Skip to main content
Log in

Weak rationalizability and Arrovian impossibility theorems for responsive social choice

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper provides representation theorems for choice functions satisfying weak rationality conditions: a choice function satisfies \(\alpha\) if and only if it can be expressed as the union of intersections of maximal sets of a fixed collection of acyclic relations, and a choice function satisfies \(\gamma\) if and only if it consists of the maximal elements of a relation that can depend on the feasible set in a particular, well-behaved way. Other rationality conditions are investigated, and these results are applied to deduce impossibility theorems for social choice functions satisfying weak rationality conditions along with positive responsiveness conditions. For example, under standard assumptions on the set of alternatives and domain of preferences, if a social choice function satisfies Pareto optimality, independence of irrelevant alternatives, a positive responsiveness condition for revealed social preferences, and a new rationality condition \(\delta ^{*}\) (a strengthening of \(\gamma\)), then some individual must have near dictatorial power.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Equivalently, B is a linear order if \(R_{B}\) is transitive and anti-symmetric; it is a weak order if \(R_{B}\) is transitive; it is a quasiorder if \(R_{B}\) is negatively transitive; and it is a suborder if \(R_{B}\) is negatively acyclic, in the sense that there do not exist a natural number k and alternatives \(x_{1},\ldots ,x_{k} \in X\) such that \(\lnot x_{j} R_{B} x_{j+1}\) for all \(j <k\) and \(\lnot x_{k}R_{B}x_{1}\).

  2. See Duggan (2013) for a review of the related literature and for general results on the uncovered set.

  3. The result is also shown in Theorem 1 of Schwartz (1976). He assumes the collection of feasible sets consists of the nonempty, finite subsets of alternatives, and he defines a condition W1 that is equivalent to the conjunction of \(\alpha\) and \(\gamma\).

  4. The axiom of Aizerman and Malishevski (1981) requires the opposite inclusion as well, so that \(C(Y)=C(Z)\), but this holds in the presence of \(\alpha\). Condition W5 of Schwartz (1976) suffers from a typo: \(\not \subseteq\) should be \(\subseteq\). See Weymark (1983) for a discussion of why condition \(\phi\) must be applied with some restriction on the size of feasible sets.

  5. To verify that \(\beta '\) implies \(\beta\), consider \(Y,Z \in {\mathcal {X}}\) and assume \(Y \subseteq Z\) and \(C(Y) \cap C(Z) \ne \emptyset\). In particular, \(C(Z) \cap Y \ne \emptyset\), so \(\beta '\) implies \(C(Y) \subseteq C(Y \cup Z)=C(Z)\), as required.

  6. Sen’s (1971) Theorem T.8 shows that the conjunction of \(\alpha\) and \(\beta\) is equivalent to the weak congruence axiom, which is equivalent to rationalizability by a weak order, which is equivalent to ACA; see Proposition 3.

  7. The term “pseudo-relation” is not my own: it appears in the overhead slides of a seminar at Caltech, collected in Aizerman et al. (1991). The term “pseudo-rationalizability” is used differently than by Moulin (1985).

  8. Mas-Colell and Sonnenschein (1972) assume that if some individual is indifferent between x and y and then this becomes a strict preference, then this is sufficient to break a social tie, and if some individual has a strict preference and then this becomes indifference, again a social tie is broken. In contrast, the antecedent of r-Tie break condition requires a strict preference reversal, making the axiom considerably weaker.

References

  • Aizerman, M., & Malishevski, A. (1981). General theory of best variants choice: Some aspects. IEEE Transactions on Automatic Control, 26, 1030–1040.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizerman, M., Vol’skiy, V., & Litvakov, M. (1991). Notes about theory of pseudo-criteria and binary pseudo-relations and their application to the theory of choice and voting. Caltech working paper #766.

  • Arrow, K. (1959). Rational choice functions and orderings. Economica, 26, 121–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. (1963). Social choice and individual values (2nd ed.). New Haven: Cowles Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, D., Bordes, G., Kelly, J., & Suzumura, K. (1976). Impossibility theorems without collective rationality. Journal of Economic Theory, 13, 361–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bordes, G. (1983). On the possibility of reasonable consistent majoritarian choice: Some positive results. Journal of Economic Theory, 31, 122–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chernoff, H. (1954) Rational selection of decision functions. Econometrica, 22, 422–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denicolò, V. (1985). Independent social choice correspondences are dictatorial. Economics Letters, 19, 9–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duggan, J. (2007). A systematic approach to the construction of non-empty choice sets. Social Choice and Welfare, 28, 491–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duggan, J. (2013). Uncovered sets. Social Choice and Welfare, 41, 489–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duggan, J. (2016). Limits of acyclic voting. Journal of Economic Theory, 163, 658–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. (1975). Semiorders and choice functions. Econometrica, 43, 5–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1969). Social choice and the arrow conditions. Discussion paper, Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan.

  • Gibbard, A. (2014). Social choice and the arrow conditions. Economics and Philosophy, 30, 269–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (1959). Solutions to general non-zero-sum games. In A. Tucker, & R. Luce (Eds.), Contributions to the theory of games IV, Annals of mathematical studies (Vol. 40). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Hansson, B. (1969). Voting and group decision functions. Synthese, 20, 526–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horan, S., Osborne, M., & Sanver, R. (2017). Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: A generalization of May’s theorem to many alternatives. Unpublished paper.

  • Houthakker, H. (1950). Revealed preference and the utility function. Economica, 17, 159–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jamison, D., & Lau, L. (1973). Semiorders and the theory of choice. Econometrica, 41, 901–912.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell, A., & Sonnenschein, H. (1972). General possibility theorems for group decisions. Review of Economic Studies, 39, 185–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, K. (1952). A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision. Econometrica, 20, 680–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. (1986). Covering, dominance, and institution-free properties of social choice. American Journal of Political Science, 30, 283–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H. (1985). Choice functions over a finite set: A summary. Social Choice and Welfare, 2, 147–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. (1973). Path independence, rationality, and social choice. Econometrica, 41, 1075–1091.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. (1938). A note on the pure theory of consumer’s behavior. Economica, 5, 61–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, T. (1976). Choice functions, ‘rationality’ conditions, and variations on the weak axiom of revealed preference. Journal of Economic Theory, 13, 414–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, T. (1986). The logic of collective choice. New York: Columbia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1971) Choice functions and revealed preference. The Review of Economic Studies, 38, 307–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weymark, J. (1983). Quasitransitive rationalization and the superset property. Mathematical Social Sciences, 6, 105–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I’m grateful for helpful feedback from an anonymous referee and from Martin Osborne. All errors are my responsibility.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Duggan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Duggan, J. Weak rationalizability and Arrovian impossibility theorems for responsive social choice. Public Choice 179, 7–40 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-018-0528-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-018-0528-2

Keywords

Navigation