Skip to main content
Log in

Whom should we believe? Aggregation of heterogeneous beliefs

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We examine the collective risk attitude of a group with heterogeneous beliefs. We prove that the wealth-dependent probability distribution used by the representative agent is biased in favor of the beliefs of the more risk tolerant consumers. Moreover, increasing disagreement on the state probability raises the state probability of the representative agent. It implies that when most disagreements are concentrated in the tails of the distribution, the perceived collective risk is magnified. This can help to solve the equity premium puzzle. We show that the trade volume and the equity premium are positively correlated.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also Mongin (1995), Gilboa, Samet and Schmeidler (2004), and Gajdos et al. (2005). Our work differs much from this branch of the literature by taking into account risk-sharing opportunities within the group.

  2. Karni (1993), Karni and Schmeidler (1993) and Nau (1995) examined the problem of disentangling beliefs and tastes with state-dependent preferences. Drèze (2001) and Drèze and Rustichini (2001) examine the effect of the state dependency of the utility function for risk management and risk transfers.

  3. In an earlier version of this paper (Gollier 2003), we presented various results on this aspect. We explored the problem of aggregating beliefs when risk aversion and pessimism are two correlated treats of individual consumers.

  4. This is not true in general, as shown by Rothschild and Stiglitz (1971). Gollier (1995) derives the necessary and sufficient condition for a change in risk to reduce the demand for this risk by risk-averse investors. See also Jouini and Napp (2005).

References

  • Athey, Susan C. (2002). “Monotone Comparative Statics Under Uncertainty,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 117(1), 187–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abel, Andrew B. (2002). “An Exploration of the Effects of Optimism and Doubt on Asset Returns,” Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control 26, 1075–1092.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borch, Karl. (1960). “The Safety Loading of Reinsurance Premiums,” Skandinavisk Aktuarietskrift 153–184.

  • Borch, Karl. (1962). “Equilibrium in a Reinsurance Market,” Econometrica 30, 424–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossaerts, Peter, Paolo Ghirardato, Serena Guarnaschelli, and William Zame. (2007). “The Impact of Ambiguity on Prices and Allocations in Competitive Financial Markets,” Mimeo.

  • Calvet, Laurent, Jean-Michel Grandmont, and Isabelle Lemaire. (2001). “Aggregation of Heterogeneous Beliefs and Asset Pricing in Complete Financial Markets,” Mimeo, Harvard University and CREST (Paris).

  • Chapman, David A. and Valery Polkovnichenko. (2006). “Heterogeneity in Preferences and Asset Market Outcomes,” Mimeo, Boston College.

  • Cecchetti, Stephen G., Pok-Sang Lam, and Nelson C. Mark. (2000). “Asset Pricing with Distorted Beliefs: Are Equity Returns too Good to be True?” American Economic Review 90, 787–805.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Constantinides, Georges M. (1982). “Intertemporal Asset Pricing with Heterogeneous Consumers and Without Demand Aggregation,” Journal of Business 55, 253–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drèze, Jacques. (2001). “Loss Reduction and Implicit Deductibles in Medical Insurance,” CORE Discussion Paper, University of Louvain.

  • Drèze, Jacques and Aldo Rustichini. (2001). “State-Dependent Utility and Decision Theory.” In Salvador Barbera, Peter Hammond, and Christian Seidl (eds), Handbook of Utility Theory 2. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gajdos, Thibault, Jean-Marc Tallon, and Jean-Christophe Vergnaud. (2005). “On the Impossibility of Preference Aggregation Under Uncertainty,” Mimeo, University of Paris 1.

  • Gilboa, Itzhak, Dov Samet, and David Schmeidler. (2004). “Utilitarian Aggregation of Beliefs and Tastes,” Journal of Political Economy 112, 932–938.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gollier, Christian. (1995). “The Comparative Statics of Changes in Risk Revisited,” Journal of Economic Theory 66, 522–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gollier, Christian. (2001). The Economics of Risk and Time. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gollier, Christian. (2003). “Who Should We Believe? Collective Risk-taking Decisions with Heterogeneous Beliefs,” Cahiers2003/0325131, http://www.toulouse.inra.fr/leerna.

  • Hylland, Aanund and Richard Zeckhauser. (1979). “The Impossibility of Bayesian Group Decision Making with Separate Aggregation of Beliefs and Values,” Econometrica 47, 1321–1336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ingersoll, Jonathan E. (1987). Theory of Financial Decision Making. Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jouini, Elyès and Clothilde Napp. (2005). “Pessimism, Riskiness, Risk Aversion and the Market Price of Risk,” Mimeo, University of Paris-Dauphine.

  • Jouini, Elyès and Clothilde Napp. (2006). “Aggregation of Heterogeneous Beliefs,” Journal of Mathematical Economics 42, 752–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jouini, Elyès and Clothilde Napp. (2007). “Consensus Consumer and Intertemporal Asset Pricing with Heterogeneous Beliefs,” Review of Economic Studies 74, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karni, Edi. (1993). “A Definition of Subjective Probabilities with State-Dependent Preferences,” Econometrica 61, 187–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karni, Edi and David Schmeidler. (1993). “On the Uniqueness of Subjective Probabilities,” Economic Theory 3, 267–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimball, Miles S. (1990). “Precautionary Savings in the Small and in the Large,” Econometrica 58, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leland, Hayne E. (1980). “Who Should Buy Portfolio Insurance?” Journal of Finance 35, 581–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lintner, John. (1969). “The Aggregation of Investor’s Diverse Judgments and Preferences in Purely Competitive Security Markets,” Journal of Financial and Quantitative Economics 4, 347–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, Robert E. (1978). “Asset Prices in an Exchange Economy,” Econometrica 46, 1429–1446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mongin, Philippe. (1995). “Consistent Bayesian Aggregation,” Journal of Economic Theory 66, 313–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nau, Robert F. (1995). “Coherent Decision Analysis with Inseparable Probabilities and Utilities,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 10, 71–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nau, Robert F. (2003). “A Generalization of Pratt–Arrow Measure to Non-Expected-Utility Preferences and Inseparable Probability and Utility,” Management Science 49, 1089–1104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothschild, Michael and Joseph Stiglitz. (1970). “Increasing Risk: I. A Definition,” Journal of Economic Theory 2, 225–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothschild, Michael and Joseph Stiglitz. (1971). “Increasing Risk: II. Its Economic Consequences,” Journal of Economic Theory 3, 66–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, Mark. (1974). “An Aggregation Theorem for Securities Markets,” Journal of Financial Economics 1, 225–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varian, Hal. (1985). “Divergence of Opinion in Complete Markets,” Journal of Finance 40, 309–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Robert. (1968). “The Theory of Syndicates,” Econometrica 36, 113–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Gollier.

Additional information

I thank Rabah Amir, Chris Carroll, Jacques Drèze, Bernard Dumas, Guenter Franke, Paolo Ghirardato, Ithzak Gilboa, Michael Haliassos, Jim Heckman, James Huang, Deborah Lucas, David Martimort, Michel Moreaux, François Salanié, Bernard Sinclair-Desgagné, Jean-Marc Tallon, Bob Townsend, seminar participants at WZB (Berlin), Toulouse, Wharton, Zurich (30th conference of EGRIE), Paris (52d conference of AFSE and seminaire Bachelier), Chicago, Montréal, Jerusalem, Konstanz, Louvain and the NBER Summer Institute 2006, and two anonymous referees for helpful discussions. This research is supported by the Institut Europlace de Finance and the Crédit Agricole.

Appendix: The case of ISHARA preferences

Appendix: The case of ISHARA preferences

In this appendix, we first prove Proposition 2.

Proof of Proposition 2 Fully differentiating Eq. 8 with respect to z and using property (6) yields that \( \partial R/\partial z\) evaluated at (z,P) has the same sign that

$$\frac{\partial T^{u}}{\partial c}(c(z,P,\theta ),\theta )-\sum_{\theta ^{\prime }=1}^{N}\frac{T^{u}(c(z,P,\theta ^{\prime }),\theta ^{\prime })}{ T^{v}(z,P)}\frac{\partial T^{u}}{\partial c}(c(z,P,\theta ^{\prime }),\theta ^{\prime }),$$
(21)

For ISHARA preferences, \(\partial T^{u}/\partial c\) is a constant, which implies that the above expression is uniformly equal to zero, implying that R is independent of the per capita wealth in the group. Reciprocally, R independent of z implies that

$$ \frac{\partial T^{u}}{\partial c}(c(z,P,\theta ),\theta )=\sum_{\theta ^{\prime }=1}^{N}\frac{T^{u}(c(z,P,\theta ^{\prime }),\theta ^{\prime })}{ T^{v}(z,P)}\frac{\partial T^{u}}{\partial c}(c(z,P,\theta ^{\prime }),\theta ^{\prime }) $$

for all θ and P. This can be possible only if \(\partial T^{u}/\partial c\) is independent of c and θ, which means that the group has ISHARA preferences. □

We now derive an analytical solution in the ISHARA case. It is easy to check that the set of utility functions that satisfies the ISHARA property must be parameterized as follows:

$$ u(c,\theta )=\kappa \left( \frac{c-a(\theta )}{\gamma }\right) ^{1-\gamma } $$
(22)

These utility functions are defined over the consumption domain such that γ  − 1( c − a(θ)) > 0. In this particular case, the first-order condition to state-dependent the Pareto program (3) implies that

$$ c(z,P,\theta )-a(\theta )=k\left[ \lambda (\theta )p(\theta )\right] ^{1/\gamma }. $$

Since T u(c,θ) = (c − a(θ))/γ, property (8) can be rewritten in the ISHARA case as

$$ R(z,P,\theta )=\frac{\left[ \lambda (\theta )p(\theta )\right] ^{1/\gamma }}{ NE\left[ \lambda (\widetilde{\theta })p(\widetilde{\theta })\right] ^{1/\gamma }}, $$
(23)

where \(Ef(\widetilde{\theta })=N^{-1}\sum_{\theta =1}^{N}f(\theta ).\) The definition of R applied to the ISHARA case implies that

$$ R(z,P,\theta )=\frac{p(\theta )p_{\theta }^{v}(P)}{p^{v}(P)}, $$
(24)

where \(p_{\theta }^{v}=\partial p^{v}/\partial p(\theta ).\) Combining Eqs. 23 and 24 yields

$$ \frac{p_{\theta }^{v}(P)}{p^{v}(P)}=\frac{\lambda (\theta )^{1/\gamma }p(\theta )^{-1+1/\gamma }}{NE\left[ \lambda (\widetilde{\theta })p( \widetilde{\theta })\right] ^{1/\gamma }} \label{C3} $$
(25)

for θ = 1,...,N. The solution to this system of partial differential equations has the following form:

$$ p^{v}(P)=C\quad \left[ E\left[ \lambda (\widetilde{\theta })p(\widetilde{ \theta })\right] ^{1/\gamma }\right] ^{\gamma }, \label{pvC} $$
(26)

where C is a constant. In order for p v to be a probability distribution, we need to select the particular solution with

$$ p^{v}(P(s))=\frac{\left[ E_{\widetilde{\theta }}\left[ \lambda (\widetilde{ \theta })p(s,\widetilde{\theta })\right] ^{1/\gamma }\right] ^{\gamma }}{ \sum_{t=1}^{S}\left[ E_{\widetilde{\theta }}\left[ \lambda (\widetilde{ \theta })p(t,\widetilde{\theta })\right] ^{1/\gamma }\right] ^{\gamma }}. \label{ISHsol} $$
(27)

Calvet, Grandmont and Lemaire (2001) and Jouini and Napp (2004) obtained the same solution. Jouini and Napp (2004) and Chapman and Polkovnichenko (2006) derived this result in the special case of CRRA (a = 0).

Three special cases are worthy to examine.

  • Consider first the case with γ tending to zero. This corresponds to risk-neutral preferences above a minimum level of subsistence. Under this specification, condition (27) is rewritten as

    $$\begin{array}{lll} p^{v}(P(s))&=p^{n}(P(s))\nonumber\\ &=_{def}\frac{\max_{\theta \in \Theta }\lambda (\theta )p(s,\theta )}{\sum_{t=1}^{S}\max_{\theta \in \Theta }\lambda (\theta )p(t,\theta )}\text{ \ for all }s\text{. (risk-neutral case)} \end{array}$$
    (28)

    With risk-neutral preferences, the efficient allocation produces a flip-flop strategy where the cake in state s is entirely consumed by the agent with the largest Pareto-weighted probability associated to that state. It implies that the group will use a state probability p n proportional to it to determine its attitude toward risk ex ante.

  • In the case of logarithmic preferences (a = 0, γ = 1), the denominator in Eq. 27 equals \(E\lambda (\widetilde{\theta })\) since

    $$ \sum_{t=1}^{S}E_{\widetilde{\theta }}\lambda (\widetilde{\theta })p(t, \widetilde{\theta })=E_{\widetilde{\theta }}\left[ \lambda (\widetilde{ \theta })\sum_{t=1}^{S}p(t,\widetilde{\theta })\right] =E\lambda (\widetilde{ \theta })=1. $$

    It implies that

    $$ p^{v}(P(s))=p^{\ln }(P(s))=_{def}E\lambda (\widetilde{\theta })p(s, \widetilde{\theta })\text{ \ for all }s\text{. (logarithmic case)} $$
    (29)

    With these Bernoullian preferences, the efficient probability that should be associated to any state s is just the weighted mean p ln (s) of the individual subjective probabilities of that state s. This is the limit case \(T_{c}^{u}\equiv 1\) of the result presented in Proposition 5.

  • In the CARA case, we assume that \(u(c,t,\theta )=-\exp (-c/t(\theta ))\) , which is equivalent to γ tending to + ∞ , and a(θ)/γ tending to − t(θ). Equation 8 implies in that case that

    $$ p^{v}(P)=p^{CARA}(P)=K\prod_{\theta =1}^{N}p(\theta )^{\frac{t(\theta )}{ \sum_{\theta ^{\prime }=1}^{N}t(\theta ^{\prime })}}, $$
    (30)

    where K is a normalizing constant. Aggregation rule (30) and (29) are due to Rubinstein (1974). This aggregation rule is particularly easy to use when all individual beliefs are normally distributed. Suppose that agent θ, θ = 1,...,N, believes that states are normally distributed with mean μ(θ) and variance σ 2(θ). An easy consequence of Eq. 30, first observed by Lintner (1969), is that the collective beliefs p v are also normally distributed with mean

    $$ \mu ^{v}=\frac{\sum_{\theta =1}^{N}\frac{t(\theta )\mu (\theta )}{\sigma ^{2}(\theta )}}{\sum_{\theta =1}^{N}\frac{t(\theta )}{\sigma ^{2}(\theta )}}, $$
    (31)

    and variance

    $$ \sigma ^{v}=\left[ \frac{\sum_{\theta =1}^{N}\frac{t(\theta )}{\sigma ^{2}(\theta )}}{\sum_{\theta =1}^{N}t(\theta )}\right] ^{-0.5}. $$
    (32)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gollier, C. Whom should we believe? Aggregation of heterogeneous beliefs. J Risk Uncertainty 35, 107–127 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-007-9021-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-007-9021-x

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation