Advertisement

Social Justice Research

, Volume 31, Issue 1, pp 85–111 | Cite as

Contributive Justice: An Exploration of a Wider Provision of Meaningful Work

Article

Abstract

Extreme inequality of opportunity leads to a number of social tensions, inefficiencies and injustices. One issue of increasing concern is the effect inequality is having on people’s fair chances of attaining meaningful work, thus limiting opportunities to make a significant positive contribution to society and reducing the chances of living a flourishing life and developing their potential. On a global scale, we can observe an increasingly uneven provision of meaningful work, raising a series of ethical concerns that need detailed examination. The aim of this article is to explore the potential of a normative framework based upon the idea of contributive justice to defend a fairer provision of meaningful work.

Keywords

Labour conditions Capabilities Deskilling Human flourishing Social justice Knowledge economy Poverty 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the participants at workshops in Mexico City, Budapest and Campinas, Isabella Trifan, Georges Félix, the journal’s editor and the anonymous reviewers for valuable feedback and Michael Pockley also for careful language editing on earlier versions of this article.

Funding

This study was funded by a postdoctoral fellowship UNAM-DGAPA [National Autonomous University of Mexico, no grant numbers are given] and a postdoctoral fellowship by FONDECYT/CONICYT No. 3170068.

Compliance with Ethical Standards

Conflict of interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by the author.

References

  1. Anderson, E. (2015). Equality and freedom in the workplace: Recovering republican insights. Social Philosophy and Policy, 31(02), 48–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Arneson, R. (1987). Meaningful work and market socialism. Ethics, 97(3), 517–545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Arneson, R. (2009). Meaningful work and market socialism revisited. Analyse & Kritik, 31(1), 139–151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Arneson, R. (2015). Equality of opportunity. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition).Google Scholar
  5. Arnold, S. (2012). The difference principle at work. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20(1), 94–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Barry, B. (1982). Humanity and justice in global perspective. Nomos, 24, 219–252.Google Scholar
  7. Bascara, R. (2016). Compatriot partiality and cosmopolitan justice: Can we justify compatriot partiality within the cosmopolitan framework? Etikk i praksis-Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics, 10(2), 27–39.Google Scholar
  8. Behrensen, M., & Kaliarnta, S. (2017). Sick and tired: Depression in the margins of academic philosophy. Topoi, 36(2), 355–364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Bowie, N. E. (1998). A Kantian theory of meaningful work. Journal of Business Ethics, 17(9), 1083–1092.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Brennan, J. (2011). The right to a competent electorate. The Philosophical Quarterly, 61(245), 700–724.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Britz, J. J. (2008). Making the global information society good: A social justice perspective on the ethical dimensions of the global information society. Journal of the Association for Information Science and Technology, 59(7), 1171–1183.Google Scholar
  12. Britz, J. J., & Lipinski, T. A. (2001). Indigenous knowledge: A moral reflection on current legal concepts of intellectual property. Libri, 51(4), 234–246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Britz, J. J., & Lor, P. (2004). A moral reflection on the digitization of Africa’s documentary heritage. IFLA Journal, 30(3), 216–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Burchell, B., Sehnbruch, K., Piasna, A., & Agloni, N. (2014). The quality of employment and decent work: Definitions, methodologies, and ongoing debates. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 38(2), 459–477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Calder, G. (2016). Family autonomy and class fate. Symposion, 3(2), 131–149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Campesina, Via. (1996). The right to produce and access land. Rome: Via Campesina.Google Scholar
  17. Claassen, R. (2012). Temporal autonomy in a laboring society. Inquiry, 55(5), 543–562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Claassen, R. (2015). The capability to hold property. Journal of Human Development and Capabilities, 16(2), 220–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Danaher, J. (2017). Will life be worth living in a world without work? Technological unemployment and the meaning of life. Science and Engineering Ethics, 23(1), 41–64.CrossRefPubMedGoogle Scholar
  20. Deranty, J. P., & MacMillan, C. (2012). The ILO’s Decent Work initiative: Suggestions for an extension of the notion of “decent work”. Journal of Social Philosophy, 43(4), 386–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Dieterlen, P. (2003). La pobreza: un estudio filosófico. México, DF: Fondo de Cultura Económica.Google Scholar
  22. Dietsch, P. (2008). Distributive lessons from division of labour. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 5(1), 96–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Dodds, W. K. (2005). The commons, game theory and aspects of human nature that may allow conservation of global resources. Environmental Values, 14, 411–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Elster, J. (1986). Self-realization in work and politics: The Marxist conception of the good life. Social Philosophy and Policy, 3(02), 97–126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Espindola, J., & Vaca, M. (2014). The problem of historical rectification for Rawlsian theory. Res Publica, 20(3), 227–243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Frischmann, B. M. (2012). Infrastructure: The social value of shared resources. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Gheaus, A., & Herzog, L. (2016). The goods of work (other than money!). Journal of Social Philosophy, 47(1), 70–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Gilabert, P. (2015). The socialist principle “from each according to their abilities, to each according to their needs”. Journal of Social Philosophy, 46(2), 197–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Gilabert, P. (2016). Labor human rights and human dignity. Philosophy & Social Criticism, 42(1), 171–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Gilabert, P. (forthcoming). Dignity at work. In H. Collins, G. Lester, & V. Mantouvlou (Eds.), Philosophical foundations of labour law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Gomberg, P. (1995). Against competitive equal opportunity. Journal of Social Philosophy, 26(3), 59–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Gomberg, P. (2007). How to make opportunity equal. New York: Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Gomberg, P. (2010). Dilemmas of Rawlsian opportunity. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 40(1), 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Gomberg, P. (2016). Why distributive justice is impossible but contributive justice would work. Science & Society, 80(1), 31–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Gomberg, P. (2017). Workers without rights. Symposion, 4(1), 49–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Gourevitch, A. (2016). Quitting work but not the job: Liberty and the right to strike. Perspectives on Politics, 14(02), 307–323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Graeber, D. (2006). Turning modes of production inside out or, Why capitalism is a transformation of slavery. Critique of Anthropology, 26(1), 61–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Graeber, D. (2013). On the phenomenon of bullshit jobs. Strike! Magazine, August (pp. 10–11).Google Scholar
  40. Hardwig, J. (2015). Ownership, possession, and consumption: On the limits of rational consumption. Journal of Social Philosophy, 46(3), 281–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Hasan, R. (2015). Rawls on meaningful work and freedom. Social Theory and Practice, 41(3), 477–504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Herzog, L. (2011). Wer Sind Wir, Wenn Wir Arbeiten? Soziale Identität Im Markt Bei Smith Und Hegel. Deutsche Zeitschrift Für Philosophie, 59(6), 835–852.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Hsieh, N. H. (2009). Justice at work: Arguing for property-owning democracy. Journal of Social Philosophy, 40(3), 397–411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Kates, M. (2015). The ethics of sweatshops and the limits of choice. Business Ethics Quarterly, 25(2), 191–212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Keat, R. (2009). Anti-perfectionism, market economies and the right to meaningful work. Analyse & Kritik, 31(1), 121–138.Google Scholar
  46. Kelbessa, W. (2013). Indigenous knowledge and its contribution to biodiversity conservation. International Social Science Journal, 64(211–212), 143–152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Kohn, M. L., & Schooler, C. (1982). Job conditions and personality: A longitudinal assessment of their reciprocal effects. American Journal of Sociology, 87(6), 1257–1286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Kumar, M., & Santoro, D. (2014). Being bound to fail. How epistemic injustice fails educational opportunities. https://imera.univ-amu.fr/sites/imera.univamu.fr/file/being_bound_to_fail.how_epistemic_injustice_fails_educational_opportunities_draft_0.pdf. Accessed 6 Oct 2017.
  49. Lamont, J., & Favor, C. (2013). Distributive Justice. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (spring 2013 edition). Stanford: Stanford University.Google Scholar
  50. Lane, R. E. (1991). The market experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Lepisto, D. A., & Pratt, M. G. (2017). Meaningful work as realization and justification: Toward a dual conceptualization. Organizational Psychology Review, 7(2), 99–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Lips-Wiersma, M., & Morris, L. (2009). Discriminating between ‘meaningful work’ and the ‘management of meaning’. Journal of Business Ethics, 88(3), 491–511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Louwaars, N. (2007). Seeds of confusion: The impact of policies on seed systems. Ph.D. thesis, Wageningen Universiteit.Google Scholar
  54. Lucas, K. (2015). Workplace dignity: Communicating inherent, earned, and remediated dignity. Journal of Management Studies, 52(5), 621–646.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. May, D. R., Li, C., Mencl, J., & Huang, C.-C. (2014). The ethics of meaningful work: Types and magnitude of job-related harm and the ethical decision-making process. Journal of Business Ethics, 121(4), 651–669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Mijs, J. J. (2016). The unfulfillable promise of meritocracy: Three lessons and their implications for justice in education. Social Justice Research, 29(1), 14–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Moellendorf, D. (2006). Equality of opportunity globalized. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, 19, 301–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Murnion, W. E. (1989). The ideology of social justice in economic justice for all. Journal of Business Ethics, 8(11), 847–854.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Narisada, A. (2017). Socioeconomic status and the relationship between under-reward and distress: Buffering-resource or status-disconfirmation? Social Justice Research, 30(3), 191–220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  61. Offe, C. (2009). Basic income and the labor contract. Analyse & Kritik, 31(1), 49–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Ooms, G. (2010). Why the west is perceived as being unworthy of cooperation. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 38(3), 594–613.CrossRefPubMedGoogle Scholar
  63. Otsuka, M. (2008). Freedom of occupational choice. Ratio, 21(4), 440–453.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Parr, T. (2015). From philanthropy to philanthropists. In B. Morvaridi (Ed.), New philanthropy and social justice: Debating the conceptual and policy discourse (pp. 64–77). Bristol: Policy Press.Google Scholar
  65. Pogge, T. W. (2008). World poverty and human rights: Cosmopolitan responsibilities and reforms (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
  66. Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (Rev. edn.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  67. Robeyns, I. (2011). The capability approach. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2011 edition). Stanford: Stanford University.Google Scholar
  68. Roessler, B. (2012). Meaningful work: Arguments from autonomy. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20(1), 71–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Sarkin, J., & Koenig, M. (2011). Developing the right to work: Intersecting and dialoguing human rights and economic policy. Human Rights Quarterly, 33(1), 1–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Sayer, A. (1989). Postfordism in question. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 13(4), 666–695.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Sayer, A. (2009). Contributive justice and meaningful work. Res Publica, 15, 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Sayer, A. (2011). Habitus, work and contributive justice. Sociology, 45(1), 7–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. Sayer, A. (2012). Capabilities, contributive injustice and unequal divisions of labour. Journal of Human Development and Capabilities, 13(4), 580–596.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Schaff, K. P. (2012). Democratic rights in the workplace. Inquiry, 55(4), 386–404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Schwartz, A. (1982). Meaningful work. Ethics, 92(4), 634–646.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Schweiger, G. (2013). Recognition and social exclusion. A recognition-theoretical exploration of poverty in Europe. Ethical Perspectives, 20(4), 529–554.Google Scholar
  77. Sen, A. (2001). Development as freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  78. Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  79. Sennett, R. (2008). The craftsman. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  80. Shaheed, F. (2012). Report of the Special Rapporteur in the field of cultural rights. United Nations (A/HRC/20/26).Google Scholar
  81. Shaver, L. (2010). The right to science and culture. Wisconsin Law Review, 121, 121–184.Google Scholar
  82. Shiffrin, S. V. (2003). Race, labor, and the fair equality of opportunity principle. Fordham Law Review, 72, 1643–1675.Google Scholar
  83. Sison, A. J. G., Ferrero, I., & Guitián, G. (2016). Human dignity and the dignity of work: Insights from Catholic Social Teaching. Business Ethics Quarterly.Google Scholar
  84. Sklair, L. (2016). The transnational capitalist class, social movements, and alternatives to capitalist globalization. International Critical Thought, 6(3), 329–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Snyder, J. (2010). Exploitation and sweatshop labor: Perspectives and issues. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(02), 187–213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. Sparrow, R., & Goodin, R. E. (2001). The competition of ideas: Market or garden? Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 4(2), 45–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  87. Spencer, D. A. (2013). Promoting high quality work: Obstacles and opportunities. Journal of Business Ethics, 114(3), 583–597.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. Stanczyk, L. (2012). Productive justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 40(2), 144–164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  89. Steger, M. F. (2017). Creating meaning and purpose at work. In: The Wiley Blackwell handbook of the psychology of positivity and strengths-based approaches at work (pp. 60–81). Hoboken: Wiley.Google Scholar
  90. Sturn, R. (2009). Volenti non fit iniuria? Contract freedom and labor market institutions. Analyse und Kritik, 31(1), 81–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  91. Tablan, F. (2015). Catholic social teachings: Toward a meaningful work. Journal of Business Ethics, 128(2), 291–303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  92. Taka, I., & Foglia, W. D. (1994). Ethical aspects of “Japanese leadership style”. Journal of Business Ethics, 13(2), 135–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  93. Taylor, C. (1994). The politics of recognition. In A. Gutmann (Ed.), Multiculturalism: Examining the politics of recognition (pp. 25–74). Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  94. Taylor, R. (2004). Self-realization and the priority of fair equality of opportunity. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 1(3), 333–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  95. Terzi, L. (2007). The capability to be educated. In M. Walker & E. Unterhalter (Eds.), Amartya Sen’s capability approach and social justice in education (pp. 25–43). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  96. Tight, M. (1998). Lifelong learning: Opportunity or compulsion? British Journal of Educational Studies, 46(3), 251–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  97. United States Catholic Bishops. (1997). Economic justice for all: Pastoral letter on Catholic Social Teaching and the U.S. economy. Washington, DC: United States Conference of Catholic Bishops.Google Scholar
  98. Valente, R. R., & Berry, B. J. (2016). Working hours and life satisfaction: A cross-cultural comparison of Latin America and the United States. Journal of Happiness Studies, 17(3), 1173–1204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  99. Van Parijs, P. (1997). Real freedom for all: What (if anything) can justify capitalism?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  100. Veltman, A. (2016). Meaningful work. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  101. Walsh, A. J. (1994). Meaningful work as a distributive good. The Southern journal of philosophy, 32(2), 233–250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  102. Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice: A defense of pluralism and equality. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  103. Wolf, S. (2010). Meaning in life and why it matters. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  104. Wolff, J. (2004). Training, perfectionism and fairness. Journal of applied philosophy, 21(3), 285–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  105. Yeoman, R. (2014). Conceptualising meaningful work as a fundamental human need. Journal of Business Ethics, 125(2), 235–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  106. Young, I. M. (2004). Responsibility and global labor justice. Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(4), 365–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  107. Ziegler, J. (2011a). Destruction massive: Géopolitique de la faim. Paris: Seuil.Google Scholar
  108. Ziegler, R. (2011b). Fair competition of ideas. Paper presented at the responsible innovation conference, The Hague, April 18–19, 2011.Google Scholar
  109. Timmermann, C., & Félix, G. F. (2015). Agroecology as a vehicle for contributive justice. Agriculture and Human Values, 32(3), 523–538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  110. Timmermann, C. (2014). Sharing in or benefiting from scientific advancement? Science and Engineering Ethics, 20(1), 111–133.CrossRefPubMedGoogle Scholar
  111. Timmermann, C., & van den Belt, H. (2012). Global justice considerations for a proposed “climate impact fund”. Public Reason, 4(1–2), 182–196.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Centro Interdisciplinario de Estudios en BioéticaUniversidad de ChileSantiagoChile
  2. 2.Instituto de Estudios InternacionalesUniversidad de ChileSantiagoChile

Personalised recommendations