Skip to main content
Log in

Semicompatibilism and Its Rivals

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I give an overview of my “framework for moral responsibility,” and I offer some reasons that commend it. I contrast my approach with indeterministic models of moral responsibility and also other compatibilist strategies, including those of Harry Frankfurt and Gary Watson.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Fischer (1994); and Fischer and Ravizza (1998). Also, see: Fischer et al. (2007); and Fischer (2006b); and Fischer (2008b).

  2. Section 1 (“A Framework for Moral Responsibility”) is a lightly revised version of pages 3–14 of “Deep Control: The Middle Way,” the introductory essay to Fischer (2012).

  3. In sketching the “resiliency desideratum” in this essay, I have simply tried to lay out my view. This is perhaps not the appropriate venue to address difficulties and objections—of which there are (lamentably) many.

  4. Strawson (1962).

  5. I take these cases from Fischer (2006b, pp. 39ff).

  6. For discussions of the relationship between God’s omniscience and human freedom, see: Fischer, Editor (1989, 1994, pp. 111–130).

  7. Frankfurt (1969).

  8. For such an example, see Fischer (1982).

  9. Although the details of the example are (obviously) out of date, what matters, for our purposes here, is the structure of the case. This structure features a signature kind of preemptive overdetermination.

  10. Kane (1985, p. 60).

  11. For a version of this sort of strategy, see Wallace (1994).

  12. Dennett (1984) and (2003). For a discussion of Dennett (2003), see: Fischer (2005a).

  13. See note 8, above.

  14. Of course, it might be that the availability of alternative possibilities is in some sense “part of the actual sequence;” I am indebted to both Carl Ginet and Patrick Todd for this point. My contention in the text relies on the intuitive notion that we can separate “actual-sequence” from “alternative-sequence” facts, but this might be too quick. In any case, my view is that moral responsibility attributions should not depend on the actual-sequence facts leaving it open that the agent in question have alternative possibilities. For a very interesting recent discussion of the contention that moral responsibility supervenes on the actual sequence, see: Sartorio (forthcoming).

  15. See Fischer and Ravizza (1998, pp. 65–69).

  16. For a further development and defense of (MRR), see Fischer and Ravizza (1998, esp. pp. 62–91).

  17. For such accounts—that explicitly build on (MRR)—see Fischer and Ravizza (1998, esp. pp. 62–91).

  18. For further reflections on various features of my account of guidance control (and thus the freedom-relevant component of moral responsibility), see: Fischer (2005b, 2006a, 2008a).

    There are certain features of my account of guidance control that a disconcerting cohort of (otherwise!) thoughtful philosophers have found rather less than irresistible, especially the subjective element and the contention that “reactivity is all of a piece.” In the trio of articles above, I argue (among other things) that (if need be) I could adjust my account so as to do without these contentious features while still maintaining all of my major claims: that moral responsibility does not require regulative control, that causal determination is compatible with moral responsibility, that moral responsibility is an essentially historical notion, and so forth. Although I of course think that much can be said for the various particularly contentious elements of the account of guidance control, it is perhaps helpful to note that they are not essential to an adequate account of guidance control that achieves the main results at which I aim; thus, it will not be sufficient for many critics to attack what they might perceive to be easier targets (the low-hanging fruit, as it were).

  19. Fischer (1999); reprinted in Fischer (2006b, pp. 106–123).

  20. Fischer (2005c); reprinted in Fischer (2008b, pp. 145–164).

  21. Fischer (2008/2009); reprinted in Fischer (2008b, pp. 165–177).

  22. Frankfurt (1971); reprinted in Fischer (1986, pp. 65–80). All references here will be to the reprinted version. In a previous paper, Frankfurt had argued that freedom to do otherwise is not necessary for moral responsibility: Frankfurt (1969); reprinted in Fischer (1986, pp. 143–152).

  23. Frankfurt (1971, pp. 70–71).

  24. Frankfurt (1971).

  25. Watson (1975); reprinted in Fischer (1986, pp. 81–96); all references will be to the reprinted version; and Thalberg (1978).

  26. Frankfurt, “Identification and Wholeheartedness,” in Schoeman (1987, pp. 27–45); reprinted in Fischer and Ravizza (1993, pp. 170–187). (All references will be to the reprinted paper.); and Frankfurt (1992); reprinted in Fischer (2005, pp. 54–67).

  27. For discussions of what are perhaps analogous issues, and a defense of my approach in light of such considerations, see: Fischer (2006c); reprinted in Fischer (2012, pp. 163–185).

  28. Watson (1975, p. 95).

  29. Frankfurt (1971, p. 69).

  30. Watson (1975, p. 95).

  31. Bratman (2004); reprinted in Fischer (2005, pp. 68–89). (All references will be to the reprinted paper.) The quoted material is on p. 79.

  32. My sister-in-law, Professor Debra Fischer (Yale University), is one of the leading scientists discovering “exoplanets.” These planets are posited to explain data we get from telescopes—typically, the “wobbling” or perturbations of other celestial bodies.

  33. Watson (1975, p. 95).

  34. I certainly have not undertaken a thorough or careful defense of my contention that positing higher-order mental states is not necessary for certain important theoretical purposes. For a thoughtful defense of the hierarchical model—one that would need to be addressed in a more thorough consideration of these issues, see Bratman (2004).

  35. Frankfurt (1971, p. 74).

  36. For a treatment of moral responsibility for omissions, see Fischer and Ravizza (1998, pp. 123–150).

  37. Watson (1975).

  38. Watson (1975, p. 91).

  39. Watson (1975, p. 91).

  40. In contrast to Frankfurt, Watson has admitted that weakness of the will constitutes a challenge for his view, and he has grappled with this problem in numerous subsequent papers, including: Watson (1977, 1999, 2003). Because of the problem of weakness of the will, I have suggested the perhaps Watson should be interpreted as giving an account of “autonomy” rather than moral responsibility: Fischer (forthcoming).

  41. For discussions of normative competence, see Watson (1999, 2003).

  42. Watson (2001). I have also argued that Thomas Scanlon would need to adopt a framework similar to mine—one that embraces a distinction between actual-sequence and alternative-sequence mechanisms—in order to accommodate the Frankfurt cases Fischer (2008c); reprinted in Fischer (2012) at Chap. 7.

  43. For a preliminary defense of this contention, see: Fischer (2011a); reprinted in Fischer (2012, pp. 85–105).

  44. For a discussion of some of the relevant issues, see: Nelson (2011); and Fischer (2011b, esp. pp. 150–156). In various conversations, Patrick Todd has pointed to the need to articulate and defend my view more effectively.

  45. An actual-sequence theory of moral responsibility is symmetric with respect to right and wrong actions, in contrast to theories such as those developed in Wolf (1990) and Nelkin (2011). Insofar as one can construct Frankfurt-cases for right and wrong actions, it seems to me that a theory of moral responsibility should be symmetric with respect to right and wrong action: Fischer and Ravizza (1992, 1998, esp. pp. 55–61).

  46. Semicompatibilism is thus consistent with, although it does not require, a thoroughgoing naturalism. Semicompatibilism thus displays an additional felicitous resilience in that it is neutral with respect to materialism or dualism about the mind.

References

  • Bratman, Michael E. 2004. Planning agency, autonomous agency. In Personal autonomy, ed. James Stacey Taylor, 33–57. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 1984. Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 2003. Freedom evolves. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon (ed.). 1999. Addictions: Entries and exits. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 1982. Responsibility and control. The Journal of Philosophy 79: 24–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin (ed.). 1986. Moral responsibility. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin (ed.). 1989. God, foreknowledge, and freedom. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 1994. The metaphysics of free will: An essay on control. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 1999. Responsibility and self-expression. The Journal of Ethics 3: 277–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2005a. Dennett on the basic argument. Metaphilosophy 36: 427–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2005b. The free will revolution. Philosophical Explorations 8: 145–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2005c. Free will, death, and immortality: The role of narrative. Philosophical Papers 34: 379–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin (ed.). 2005d. Critical concepts in philosophy: Free will, vol. IV. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2006a. The free will revolution (continued). The Journal of Ethics 10: 315–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2006b. My way: Essays on moral responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2006c. The cards that are dealt you. The Journal of Ethics 10: 107–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2008a. My way and life’s highway: Replies to Steward, Smilansky, and Perry. The Journal of Ethics 12: 167–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2008b. Our stories: Essays on life, death, and free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2008c. Responsibility and the kinds of freedom. The Journal of Ethics 12: 203–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2008/2009. Stories and the meaning of life. Philosophic Exchange 39: 2–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2011a. Indeterminism and control: The problem of luck. In Current legal issues: Law and neuroscience, ed. Michael Freeman, 41–60. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2011b. Reply to Michael Nelson. Social Theory and Practice 37: 150–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. 2012. Deep control: Essays on free will and value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin. Forthcoming. Responsibility and autonomy: The problem of mission creep. Philosophical Issues 22.

  • Fischer, John Martin, and Mark Ravizza. 1992. Responsibility, freedom, and reason. Ethics 102: 368–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin, and Mark Ravizza. 1998. Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin, Robert Kane, Derk Pereboom, and Manuel Vargas. 2007. Four views on free will. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1969. Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. The Journal of Philosophy 66: 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 68: 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1987. Identification and wholeheartedness. In Responsibility, character, and the emotions, ed. Ferdinand Schoeman, 27–45.

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1992. The faintest passion. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association 66: 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, Michael (ed.). 2011. Current legal issues: Law and neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, Robert. 1985. Free will and values. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, Dana. 2011. Making sense of freedom and responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, Michael. 2011. Default compatibliism and narrativity: Comments on John Martin Fischer’s Ways and stories. Social Theory and Practice 37: 35–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartorio, Carolina. Forthcoming. Actuality and responsibility. Mind.

  • Schoeman, Ferdinand (ed.). 1987. Responsibility, character, and the emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawon, P.F. 1962. Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy 48: 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, Sarah, and Christine Tappolet (eds.). 2003. Weakness of the will and practical irrationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, James Stacey (ed.). 2004. Personal autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thalberg, Irving. 1978. Hierarchical analyses of free action. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8: 211–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R.Jay. 1994. Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Gary. 1975. Free agency. The Journal of Philosophy 72: 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Gary. 1977. Skepticism about weakness of the will. The Philosophical Review 86: 316–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Gary. 1987. Free action and free will. Mind 96: 145–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Gary. 1996. Two faces of responsibility. Philosophical Topics 24: 227–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Gary. 1999. Disordered appetites. In Addictions: Entries and exits, ed. Jon Elster, 23–28. New York: Russell Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Gary. 2001. Reason and responsibility [critical notice of John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza, Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility]. Ethics 111: 374–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Gary. 2003. The work of the will. In Weakness of the will and practical irrationality, ed. Sarah Stroud, and Christine Tappolet, 172–200.

  • Wolf, Susan. 1990. Freedom within reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Martin Fischer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fischer, J.M. Semicompatibilism and Its Rivals. J Ethics 16, 117–143 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-012-9123-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-012-9123-9

Keywords

Navigation