Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 195, Issue 7, pp 3097–3119 | Cite as

Two directions for teleology: naturalism and idealism

  • Andrew Cooper
Article

Abstract

Philosophers of biology claim that function talk is consistent with naturalism. Yet recent work in biology places new pressure on this claim. An increasing number of biologists propose that the existence of functions depends on the organisation of systems. While systems are part of the domain studied by physics, they are capable of interacting with this domain through organising principles. This is to say that a full account of biological function requires teleology. Does naturalism preclude reference to teleological causes? Or are organised systems precisely a naturalised form of teleology? In this paper I suggest that the biology of organised systems reveals several contradictions in the main philosophical conceptions of naturalism. To integrate organised systems with naturalism’s basic assumptions—that there is no theory-independent view for metaphysics, and that nature is intelligible—I propose an idealist solution.

Keywords

Naturalism Evolutionary biology Function Idealism Kant 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Markus Gabriel, Andy Jones, Tim Smartt, Paul Redding, and Yarran Hominh for their insightful discussion and invaluable feedback on early drafts of this paper. I would also like to thank my anonymous reviewers for their detailed and stimulating comments, which helped improve this paper immensely.

References

  1. Aristotle. (1984). The complete works of Aristotle. In Barnes, J. (Ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Amundson, R., & Lander, G. (1994). Function without purpose: The uses of causal role function in evolutionary biology. Biology and Philosophy, 9, 443–469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Blackburn, S. (1993). Realism, quasi, or queasy. In J. Haldane & C. Wright (Eds.), Reality, representation, and projection (pp. 365–384). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Barbieri, M. (2008). Biosemantics: A new understanding of life. Naturwissenschaften, 95, 577–599.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bernard, C. (1865). Introduction à l’étude de la medicine expérimentale. Paris: Baillière.Google Scholar
  6. Breitenbach, A. (2009). Teleology in biology: A Kantian perspective. Kant Yearbook, 1, 31–56.Google Scholar
  7. Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 11, 20–44.Google Scholar
  8. Chalmers, D. (1997). The conscious mind. In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Chase, M. (2011). Teleology and final causation in Aristotle and in contemporary science. Dialogue, 50, 511–536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Cooper, A. (2017). Kant and experimental philosophy. British Journal for the History of Philosophy. doi: 10.1080/09608788.2016.1268996.
  11. Cummins, R. (1975). Functional Analysis. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 741–765.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. De Caro, M., & Macarthur, D. (Eds.). (2008). Naturalism in question. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Dupré, J. (1993). The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Dupré, J. (2001). Human nature and the limits of science. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Gabriel, M. (2011). Transcendental Ontology. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
  16. Ginsborg, H. (2006). Kant’s biological teleology and its philosophical significance. In G. Bird (Ed.), A companion to Kant (pp. 455–469). Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Gotthelf, A. (2012). Teleology, first principles, and scientific method in Aristotle’s biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Guyer, P. (2001). Organism and the Unity of Science. In E. Watkins (Ed.), Kant and the sciences (pp. 259–281). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Henning, B. (2009). The four causes. The Journal of Philosophy, 106, 137–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Kant, I. (1999). Critique of pure reason (P. Guyer & A. Wood, Trans.) . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Kant, I. (2000a). Critique of the power of judgment (P. Guyer, Trans.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Kant, I. (2000b). Of the different human races [1777]. In R. Bernasconi (Ed.), The idea of race (pp. 8–22). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  23. Kant, I. (2004). Metaphysical foundations of natural science (M. Friedman Trans. & Ed.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Kamimura, Y., & Matsuo, Y. (2001). A ‘spare’ compensates for the risk of destruction of the elongated penis of earwigs. Naturwisschaften, 88, 468–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kauffman, S. (2013). Evolution beyond Newton, Darwin, and Entailing law. In B. Henning & A. Scarfe (Eds.). Beyond mechanism: Putting life back into biology. Lanham: Lexington Books: 1–24.Google Scholar
  26. Kitcher, Philip. (1986). ‘Projecting the order of nature.’ In R. Butts (Ed.), Kant’s Philosophy of Physical Science (pp. 201–238). Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  27. Kreines, J. (2005). The inexplicability of Kant’s Naturzweck: Kant on teleology, explanation and biology. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 87, 270–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Leiter, B., & Weisberg, M. (2012). Do you only have a brain? On Thomas Nagel. The Nation October 22.Google Scholar
  29. Lewens, T. (2004). Organisms and artifacts: Design in nature and elsewhere. Massachusetts: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Massimi, M. (2008). Why there are no ready-made phenomena: What philosophers of science should learn from Kant. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 63, 1–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Mayr, E. (1988). Toward a new philosophy of biology: Observations of an evolutionist. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Mayr, E. (2004). What Makes Biology Unique? Considerations on the Autonomy of a Scientific Discipline. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. McLaughlin, P. (1990). Kant’s critique of teleology in biological explanation: Antinomy and teleology. New York: Lewiston.Google Scholar
  34. Millikan, R. (1984). Thought, language, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  35. Moreno, A., & Mossio, M. (2015). Biological autonomy: A philosophical and theoretical enquiry. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Mossio, M., & Bich, L. (2014). What makes biological causation teleological? Synthese. doi: 10.1007/s11229-014-0594-z.
  37. Mossio, M., & Saborido, C. (2016). Functions, organisation, and etiology. A reply to Artiga and Martinez. Acta Biotheoretica, 64, 263–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and cosmos. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Piaget, J. (1967). Biologie et connaissance. Paris: Gallimard.Google Scholar
  40. Price, H. (1997). Naturalism and the fate of the M-worlds. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 71, 247–267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Price, H. (2011). Naturalism without mirrors. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Redding, P. (2010). Two directions for analytic Kantianism: Naturalism and idealism. In M. De Caro & D. Macarthur (Eds.), Naturalism and Normativity. New York: Columbia University Press: 263-285.Google Scholar
  43. Richards, R. (2000). Kant and Blumenbach on the Bildungstrieb: A historical misunderstanding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences, 31, 11–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Roqué, A. (1985). Self-organisation: Kant’s concept of teleology and modern chemistry. The Review of Metaphysics, 39, 107–135.Google Scholar
  45. Rosen, R. (1972). Some relational cell models: The metabolism-repair systems. Foundations of mathematical biology (Vol. 2, pp. 217–253). New York: Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Schelling, F. (2007). The grounding of positive philosophy: The Berlin Lectures B. Matthews (Ed.), SUNY Press, Albany.Google Scholar
  47. Schwenk, K. (2000). Tetrapod feeding in the context of vertebrate morphology. In K. Schwenk (Ed.), Feeding: Form, function, and evolution in tetrapod vertebrates. San Diego: Academic Press: 3-20.Google Scholar
  48. Sober, E. (2000). Philosophy of Biology. Colorado: Westview Press.Google Scholar
  49. Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. New Haven: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  50. Weber, A., & Verela, F. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Zammito, J. (2006). Teleology then and now: The question of Kant’s relevance for contemporary controversies over function in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Medical Sciences, 37, 748–770.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of DurhamDurhamUK

Personalised recommendations