Skip to main content
Log in

Ellsberg paradox: Ambiguity and complexity aversions compared

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We present a simple model where preferences with complexity aversion, rather than ambiguity aversion, resolve the Ellsberg paradox. We test our theory using laboratory experiments where subjects choose among lotteries that “range” from a simple risky lottery, through risky but more complex lotteries, to one similar to Ellsberg’s ambiguity urn. Our model ranks lotteries according to their complexity and makes different—at times contrasting—predictions than most models of ambiguity in response to manipulations of prizes. The results support that complexity aversion preferences play an important and separate role from beliefs with ambiguity aversion in explaining behavior under uncertainty.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Leading theories include Schmeidler (1989), Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989), Segal (1987, 1990), and more recently Klibanoff et al. (2005) and Maccheroni et al. (2006). Section 2 and Online Appendix A provide a more detailed exposition of these theories in the context of our experiment.

  2. Modeling complexity aversion as taxing utilities due to the extra (cognitive) costly effort to compute reduced-form equivalents would result in a circular argument. The reason is that, once such effort is already taken, it becomes sunk and should not affect choices. However, we do not assume that DMs reduce the lotteries, and our simple model and treatment manipulations enable us to distinguish complexity from uncertainty aversion. See below.

  3. We model the DM as having a particular prior on the Ellsberg urn lottery only to illustrate our claim: There do exist priors with complexity aversion that resolve the Ellsberg paradox.

  4. The results of Halevy (2007) and Abdellaoui et al. (2011) are generally in line with the idea that people rank prospects according to their complexity. See also Yates and Zukowski (1976).

  5. In contrast, the urns with n ∈ (50,100) can be viewed as twice compound and thus more complex lotteries.

  6. We use the linear, additive structure for expositional simplicity. However, qualitative results will not change with any utility that is declining in δ.

  7. This approach is also taken by e.g. Segal (1987) or Klibanoff et al. (2005).

  8. We use one half for expositional simplicity. The arguments extend for different probability levels.

  9. Note that δ in fact measures the difference in complexity between A and B, rather than being an absolute measure of complexity of lottery B.

  10. Obviously, the complexity of the lottery itself may shape this distribution through the variance of the estimates in the population. This, however, does not affect any of the predictions below.

  11. See Appendix A for more details.

  12. Ambiguity aversion requires the concavity of ϕ, whereas complexity aversion is modeled as a linear transformation of payoffs which depends on the complexity of alternative prospects. This model is related to source-dependent approaches to uncertainty (Ergin and Gul 2009; Grant et al. 2009). See Appendix A for more details.

  13. We prefer this more conservative prediction. However, if most of the subjects in the experiment are averse to ambiguity (concave ϕ) fewer people should prefer B over A after our prize manipulation. See Online Appendix A for more details.

  14. To see this, note that the area A in Fig. 2b does not exist and these theories only suffer the loss of the B-preferring individuals corresponding to area B.

  15. Appendix A.3 contains the formal analysis of these arguments.

  16. The experimental instructions can be found in the Online Appendix.

  17. Note that we did not multiply the low prize in the experiment. In Appendix A, we show formally that it neither affects the derived theoretical predictions of complexity aversion nor alters the predictions of the ambiguity literature.

  18. Naturally, the terms risky, ambiguous, and compound were never used in the actual experiment.

  19. As mentioned, we use \(\frac {1}{2}\) as the probability of high prize to simplify the exposition of complexity aversion, whereas in the actual experiments the probabilities are \(\frac {3}{8}\) in Wave 1 and \(\frac {3}{4}\) in Wave 2. The reason is to prevent subjects from focusing on the symmetric \( \frac {1}{2}\) while evaluating or estimating probabilities of prizes during the experiment. The theoretical predictions are robust to considering \(\frac { 1}{2}\), \(\frac {3}{8}\) or \(\frac {3}{4}\).

  20. We thank the participants in the DT conference in HCE, Paris, 2009 for suggesting this design.

  21. Note that, in contrast to the experiment, the lotteries are ordered according to their complexity here. Hence, the Ellsberg lottery B appears as last in Tables 2 and 3.

  22. The two exceptions, both in Wave 2, are still close to 50%.

  23. Wilcoxon signed-rank test rejects that the percentages are significantly different from zero in all cases (p = 0 in all cases).

  24. Pairwise Wilcoxon signed-rank tests confirm this finding with some exceptions. First, the first percentage in each row is always lower than the third percentage (e.g. A over C vs. A over B in the first row etc.) in both tables (p < 0.002 in all cases but Wave 1 L = 50 with p < 0.045). The comparison between the first and second percentage is almost always significant at 5%, except the A row (p > 0.46 in Wave 1 and p > 0.11 in Wave 2), the D row in Wave 1 for H = 100 (p = 0.132), and the C row for H = 50 (p = 0.063). The last comparison, the second vs. third percentage, is again almost always significant at 5%, the exceptions being row A for H = 50 (p = 0.098), row C for (p = 0.065,0.698 for H = 50,100, resp.), and row B (p = 0.99,0.114 for low and high stakes, resp.). Note that most of these exceptions are at least marginally (p≤0.1) or close to marginally significant.

  25. Since the dependent variable takes values −1, 0, and 1 if, respectively, the individual prefers the more complex lottery, she is indifferent between them, or she prefers the simpler option, we estimate the ordered-logit model. The results are generally robust to alternative specifications of the dependent variable, different estimation techniques, or panel data regressions, in which subjects’ different choices play the role of the time-series variable.

  26. In his experiment, Halevy (2007) provides a robustness test of his main treatment, in which he multiplies the stakes by 10. We used his data and found that 22.2% prefer the Ellsberg-like lottery to the risky one for low stakes, but this fraction increases to 25% if stakes are higher. The difference is not statistically significant, though. There are three reasons why this additional finding may support complexity aversion: (i) any increase already contradicts most of the theories of ambiguity aversion, (ii) there are only 38 observations in the high-stake treatment, (iii) multiplying the stakes by 10 should increase subjects’ estimation effort considerably and thus work against the prediction of complexity aversion. In contrast, his ten-ball lotteries are more complex than ours. Hence, we consider his data stimulating for further exploration of complexity aversion but prefer to be cautious using this data to make general conclusions concerning our theory.

References

  • Abdellaoui, M., Klibanoff, P., & Placido, L. (2011). Ambiguity and compound risk attitudes: an experiment. Mimeo, HEC Paris.

  • Ahn, D., Choi, S., Gale, D., & Kariv, S. (2014). Estimating ambiguity aversion in a portfolio choice experiment. Quantitative Economics, 5, 195–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, F.J., & Aumann, R.J. (1963). A definition of subjective probability. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 34, 199–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew, S.H., Miao, B., & Zhong, S. (2013). Partial ambiguity. Mimeo, National University of Singapore.

  • Dean, M., & Ortoleva, P. (2015). Is it All Connected? A Testing Ground for Unified Theories of Behavioral Economics Phenomena, mimeo: Columbia University.

  • Ergin, H., & Gul, F. (2009). A theory of subjective compound lotteries. Journal of Economic Theory, 144, 899–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P., Maccheroni, F., & Marinacci, M. (2004). Differentiating ambiguity and ambiguity attitude. Journal of Economic Theory, 118, 133–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., & Marinacci, M. (2013). Ambiguity and the Bayesian paradigm. In D. Acemoglu, M. Arellano, & E. Dekel (Eds.), Advances in economics and econometrics: theory and applications, 10th World Congress of the Econometric Society. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (1989). Maxmin expected utility with a non-unique prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 18, 141–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, S., Polak, B., & Strzalecki, T. (2009). Second-order expected utility. Mimeo, Harvard University.

  • Halevy, Y. (2007). Ellsberg revisited: an experimental study. Econometrica, 75, 503–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, B. (2011). Confidence and decision. Mimeo, HEC Paris (http://www.hec.fr/hill).

  • Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M., & Mukerji, S. (2005). A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica, 73, 1849–1892.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1982). A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3, 323–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., & Rustichini, A. (2006). Ambiguity aversion, robustness, and the variational representation of preferences. Econometrica, 74, 1447–1498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. J. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (1989). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica, 57, 571–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, U. (1987). The Ellsberg paradox and risk aversion: an anticipated utility approach. International Economic Review, 28, 175–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, U. (1990). Two-stage lotteries without the reduction axiom. Econometrica, 58, 349–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yates, F.J., & Zukowski, L.G. (1976). Characterization of ambiguity in decision making. Behavioral Science, 21, 19–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jaromír Kovářík.

Additional information

Our paper greatly benefited from comments and suggestions of a referee and the Editor. We also thank Itzhak Gilboa, Yoram Halevy, Brian Hill, Dimitry Mezhvinsky, Jim Peck, and participants of the DT conference 2009 in HCE Paris and SEET 2013. Jaromír Kovářík greatly acknowledges support from Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation (ECO 2012-31626, ECO 2012-35820), the Basque Government (IT-783-13), and GACR (14-22044S).

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

(PDF 262 KB)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kovářík, J., Levin, D. & Wang, T. Ellsberg paradox: Ambiguity and complexity aversions compared. J Risk Uncertain 52, 47–64 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-016-9232-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-016-9232-0

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation