Skip to main content
Log in

Empirical social choice: an introduction

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

[Even] if an omniscient observer, call him Zeus, knew the true tastes of every voter, it would still be impossible for him to predict the social choice or the product of aggregating preferences unless he also knew the method of aggregation. This means that the social choice depends not simply on the wills of individuals, but also on the method used to summarize these wills.

William H. Riker (1982: 31)

Abstract

The year 2012 was the 30th anniversary of William H. Riker’s modern classic Liberalism against populism (1982) and is marked by the present special issue. In this introduction, we seek to identify some core elements and evaluate the current status of the Rikerian research program and its empirical applications. Special attention is given to three phenomena and their possible empirical manifestations: The instability of social choice in the form of (1) the possibility of majority cycles, (2) the non-robustness of social choices given alternative voting methods, and (3) the possibility of various forms of manipulation of the decisions (heresthetics). These topics are then connected to the contributions to the current special issue.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Two distinguished students of Riker’s view Liberalism against populism as his most seminal work (Bueno de Mesquita and Shepsle 2001). Looking at the number of citations relative to the age of the publication, the book certainly is the most influential single work by Riker, cf. Maske and Durden (2003: 193ff).

  2. In 2013 Google Scholar counted Liberalism against populism as having been cited almost 2300 times (ca. 750 times going by the Social Science Citation Index). His seminal article in American Political Science Review on disequilibrium in majority decision-making (Riker 1980) was in many ways a precursor to the 1982 book and had in 2013 been cited almost 900 times (ca. 300 citations in SSCI). Riker’s direct follow-up to the book, the less technical and more popular The art of political manipulation (Riker 1986), had been cited ca. 1250 times. Together the citations of two of these three matches Riker’s most cited work, A theory of political coalitions (ca. 3150 citations). For an earlier citation analysis of Riker’s works (using only SSCI data), see Maske and Durden (2003).

  3. Shortly after his death the editors of the pluralistic, multidisciplinary New handbook of political science (Goodin and Klingemann 1996) estimated that across all the sub-disciplines of political science Riker shared a third place in terms of citations, along with Gabriel Almond and Robert Dahl. Quite remarkably Riker’s own student, Kenneth Shepsle, beat him, sharing second place with Seymour Martin Lipset, with Sidney Verba in first place. Riker was also judged to be one of a small group of “highly visible integrators” making an impact across a wide set of sub-disciplines within political science. (See Goodin and Klingemann 1996: 31, 34 and 41.)

  4. On the life and academic contributions of Riker more broadly, see, e.g., Mitchell (1994), Bueno de Mesquita and Shepsle (2001), McLean (2002, 2008), Aldrich (2004).

  5. On Riker’s role as the founder of the “Rochester School” or “positive political theory”, see Mitchell (1988) and Amadae and Bueno de Mesquita (1999).

  6. See Smith (2009). Smith’s analysis has only been published on-line; all of the information presented here is derived from that presentation.

  7. There may have been fraud involved in the election, but for the present purposes these official results have been treated as the correct ones.

  8. See Smith (2009) for further details, calculations and reservations about the conclusions.

  9. See also Kurrild-Klitgaard (2005: 124–138). For presentations of these and other voting methods and their properties when choosing between more than two alternatives, see, e.g., Riker (1982: 66–101), Nurmi (1987).

  10. A very obvious (but far from isolated) example derived from the US Congress was the case of the impeachment of President Clinton, wherein the House leadership simply refused to allow a vote on an alternative they knew would pass (Kurrild-Klitgaard 1999).

  11. Strategic (insincere) voting is characterized by some voters casting ballots for lower ranked candidates or alternatives in order to avoid even worse outcomes (for them) that otherwise will be selected on the basis of the “setter’s” agenda.

  12. Cf. Federalist #51, in Hamilton et al. [1787] (2001).

References

  • Aldrich, J. H. (2004). William H. Riker. In C. K. Rowley & F. Schneider (Eds.), The encyclopedia of public choice (Vol. 2, pp. 321–324). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amadae, S. M., & Bueno de Mesquita, B. (1999). The Rochester school: the origins of positive political theory. Annual Review of Political Science, 2, 269–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J. (1963). Social choice and individual values (2nd ed.). New Haven: Yale University Press. [1951].

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. (1948). On the rationale of group decision making. Journal of Political Economy, 56, 23–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brams, S. J., & Fishburn, P. C. (1978). Approval voting. American Political Science Review, 72, 831–847.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (2004). The calculus of consent: logical foundations of constitutional democracy. In C. K. Rowley (Ed.), The selected works of Gordon Tullock (Vol. 2). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. [1962].

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno de Mesquita, B., & Shepsle, K. A. (2001). William Harrison Riker, September 22, 1920—June 26, 1993. Biographical Memoirs of the National Academy of Sciences, 79, 3–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, C., & Tullock, G. (1965). A measure of the importance of cyclical majorities. Journal of Economics, 75, 853–857.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeMeyer, F., & Plott, C. R. (1970). The probability of a cyclical majority. Econometrica, 38, 345–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobra, J. L., & Tullock, G. (1981). An approach to empirical measures of voting paradoxes. Public Choice, 36, 193–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyer, J. S., & Miles, R. E. (1976). An actual application of collective choice theory to the selection of trajectories for the Mariner Jupiter/Saturn 1977 project. Operations Research, 24, 220–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garman, M. B., & Kamien, M. I. (1968). The paradox of voting: probability calculations. Behavioral Science, 13, 306–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V. (1983). Condorcet’s paradox. Theory and Decision, 15, 161–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V. (2006). Condorcet’s paradox. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Fishburn, P. C. (1976). The probability of the paradox of voting: a computable solution. Journal of Economic Theory, 12, 14–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2011). Voting paradoxes and group coherence. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1973). Manipulation of voting schemes. Econometrica, 41, 587–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. E., & Klingemann, H.-D. (1996). Political science: the discipline. In R. E. Goodin & H.-D. Klingemann (Eds.), A new handbook of political science (pp. 3–49). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, D. P., & Shapiro, I. (1994). Pathologies of rational choice: a critique of applications in political science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, A., Jay, J., & Madison, J. (2001). In G. W. Carey & J. McClellan (Eds.), The Federalist (Gideon ed.). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. [1787].

    Google Scholar 

  • Härd, S. (2000). Arbitrary democracy. In N. Berggren, N. Karlson, & J. Nergelius (Eds.), Why constitutions matter (pp. 137–166). Stockholm: City University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jamison, D. T. (1975). The probability of intransitive majority rule: an empirical study. Public Choice, 23, 87–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, B., Radcliff, B., Taber, C. S., & Timpone, R. J. (1995). Condorcet winners and the paradox of voting: probability calculations for weak preference orders. American Political Science Review, 89(1), 137–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurrild-Klitgaard, P. (1999). Voting, agenda control and the Clinton impeachment. Paper presented at Danish Public Choice Workshop, 17, 1999, Aarhus. Aarhus: Dept. of Political Science, University of Aarhus.

  • Kurrild-Klitgaard, P. (2005). Individ, stat og marked: Studier i rationalitet og politik. København: Forlaget Politiske Studier.

  • Kurrild-Klitgaard, P. (2008). Voting paradoxes under proportional representation: evidence from eight danish elections. Scandinavian Political Studies, 31(3), 242–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurrild-Klitgaard, P. (2013). Election inversions, coalitions and proportional representation: examples of voting paradoxes in danish government formations. Scandinavian Political Studies, 36(2), 121–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, M. E., & Plott, C. R. (1977). Agenda influence and its implications. Virginia Law Review, 63(4), 561–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, G. (2003). Democracy defended. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Malkevitch, J. (1990). Mathematical theory of elections. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 607, 89–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maske, K., & Durden, G. (2003). The contributions and impact of Professor William H. Riker. Public Choice, 117, 191–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. D. (1976). Intransitivities in multidimensional voting models and some implications for agenda control. Journal of Economic Theory, 12, 472–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. D., & Ordeshook, P. C. (1984). The influence of committee procedures on outcomes: some experimental evidence. The Journal of Politics, 46, 182–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLean, I. (2002). William H. Riker and the invention of heresthetic(s). British Journal of Political Science, 32, 535–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLean, I. (2008). In Riker’s footsteps. British Journal of Political Science, 39, 195–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLean, I. & Hewitt, F. (Eds.) (1994). Condorcet: foundations of social choice and political theory. Aldershot: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLean, I. & Urken, A. B. (Eds.) (1995). Classics of social choice. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, N. R. (2011). Why the Electoral College is good for political science (and public choice). Public Choice, 150, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, N. R. (2012). Election inversions by the U.S. Electoral College. In D. S. Felsenthal & M. Machover (Eds.), Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions and procedures. Studies in choice and welfare (pp. 93–127). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, N. R. (2013). Election inversions under proportional representation, Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the Public Choice Society, New Orleans.

  • Mitchell, W. C. (1988). Virginia, Rochester and Bloomington: twenty-five years of public choice and political science. Public Choice, 56, 101–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, W. C. (1994). William H. Riker (1921–1993). Public Choice, 78, iii–iv.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, W. C. (1999). Political science and public choice: 1950-70. Public Choice, 98, 237–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mueller, D. C. (2003). Public choice III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niemi, R. G., & Weisberg, H. F. (1968). A mathematical solution for the probability of the paradox of voting. Behavioral Science, 13, 317–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (1987). Comparing voting systems. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. R. (1967). A notion of equilibrium and its possibility under majority rule. The American Economic Review, 57, 787–806.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. R., & Levine, M. E. (1978). A model of agenda influence on committee decisions. The American Economic Review, 68, 146–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regenwetter, M., Grofman, B., Marley, A. A. J., & Tsetlin, I. M. (2006). Behavioral social choice: probabilistic models, statistical inference, and applications. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1958). The paradox of voting and congressional rules for voting on amendments. American Political Science Review, 52(2), 349–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1962). The theory of political coalitions. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1964). Federalism: origin, operation, significance. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1965). Arrow’s theorem and some examples of the paradox of voting. In J. M. Claunch (Ed.), Mathematical applications in political science (pp. 41–60). Dallas: Southern Methodist University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1980). Implications from the disequilibrium of majority rule for the study of institutions. American Political Science Review, 74(2), 432–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1982). Liberalism against populism: a confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1984). The heresthetic of constitution-making: the presidency in 1787. American Political Science Review, 78(1), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1986). The art of political manipulation. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1987). The lessons of 1787. Public Choice, 55(1–2), 5–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1988). The place of political science in public choice. Public Choice, 37, 247–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (Ed.) (1993). Agenda formation. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1996). The strategy of rhetoric: campaigning for the American constitution. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (1994). Basic geometry of voting. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Satterthwaite, M. A. (1975). Strategy-proofness and arrow’s conditions: existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 10, 187–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N. (1978). Instability of simple dynamic games. Review of Economic Studies, 45, 575–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shepsle, K. A., & Bonchek, M. S. (1997). Analyzing politics: rationality, behavior, and institutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepsle, K. A., & Weingast, B. R. (1981). Structure-induced equilibrium and legislative choice. Public Choice, 37(3), 503–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shepsle, K. A., & Weingast, B. R. (2012). Why so much stability? Majority voting, legislative institutions, and Gordon Tullock. Public Choice, 152(1–2), 83–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, W. D. (2009). The Romanian 2009 presidential election featured one or more high Condorcet cycles. http://rangevoting.org/Romania2009.html.

  • Timpone, R. J., & Taber, C. S. (1998). Simulation: analytic and algorithmic analyses of Condorcet’s Paradox - variations on a classical theme. Social Science Computer Review, 16(1), 72–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Deemen, A. M. A., & Vergunst, N. P. (1998). Empirical evidence of paradoxes of voting in Dutch elections. Public Choice, 97(3), 475–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, S. G., & Riker, W. H. (1989). Plurality and runoff systems and numbers of candidates. Public Choice, 60(2), 155–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Steve Brams, Bernie Grofman, Iain McLean, Mike Munger and Gordon Tullock for many enlightening discussions on these topics over the years and to Bill Shughart for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Kurrild-Klitgaard.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kurrild-Klitgaard, P. Empirical social choice: an introduction. Public Choice 158, 297–310 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-014-0164-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-014-0164-4

Keywords

Navigation