Skip to main content
Log in

A simpler free will defence

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Otte (Philos Phenomenol 78(1):165–177, 2009) and Pruss (Faith Philos 29(4):400–415, 2012) have produced counterexamples to Plantinga’s (The nature of necessity, 1974) famous free will defence against the logical version of the problem of evil. The target of this criticism is the possibility of universal transworld depravity, which is crucial to Plantinga’s defence. In this paper, we argue that there is a simpler and more plausible free will defence that does not require the possibility of universal transworld depravity or the truth of counterfactuals of creaturely freedom. We assume only (a) that libertarianism is possibly true and (b) that God’s existence is consistent with the existence of free agents who never go wrong. We conclude the paper by explaining how our defence may be able to succeed without assuming (a), in a way that is consistent with compatibilism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Adams (1985) writes, ‘I think it is fair to say that Plantinga has solved this problem.’ Rowe (1979) writes of Plantinga’s defence, ‘granted incompatibilism, there is a fairly compelling argument for the view that the existence of evil is logically consistent with the existence of the theistic God.’ Before arguing against Plantinga’s FWD, DeRose (1991) writes, ‘I think it is not an exaggeration to say that in some circles, Plantinga is thought to have scored a victory over the “atheologians” with respect to this form of the problem of evil that is about as decisive as philosophical victories get.’

  2. See Otte (2009) and Pruss (2012).

  3. For defences of the possibility of the existence of God, see Swinburne (1993), Maydole (2003), or Bernstein (2014).

  4. Something’s essence is the set of its essential properties.

  5. A property P entails a property Q if the following is true: \(\Box (\forall \hbox {x})(\hbox {Px} \rightarrow \hbox {Qx})\).

  6. We are restricting this to cases of non-derivative freedom.

  7. We understand the notion of sharing initial world segments in terms of hard facts. A hard fact is a fact that does not stand in a temporal relation to the future. Prior to the agent’s making some decision at a time t, there are at least two distinct worlds that are identical with respect to their hard facts prior to t. According to Fischer (2011), ‘For any action Y, agent S, and time t, S can perform Y (freely) at t only if there is a possible world with the same “hard” past up to t as the actual world in which S does Y at t.’

  8. One reply comes from classical theism, according to which God, if he exists, exists necessarily. Since it is clearly conceivable that God does not exist, it is either possible that God does not exist, or there is evidence that it is possible that he does not exist, both of which undermine the classical theist conception of God. Perhaps this argument is not open to theists who think God is necessary. However, God’s being contingent is consistent with our FWD, and so the theist who thinks God is contingent (e.g. Swinburne 2012) has access to this argument from conceivability.

References

  • Adams, R. (1985). Plantinga on the problem of evil. In P. van Inwagen & J. E. Tomberlin (Eds.), Alvin Plantinga. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, C. (2014). Giving the ontological argument its due. Philosophia, 42(3), 665–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1991). Plantinga, presumption, possibility, and the problem of evil. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 21, 497–512.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2011). The truth about freedom: A reply to Merricks. Philosophical Review, 120(1), 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1955). Evil and omnipotence. Mind, 64(254), 200–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maydole, R. (2003). The modal perfection argument for the existence of a supreme being. Philo, 6(2), 299–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Otte, R. (2009). Transworld depravity and unobtainable worlds. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78(1), 165–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2009). Transworld depravity, transworld sanctity, and uncooperative essences. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78, 178–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pruss, A. (2012). A Counterexample to Plantinga’s Free Will Defense. Faith and Philosophy, 29(4), 400–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. (1979). The problem of evil and some varieties of atheism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16(4), 335–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1993). The coherence of theism. Oxford: oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2012). What kind of necessary being could god be? In M. Szatkowski (Ed.), Ontological proofs today. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to C’Zar Bernstein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bernstein, C., Helms, N. A simpler free will defence. Int J Philos Relig 77, 197–203 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-015-9512-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-015-9512-7

Keywords

Navigation