Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Temporal discounting of gains and losses of time: An experimental investigation

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper investigates “asymmetries” between non-monetary gains and losses in intertemporal choice. We considered gains and losses of spare/working time with respect to a reference duration defined in a working contract. Specifically, we elicited a behavioral model of intertemporal choice that accounts for a gain/loss-dependent discounting function and a reference-dependent utility. Additionally, we did not impose preference for the present (positive discounting) and allowed for both decreasing and increasing impatience. While our results are standard regarding the discount of money (our baseline treatment), our subjects heavily discounted gains of time. More patience was observed for losses of time and a sizable portion of subjects even exhibited negative discounting, i.e. they preferred to expedite losses of time. Our econometric estimations also reveal a much larger heterogeneity of behavior in terms of both utility and discounting for gains and losses of spare time as compared to money.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Many researchers invoke the difficulty of recruiting volunteers to participate in an experiment in which they may lose money. Furthermore, the payment of a participation fee that covers the largest loss is only feasible when small amounts of money are involved.

  2. Impatience, resulting from a strictly decreasing discounting function, implies preference for the present.

  3. This specification fits our data better than the exponential one (Section B.3 in Online Appendix B).

  4. In order to avoid any confusion between the attribute time and the delay before receipt of the outcome, we will call delay-sensitivity the parameter \(\gamma \) of the constant-sensitivity discounting function instead of time-sensitivity (Ebert and Prelec 2007).

  5. The video is available upon request.

  6. We used the absolute values of the outcomes in the presentation of the choice lists.

  7. Δ was fixed at 60 minutes for both questions on gains of time and losses of time.

  8. The experiment included a fourth treatment: losses of money. Because of the difficulties to implement real losses of money, questions in this treatment were hypothetical. In this study, we focus on incentivized choices and do not report the treatment with hypothetical losses of money.

  9. A simpler (atemporal) approach was used by Abdellaoui and Kemel (2013b) and Kemel and Travers (2016) for decision under risk.

  10. Due to the temporal nature of outcomes and the fact that subjects were interviewed successively during a period of 2 weeks, we could not select the eligible subjects at the end of the experiment.

  11. We excluded choice lists \(CL_{10}\) to \(CL_{15}\) as they are designed to measure the utility parameter.

  12. Exponential (constant) discounting can always be retrieved from the specifications considered, when \(\gamma \) is fixed to a given value. For instance, the constant-sensitivity discounting function is equivalent to the exponential discounting function when \(\gamma = 1\).

  13. To illustrate this, an individual with a concave utility function for gains of time might prefer to gain 1 hour twice at two different periods of time than to gain 2 hours at one point of time. On the other hand, an individual with a convex utility function for gains of time may prefer to group the 2 hours in one gain at a single point of time.

  14. As an illustration, the present value \(c^{*}\) of the temporal prospect that offered a gain of time of 120 minutes six months from now (120,6) was greater than 120 for 20 subjects in our sample: these individuals did not exhibit preference for the present. By imposing preference for the present \((c\leq 120\) in this example), we would obtain “corner estimates” for these individuals as they would never switch and always prefer the option (120,6) rather than any option \((c,0)\).

References

  • Abdellaoui, M., Bleichrodt, H., l’Haridon, O. (2013a). Sign-dependence in intertemporal choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 47(3), 225–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., & Kemel, E. (2013b). Eliciting prospect theory when consequences are measured in time units: “Time is not money”. Management Science, 60(7), 1844–1859.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Attema, A.E. (2012). Developments in time preference and their implications for medical decision making. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 63(10), 1388–1399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Augenblick, N., Niederle, M., Sprenger, C. (2015). Working over time: Dynamic inconsistency in real effort tasks. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 130(3), 1067–1115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, J.P., Benjamin, D.J., Chabris, C.F., Laibson, D.I. (2012). How malleable are risk preferences and loss aversion. Technical report, Harvard University Mimeo.

  • Bleichrodt, H., Rohde, K.I.M., Wakker, P.P. (2009). Non-hyperbolic time inconsistency. Games and Economic Behavior, 66(1), 27–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H., Gao, Y., Rohde, K.I.M. (2016a). A measurement of decreasing impatience for health and money. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 52(3), 213–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H., Potter van Loon, R.J.D., Prelec, D., Wakker, P.P. (2016b). Beta-Delta or Tau-Delta? A Reformulation of Quasi-hyperbolic Discounting. Unpublished Manuscript.

  • Bruhin, A., Fehr-Duda, H., Epper, T. (2010). Risk and rationality: uncovering heterogeneity in probability distortion. Econometrica, 78(4), 1375–1412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cubitt, R.P., & Read, D. (2007). Can intertemporal choice experiments elicit time preferences for consumption? Experimental Economics, 10(4), 369–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, J.E.J., & Prelec, D. (2007). The fragility of time: Time-insensitivity and valuation of the near and far future. Management Science, 53(9), 1423–1438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Estle, S.J., Green, L., Myerson, J., Holt, D.D. (2007). Discounting of monetary and directly consumable rewards. Psychological Science, 18(1), 58–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fetter, F.A. (1915). Economic principles volume 1. New York: The Century Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S., Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T. (2002). Time discounting and time preference: A critical review. Journal of Economic Literature, 40(2), 351–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ganiats, T.G., Carson, R.T., Hamm, R.M., Cantor, S.B., Sumner, W., Spann, S.J., Hagen, M.D., Miller, C. (2000). Population-based time preferences for future health outcomes. Medical Decision Making, 20(3), 263–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerber, A., & Rohde, K.I.M. (2015). Eliciting discount functions when baseline consumption changes over time. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 116, 56–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardisty, D.J., & Weber, E.U. (2009). Discounting future green: money versus the environment. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 138(3), 329–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardisty, D.J., Appelt, K.C., Weber, E.U. (2013). Good or bad, we want it now: Fixed-cost present bias for gains and losses explains magnitude asymmetries in intertemporal choice. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 26(4), 348–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ioannou, C.A., & Sadeh, J. (2016). Time preferences and risk aversion: tests on domain differences. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 53(1), 29–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemel, E., & Travers, M. (2016). Comparing attitudes toward time and toward money in experience-based decisions. Theory and Decision, 80(1), 71–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirby, K.N., & Maraković, N.N. (1995). Modeling myopic decisions: evidence for hyperbolic delay-discounting within subjects and amounts. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 64(1), 22–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T.C. (1960). Stationary ordinal utility and impatience. Econometrica, 28, 287–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laibson, D. (1997). Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112(2), 443–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. (1987). Anticipation and the valuation of delayed consumption. Economic Journal, 97(387), 666–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (1991). Negative time preference. The American Economic Review, 81(2), 347–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (1992). Anomalies in intertemporal choice: Evidence and an interpretation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107(2), 573–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G.F., & Prelec, D. (1993). Preferences for sequences of outcomes. Psychological Review, 100(1), 91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., & Mariotti, M. (2009). Choice over time. In Anand, P., Pattanaik, P., Puppe, C. (Eds.), Oxford handbook of rational and social choice, chapter 10. Oxford University Press.

  • Meissner, T., & Pfeiffer, P. (2015). I want to know it now: Measuring preferences over the temporal resolution of consumption uncertainty. Unpublished Manuscript. Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2654668.

  • Miao, B., & Zhong, S. (2012). Separating risk preference and time preference. Unpublished Manuscript. Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2096944.

  • Prelec, D., & Loewenstein, G. (1997). Beyond time discounting. Marketing Letters, 8(1), 97–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Read, D., & Van Leeuwen, B. (1998). Predicting hunger: the effects of appetite and delay on choice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 76(2), 189–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Read, D., Loewenstein, G., Kalyanaraman, S. (1999). Mixing virtue and vice: combining the immediacy effect and the diversification heuristic. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 12(4), 257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1937). A note on measurement of utility. The Review of Economic Studies, 4(2), 155–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sayman, S., & Önçüler, A. (2008). An investigation of time inconsistency. Management Science, 55(3), 470–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholten, M., & Read, D. (2006). Discounting by intervals: A generalized model of intertemporal choice. Management Science, 52(9), 1424–1436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholten, M., & Read, D. (2010). The psychology of intertemporal tradeoffs. Psychological Review, 117(3), 925–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, M.K. (1994). Gain/loss asymmetry in risky intertemporal choice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 59(1), 124–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Train, K.E. (2009). Discrete choice methods with simulation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tsukayama, E., & Duckworth, A.L. (2010). Domain-specific temporal discounting and temptation. Judgment and Decision Making, 5(2), 72.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Pol, M.M., & Cairns, J.A. (2000). Negative and zero time preference for health. Health Economics, 9(2), 171–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Gaudecker, H.-M., van Soest, A., Wengström, E. (2011). Heterogeneity in risky choice behavior in a broad population. The American Economic Review, 101 (2), 664–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winer, R.S. (1997). Discounting and its impact on durables buying decisions. Marketing Letters, 8(1), 109–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yates, J.F., & Watts, R.A. (1975). Preferences for deferred losses. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 13(2), 294–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zauberman, G., & Lynch, Jr. J.G. (2005). Resource slack and propensity to discount delayed investments of time versus money. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 134(1), 23–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

We are grateful to the Editor and an anonymous referee, as well as the participants of FUR (2016), INFORMS annual meeting (2015) and SPUDM (2015) for helpful comments. We also thank the Investissements d’Avenir (ANR-11-IDEX-0003/Labex Ecodec/ANR-11-LABX-0047) for supporting our research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mohammed Abdellaoui.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

(PDF 2.21 MB)

Appendix: Experimental design

Appendix: Experimental design

Fig. 9
figure 9

Visualization of Losses of Time

Fig. 10
figure 10

Screenshot of a Validation Screen

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Abdellaoui, M., Gutierrez, C. & Kemel, E. Temporal discounting of gains and losses of time: An experimental investigation. J Risk Uncertain 57, 1–28 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-018-9287-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-018-9287-1

Keywords

JEL Classifications

Navigation