevanz der Relevanz. Fallstudie zur Semantik der englischen Konjunktion ‘but’, Habilitationsschrift, University of Stuttgart 1996. Distributed as Arbeitsberichte des SFB 340, Nr. 142, Universities of Stuttgart and Tübingen, 1999.

  • Merin, A. (2006). Decision theory of rhetoric. Mimeograph: University of Konstanz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Modgil, S. J., & Prakken, H. (2013). A general account of argumentation with preferences. Artificial Intelligence 195, 361–397. (A corrected version is available at: http://www.staff.science.uu.nl/~prakk101/corraij13.html.

  • Nute, D. (Ed.). (1997). Defeasible deontic logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (1990). System Z: A natural ordering of defaults with tractable applications to default reasoning. In R. Parikh (Ed.), Proceedings TARK-90 (pp. 121–135). San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigden, C. R. (Ed.). (2010). Hume on is and ought. Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1987). Defeasible reasoning. Cognitive Science,11, 481–518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1995). Cognitive carpentry: A blueprint for how to build a person. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. (2010). An abstract framework for argumentation with structured arguments. Argument and Computation,1, 93–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H., & Sergot, M. J. (1996). Contrary-to-duty obligations. Studia Logica,57, 91–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H., & Sergot, M. J. (1997). Dyadic deontic logic and contrary-to-duty obligations. In Nute (1997) (pp. 223–262).

  • Raidl, E. (2018). Completeness for counter-doxa conditionals—Using ranking semantics. Review of Symbolic Logic. https://doi.org/10.1017/s1755020318000199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rott, H. (2001). Change, choice and inference: A study of belief revision and nonmonotonic reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rott, H. (2011). Reapproaching Ramsey: Conditionals and iterated belief change in the spirit of AGM. Journal of Philosophical Logic,40, 155–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartor, G. (2018). Defeasibility in law. In G. Bongiovanni, G. Postema, A. Rotolo, G. Sartor, C. Valentini, & D. Walton (Eds.), Handbook of legal reasoning and argumentation. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (1997). The is-ought problem. A study in philosophical logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (1975). An analysis of Hansson’s dyadic deontic logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic,4, 237–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2002). A brief comparison of Pollock’s defeasible reasoning and ranking functions. Synthese,131, 39–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2009). A survey of ranking theory. In F. Huber & C. Schmidt-Petri (Eds.), Degrees of belief. An anthology (pp. 185–228). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2012). The laws of belief. Ranking theory and its philosophical applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2014). The epistemic account of ceteris paribus conditions. European Journal for the Philosophy of Science,4, 385–408.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2015). Conditionals: A unified ranking-theoretic perspective. In Philosophers’ Imprints 15(1), 1–30; see: http://quod.lib.umich.edu/p/phimp/3521354.0015.001/.

  • Spohn, W. (2017). Knightian uncertainty meets ranking theory. Homo Oeconomicus,34, 293–311.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to three fortunately very critical reviewers for many most helpful commentaries and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wolfgang Spohn.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Spohn, W. Defeasible normative reasoning. Synthese 197, 1391–1428 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02083-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02083-2

Keywords

Navigation