Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Energy, Metaphysics, and Space: Ernst Mach’s Interpretation of Energy Conservation as the Principle of Causality

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper discusses Ernst Mach’s interpretation of the principle of energy conservation (EC) in the context of the development of energy concepts and ideas about causality in nineteenth-century physics and theory of science. In doing this, it focuses on the close relationship between causality, energy conservation and space in Mach’s antireductionist view of science. Mach expounds his thesis about EC in his first historical-epistemological essay, Die Geschichte und die Wurzel des Satzes von der Erhaltung der Arbeit (1872): far from being a new principle, it is used from the early beginnings of mechanics independently from other principles; in fact, EC is a pre-mechanical principle which is generally applied in investigating nature: it is, indeed, nothing but a form of the principle of causality. The paper focuses on the scientific-historical premises and philosophical underpinnings of Mach’s thesis, beginning with the classic debate on the validity and limits of the notion of cause by Hume, Kant, and Helmholtz. Such reference also implies a discussion of the relationship between causality on the one hand and space and time on the other. This connection plays a major role for Mach, and in the final paragraphs its importance is argued in order to understand his antireductionist perspective, i.e. the rejection of any attempt to give an ultimate explanation of the world via reduction of nature to one fundamental set of phenomena.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On Helmholtz’s attitude towards the terminological shift Kraft/Energie and for a discussion of Tyndall’s translation, see Elkana (1974, pp. 122–137).

  2. About the relationship between Mach and Carus see Holton (1993, pp. 4–7).

  3. It is also remarkable that Mach (1895) does not mention the view expressed by Planck (1887, p. 139), that EC actually consists of two parts: the impossibility to create work from nothing and the impossibility to destroy work without any other effect. Planck argues that the two assumptions are logically independent. This could obviously imply a potential criticism of Mach’s position, but Mach does not seem to have taken it into account in the subsequent presentations of his argument. In the Preface to the second edition of the Erhaltung der Arbeit (1909) he only complains that Planck has paid scanty attention to his book (Mach 1872, p. V; Engl. transl., p. 10).

  4. According to Mach (1872, p. 39; Engl. transl., p. 65), an application of the principle of sufficient reason can be exemplified in this way: “Let us take a straight horizontal bar, which we support in its middle and at both ends of each we hang equal weights. Then we perceive at once that equilibrium must subsist, because there is no reason why the bar should turn in one direction rather than in the other”.

  5. See on this Guzzardi (2005, pp. 17–35).

  6. In the referred Sect. 8 of the “Antimetaphysical Introductory Remarks” (Mach 1886, chapt. 1) Mach specifies the “monistic point of view” he had expounded in the previous paragraphs: both the Self and the outer World are made of the same elements which only differ in their mutual connection. They are sensations when they present themselves in a physio-psychological connection; but “in another functional relation they are at the same time physical objects”. So the Self and the World are not conflicting terms, for “all elements […] form a single coherent mass [zusammenhängende Masse]” (Mach 1886, pp. 11–14; see also Mach 1905, pp. 8–9, Engl. transl., pp. 6–7: “The mental and physical have common elements and are not in stark opposition as commonly supposed”).

  7. On the relationship between Mach and Hume see also Hamilton 1990; Guzzardi 2010, pp. 63–67. Banks (2003, pp. 42–44) finds in Mach’s function concept some important theoretical differences between Hume’s and Mach’s empiricism; nevertheless, these don’t seem to affect the notion of causality as a regulative principle.

  8. See also other similar expressions implying temporality, such as “were the power or energy of any cause discoverable by the mind, we could foresee the effect” (Hume 1748, p. 51; emphasis added), “one event follows another” and “the only immediate utility of all sciences, is to teach us, how to control and regulate future events by their causes” (Hume 1748, p. 60; emphasis added), etc.

  9. On Kant’s relationship with Hume regarding the Second Analogy, see Ward (1986).

  10. There is of course a connection between both principle. See Ward (2001), pp. 405–406.

  11. On Kant’s influence over Helmholtz’s On the Conservation of Force, with particular reference to the notion of regulative principles, see Hyder (2009, pp. 76–88).

  12. “The first product of the thoughtful comprehension of the phenomena is lawfulness […]. We acknowledge it as an existence enduring independent of the way in which we form representations, and call it the cause, i.e. that which primarily remains and endures behind what alternates […]. Inasmuch as we then acknowledge the law to be something compelling our perception and the course of natural processes […] we call it ‘force’”. See Helmholtz (1977, p. 139).

  13. On Kant’s view of force as a cause see the sections “Dynamics” and “Mechanics” in Kant (1786), in particular A31–A37 and A119, “Lehrsatz 3”). See also Kant (1787, p. 593: A649/B677): note that in the English translation the crucial passage: “[die] Kausalität einer Substanz, welche Kraft [force] genannt wird” is rendered as: “the causality of a substance, which is called ‘power’”. On the development of Helmholtz’s views on causality, see Schiemann (1997, pp. 259–264, 369–374).

  14. Taking account of Helmholtz’s dislike for mere mathematical expedients in physical equations, it is important here to recognize that in the subsequent equation the q a ’s are Lagrangian multipliers, i.e. they are endowed with a clear physical meaning. On their physical significance see Lanczos (1970), pp. 83–86. On Helmholtz’s inclination to introduce “physically sound concepts” (logically) before their mathematical counterparts, see Helmholtz (1854, in particular p. 82); for useful comments on this tendency, see Bevilacqua (1993, p. 328), and Hyder (2009, pp. 78–79).

  15. For a presentation of the derivation of EC from Hamilton’s principle in modern terms, which happens to be close to Helmholtz’s, see Lanczos (1970, pp. 111–122).

  16. I cannot agree with Michael Heidelberger, that Helmholtz found in the principle of the least action “a more general law into which he could embed the conservation principle” (Heidelberger 1993, p. 496). In fact, this seems to be literally excluded by Helmholtz himself in stating that the principle of the least action “does not applies in all cases where the constance of energy takes place [gewahrt ist]. So the latter tells us [sagt… aus] more than the former.” (Helmholtz 1886, p. 211).

  17. On technical aspects of this analogy see Banks (2003, pp. 169–171), who also briefly accounts for a number of differences between Mach and the energeticists (pp. 222–224). Mach was fully aware of possible analogies and differences at least with Ostwald. For instance, he declared in a letter on January 27th, 1902: “You may have already received the third edition of Analyse der Empfindungen […] you will find many points in common between us, and ideed, perhaps also some differences between our views. […] As a scientist, wherever we agree makes me happy; and let the philosophers live with differences” (Blackmore 1992, p. 79, emphasis in original text). For a comprehensive study on Mach and the energeticists see Neuber (2005).

  18. Jourdain’s original translation reads “is to be deduced” instead of “results”; however, ergibt sich aus is not meant here in strictly logical terms; it rather means ‘it historically results’.

  19. Note that Ostwald considered his Vorlesungen as philosophically inspired by Mach, as he stated in a letter on May 31st, 1901: “This semester under the designation Naturphilosophie I am giving a series of lectures which are essentially on the theory of knowledge, and of which my foundations for the most part I owe to you” (Blackmore 1992, p. 76).

  20. On Ostwald’s peculiar Kantian background see Moiso (1998, pp. 270–275).

  21. So Thomas McCormack, the English translator of Mach’s paper, correctly rendered Mach’s phrase as “Black’s material conception of heat” (Mach 1895, p. 53).

  22. It is worthwhile to notice that this paper, barely taken into consideration by historians and philosophers of science, shows a remarkable convergence between Mach and Boltzmann, all too often regarded as antagonists by influential books like Popper (1974, pp. 181–182) and Janik and Toulmin (1973, in particular chapter 5).

  23. Note that, like Helmholtz (1847, p. 68), Mach uses here the verb voraussetzen (presuppose) in order to qualify the law of causality. So the whole phrase, which is emphasized in the original text, reads in German: “Das Causalgesetz ist also hinreichend charakterisiert, wenn man sagt, es setzte eine Abhängigkeit der Erscheinungen von einander voraus”.

  24. Holton (1993, pp. 60–65) has questioned Mach’s correct understanding of Minkowski’s conception of space–time as a geometrical four-dimensional variety, because of Mach’s lack of the appropriate mathematical tools. It is not my aim to discuss this thesis in the present paper. It might be true that Mach’s education in mathematics was not sufficient in order to penetrate all the technical aspects for example in the case of differential geometry and topology, or even in the case of Hertz’s geometric image, as it is based upon “a differential geometry of configuration space” (Lützen 2005, p. v). But he surely could realize the significance of Bernhard Riemann’s or Felix Klein’s works and recognize the meaning and the coherence of Hertz’s efforts from the theory of electromagnetism to mechanics. Against Holton’s thesis, this is also substantiated by the fact that Mach discusses the importance of Riemann’s and Klein’s results (not to say of Hertz’s) on several occasions (e.g. Mach 1905, pp. 415–421; Engl. transl., pp. 321–327).

  25. For a critical reading of Mach on space and time see DiSalle (2002).

  26. It is to be noted that Mach developed his space conception quite independentely from Riemann, whose writing Über die Hypothesen, welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen (1868) he probably knew in 1871–1872. However, Herbart’s philosophy, particularly because of his insistence on the concept of serie (Rehie) in order to construct space, was an obvious reference shared both by Mach and Riemann. A detailed account of Mach’s relationship with Riemann is given by Banks (2003, pp. 77–90).

  27. Mach first attempt to regard the sound scale (or better, sound serie) as a one-dimensional space traces back to his ‘Herbartian’ physiological essay Zur Theorie des Gehörorgans, whose reader will find this meaningful passage: “We order sounds in a serie [Rehie]. How do we get to this? […] There are completely analogous phenomena in other sensory apparatus which have been already explained. We also order our space sensations in series, namely spatial series” (Mach 1863, p. 298). The example of the one-dimensional sound serie reappears in other works with more emphasis on space (while the concept of serie remains in the background): see Mach (1872, pp. 27, 55; Engl. transl., pp. 50–51, 87), Mach (1886, pp. 225, 227, where the serial order of sounds and the space analogy are treated separately), and Mach (1905, p. 393 and footnote 1: “My attention was drawn to this analogy [with space] while studying the organ of hearing; since then I have further developed this subject [i.e. the analogy itself]”; see also Engl. transl., pp. 302, 328).

  28. For this description of the concept of intensive magnitudes and a related discussion, see Hyder (2009, pp. 129–130). Hyder also shows that the originally Kantian distinction between intensive and extensive magnitudes came to a turning point with the emergence of the colour-space theories in the second half of the nineteenth century—a debate of which Mach was fully aware (see Mach 1905, pp. 392–395).

  29. It is remarkable that Mach ascribes the beginnings of this conception to Lagrange, who actually poses the bases of the concept of generalized co-ordinates—but to say that with Lagrange time is to be considered a fourth dimension is at least very questionable from a historical point of view. This is much more Mach’s own view than Lagrange’s.

  30. On Mach’s economic view of science in a broader context, also discussing the role of Richard Avenarius and Joseph Petzoldt, see Moiso 1998.

  31. Mach has treated this subject in various works and under many aspects. In Erkenntnis und Irrtum he describes the difference between physiological and physical space and time as follows: “As regards physiology, time and space are systems of sensations of orientation that, together with the sensations of the sensory apparatus [Sinnesempfindungen], determine the release of biologically appropriate reactions of adaptation. As regards physics, time and space are special dependences of physical elements on each other” (Mach 1905, p. 434, emphasis in original text; Engl. transl., p. 339: my translation slightly differs from the usual English translation).

  32. Leaving aside the question of Mach’s understanding of the essence and role of topology, a philosophical speculation is that the most appropriate concept of space to express Mach’s notion of causality and EC could be that of a topological space, of which the physical space, energetic relations and the causality principle are mere forms. From a historical point of view it would be of course strained to seek a translation of Mach’s insights into topology. Moreover, this would add nothing to the understanding of Mach’s science and philosophy themselves. Nevertheless, such an attempt can be philosophically interesting in the light of further developments of the very “fundamental transformation” which affected the space conception in the second half of the nineteenth century and the subsequent geometrization of physics. See e.g. Boi (1995, in particular pp. 481–484; Boi refers to Misner and Wheeler’s idea that “physics is geometry” as a development of Clifford’s “new theory of matter”).

  33. Mach would regard as mysticism a view like this: “All we agree that it makes no great difference in which of the three forms an equation is written, f (α β γ…) = 0, α = F (α β γ…), F (α β γ…) = const., and that in the last of these forms there lies no specially higher wisdom than in the others. But it is merely by this form that the law of the conservation of work differs from other laws of nature. We can easily give a similar form to any other law of nature […]. However beautiful, simple, and perspicuous much in the form of the principle [Satz] of the conservation of work looks, I cannot feel any enthusiasm for the mysticism which some people love to push forwards by means of this principle” (Mach 1872, p. 46; Engl. transl., p. 73. See also Mach 1895, p. 54, Germ. version, p. 214, where the same term Mystik/mysticism occurs).

  34. A pithy formulation of Mach’s principle is accorded to Stephen Hawking: “Matter possesses inertia only relatively to other matter in the Universe” (Hawking 1990, p. 189). For a discussion of Mach’s principle see Barbour and Pfister (1995). About the substantial equivalence of various formulation of Mach’s principle, see Bartocci and Guzzardi (2007). For Einstein’s expression of Mach’s principle, see Einstein (1916, p. 771) and Einstein (1917, p. 50). Both papers have been reprinted in chronological order in Einstein (1996).

  35. In the Preface to Hertz’s Prinzipien there was a second image which Hertz undermined: the energetic image. Hertz was well aware that the theory of energy could provide an alternative foundation for mechanics, which could solve some problems of the standard force-based mechanics. But after having enthusiastically looked at energetic concepts for some time, he became convinced that they could even lead to paradoxes, if one was willing to assume a substantial conception of energy at the basis of physics (Lützen 2005, pp. 78–79). Mach’s suspicious attitude towards energetism and the substantialist conception of energy went in the same direction.

  36. The meaning and translation of the term Fallkraft (fallforce) in this passage may be problematic. Jourdain’s original English translation as “tendency to fall” is not exactly Mayer’s original idea. In fact, in Mayer’s Bemerkungen über die Kräfte der unbelebten Natur (1842) Fallkraft is described as follows: “A cause that brings about the raising of a weight [die Hebung einer Last] is a force; its effect, the raised weight, is thus likewise a force; expressed more generally this means that the spatial difference of ponderable objects is a force; since this force brings about the fall of the body, we thus call it fallforce [Fallkraft]”. After few lines Mayer makes clear that Fallkraft is not Schwerkraft (i.e. gravitational force): “As far as one regards gravity [Schwere] as the cause of fall, one speaks of a force of gravity [Schwerkraft] and thereby confuses the concepts of force and property […]. If one calls gravity a force, one thereby imagines a cause which, without itself diminishing, produces effect, and one thereby thus entertains incorrect ideas [Vorstellungen] about the causal connection of things” (Mayer 1867, pp. 235–236; a slightly different translation of these passages is given in Caneva 1993, p. 24).

References

  • Banks, E. C. (2003). Ernst Mach’s world elements. A study in natural philosophy. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J., & Pfister, H. (Eds.). (1995). Mach’s principle. From Newton’s bucket to quantum gravity. Boston, Basel, Berlin: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartocci, C., & Guzzardi, L. (2007). Gödel e l’irrealtà del tempo: Kant, Einstein e gli universi rotanti. Lettera matematica Pristem, 62–63, 69–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bevilacqua, F. (1993). Helmholtz’s Über die Erhaltung der Kraft. In D. Cahan (Ed.), Hermann von Helmholtz and the foundations of 19th-century science (pp. 291–333). Berkeley: University of California press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackmore, J. (Ed.). (1992). Ernst Mach—A deeper look. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boi, L. (1995). Le problème mathématique de l’espace. Une quête de l’intelligible. Berlin, New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boltzmann, L. (Ed.). (1905). Entgegnung auf einen von Prof. Ostwald über das Glück gehaltenen Vortrag. In Populäre Schriften (pp. 364–378). Leipzig: Barth.

  • Caneva, K. L. (1993). Robert Mayer and the conservation of energy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DiSalle, R. (2002). Reconsidering Ernst Mach on space, time, and motion. In D. Malament (Ed.), Reading natural philosophy: Essays in the history and philosophy of science and mathematics to honor Howard Stein on his 70th birthday (pp. 167–191). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1916). Die Grundlagen der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie. Annalen der Physik, 49(1916), 769–822.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1917). Über die spezielle und die allgemeine Relativitätstheorie: Gemeinverständlich. Braunschweig: Vieweg & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1996). The collected papers of Albert Einstein, Volume 6, The Berlin years: Writings, 1914–1917. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elkana, Y. (1974). The discovery of the conservation of energy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guzzardi, L. (2005). Introduzione. In E. Mach (Ed.), Scienza tra storia e critica (pp. 13–35). Monza: Polimetrica.

  • Guzzardi, L. (2010). Lo sguardo muto delle cose. Oggettività e scienza nell’età della crisi. Milano: Raffaello Cortina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, A. (1990). Ernst Mach and the elimination of subjectivity. Ratio, 3(2), 117–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawking, S. (1990). Introductory note to 1949 and 1952. In K. Gödel (Ed.), Collected works. Volume II: Publications 19381974 (pp. 189–190). Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Heidelberger, M. (1993). Force, law, and experiment: The evolution of Helmholtz’s philosophy of science. In D. Cahan (Ed.), Hermann von Helmholtz and the foundations of 19th-century science (pp. 461–497). Berkeley: University of California press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heimann, P. M. (1974). Helmholtz and Kant. Studies in history and philosophy of science, 5(3), 205–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. von (1847). Über die Erhaltung der Kraft: Eine physikalische Abhandlung. In Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. I.1.1, Wissenschaftliche Abhandlungen: Erster Band (pp. 12–75). New edition 2006. Hildesheim: Olms-Weidmann.

  • Helmholtz, H. von (1853). On the conservation of force; a physical memoir. In J. Tyndall & W. Francis (Eds.), Scientific memoires, selected from the transactions of foreign academies of science, and from foreign journals (pp. 114–162). London: Taylor & Francis.

  • Helmholtz, H. von (1854). Erwiderung auf die Bemerkung von Herrn Clausius. In Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. I.1.1, Wissenschaftliche Abhandlungen: Erster Band (pp. 76–93). New Edition 2006. Hildesheim: Olms-Weidmann.

  • Helmholtz, H. von (1873). On the conservation of force. Introduction to a series of lectures delivered at Carlsruhe in the winter of 1862–1863. In Popular lectures on scientific subjects. Translated by E. Atkinson, with an introduction by Professor Tyndall. London: Longmans, Green & Co, 1873. (Original German edition 1896: Über die Erhaltung der Kraft. Einleitung zu einem Cyclus von Vorlesungen gehalten zu Karlsruhe im Winter 1862/63. In Gesammelte Schriften, vol. V.1, Vorträge und Reden (pp. 187–229). New Edition 2002 Hildesheim: Olms-Weidmann.).

  • Helmholtz, H. von (1886). Über die physikalische Bedeutung des Princips der kleinsten Wirkung. In Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. I.3, Wissenschaftliche Abhandlungen: Dritter Band (pp. 202–248). New Edition 2003 Hildesheim: Olms-Weidmann.

  • Helmholtz, H. von (1887). Zur Geschichte des Princips der kleinsten Action. In Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. I.3, Wissenschaftliche Abhandlungen: Dritter Band (pp. 249–263). New Edition 2003 Hildesheim: Olms-Weidmann.

  • Helmholtz, H. von (1900). Rede über die Entdeckungsgeschichte des Princips der kleinsten Action (1887). In A. Harnack (Ed.), Geschichte der Königlich-Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin (Vol. II, pp. 282–296). Berlin: Reichsdruckerei.

  • Helmholtz, H. von (1977). The facts in perception (1878). In Epistemological writings (pp. 115–163). Dordrecht-Boston: Reidel. (Original German edition: Die Thatsachen in der Wahrnehmung. In Gesammelte Schriften, vol. V.2, Vorträge und Reden: Zweiter Band (pp. 240–241). New Edition 2002 Hildesheim: Olms-Weidmann.

  • Hiebert, E. N. (1973). Ernst Mach. In Dictionary of scientific biography. (Vol. 8, pp. 595–607). New York: Scribner’s.

  • Holton, G. (1993). Science and anti-science. Cambridge,London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1740). A treatise of human understanding. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hume, D. (1748). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hyder, D. (2009). The determinate world. Berlin, New York: de Gruyter.

  • Janik, A., & Toulmin, S. (1973). Wittgenstein’s Vienna. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1783). Prolegomena to any future metaphysics that will be able to come forward as science. New York: Cambridge University Press 1997 after the original German edition Riga: Hartknoch 1783, and Karl Vorländer’s revised edition Hamburg: Meiner 1976.

  • Kant, I. (1786). Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaften. New Edition 1911 Berlin: Akademie Ausgabe.

  • Kant, I. (1787). Critique of pure reason. New York: Cambridge University Press 1998 after the original German 2nd edition. Riga: Hartknoch 1787.

  • Lanczos, C. (1970). The variational principles of mechanics (4th ed.). New York: Dover publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linsday, R. B. (1976). Applications of energy: Nineteenth century. Benchmark papers on energy, Vol. 2. Hutchinson & Ross: Dowden.

  • Lützen, J. (1999). Geometrising configurations: Heinrich Hertz and his mathematical precursors. In J. Gray (Ed.), The symbolic universe: Geometry and physics 1890–1930 (pp. 25–46). Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lützen, J. (2005). Mechanistic images in geometric form: Heinrich Hertz’s principles of mechanics. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1863). Zur Theorie des Gehörorgans. Sitzungsberichte der kaiserlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftliche Classe, 48(2), pp. 283–300.

  • Mach, E. (1866). Bemerkungen über die Entwickelung der Raumvorstellungen. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 49, 227–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1872). Die Geschichte und die Wurzel des Satzes von der Erhaltung der Arbeit. Prag: Calve. 2nd Edition 1909 Leipzig: Barth. Quoted after the English edition by P.E.B. Jourdain, History and root of the principle of the conservation of energy. Chicago: The Open Court 1911.

  • Mach, E. (1883). Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwicklung historisch-kritisch dargestellt. Leipzig: Brockhaus. 3rd edition 1897 Leipzig: Brockhaus. Quoted after the English edition by T. McCormack, The science of mechanics. 6th ed. 1960 London: The Open Court.

  • Mach, E. (1886). Die Analyse der Empfindungen und das Verhältnis des Physischen zum Psychischen. New Edition 1991 Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

  • Mach, E. (1894). Über das Prinzip der Vergleichung in der Physik. In E. Mach, Populär-wissenschaftliche Vorlesungen (pp. 266–289). 4th Edition 1910 Leipzig: Barth.

  • Mach, E. (1895). On the principle of the conservation of energy. The monist, 5, pp. 23–53. (German version: Über das Prinzip der Erhaltung der Energie. In E. Mach, Populär-wissenschaftliche Vorlesungen (pp. 167–216). 4th Edition 1910 Leipzig: Barth).

  • Mach, E. (1896). Die Principien der Wärmelehre. 3rd Edition 1919 Leipzig: Barth. English edition 1986 by B. McGuinness, Principles of the theory of heat. Dordrecht-Boston-Lancaster: Reidel.

  • Mach, E. (1905). Erkenntnis und Irrtum. Skizzen zur Psychologie der Forschung. 3rd Edition 1917 Leipzig: Barth. English edition 1976 by B. McGuinness, Knowledge and Error. Dordrecht-Boston: Reidel.

  • Mach, E. (1910). Die Leitgedanken meiner Erkenntnislehre und ihre Aufnahme durch die Zeitgenossen. Scientia. Organo internazionale di sintesi scientifica, 7(1910), 225–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, J. R. (1867). Bemerkungen über die Kräfte der unbelebten Natur (1842). In Die Mechanik der Wärme (pp. 1–12). Stuttgart: Cotta.

  • Moiso, F. (1998). Fisica, fisiologia e psicologia nel pensiero di Ernst Mach. Annuario Filosofico, 1997, 269–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neuber, M. (2005). Uneasy allies. Ostwald, Helm, Mach and their philosophies of science. In B. Görs, N. Psarros, & P. Ziche (Eds.), Wilhelm Ostwald at the crossroads of chemistry, philosophy, and media culture (pp. 47–57). Leipzig: Leipziger Universitätsverlag.

  • Ostwald, W. (1895). Die Überwindung des wissenschaftlichen Materialismus. Verhandlungen der Gesellschaft deutscher Naturforscher und Ärzte, 1(1), 155–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostwald, W. (1902). Vorlesungen über Naturphilosophie: Gehalten im Sommer 1901 an der Universität Leipzig. Leipzig: Veit & Comp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Planck, M. (1887). Das Princip der Erhaltung der Energie. Leipzig: Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1974). Unended quest. An intellectual autobiography. New Edition 1974 London and New York: Routledge.

  • Schiemann, G. (1997). Wahrheitsgewissheitsverlust. Hermann von Helmholtz’ Mechanismus im Anbruch der Moderne. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, A. (1986). On Kant’s second analogy and his reply to Hume. Kant-Studien, 77(4), 409–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, A. (2001). Kant’s first analogy of experience. Kant-Studien, 92(4), 387–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolters, G. (1991). Vorwort zum Neudruck 1985. In E. Mach (Ed.), Die Analyse der Empfindungen und das Verhältnis des Physischen zum Psychischen (pp. IX–XXIII). New Edition 1991 Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I owe a debt of gratitude to Claudio Bartocci, Fabio Bevilacqua, Giulio Giorello, and Riccardo Pozzo, who read an early version of this paper and made many useful suggestions. Finally I wish to thank three anonymous referees for their constructive comments, which helped in significantly improving the text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luca Guzzardi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Guzzardi, L. Energy, Metaphysics, and Space: Ernst Mach’s Interpretation of Energy Conservation as the Principle of Causality. Sci & Educ 23, 1269–1291 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9542-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9542-9

Keywords

Navigation