Skip to main content
Log in

The Structure of Character

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I defend a local account of character traits that posits traits like close-friend-honesty and good-mood-compassion. John Doris also defends local character traits, but his local character traits are indistinguishable from mere behavioral dispositions, they are not necessary for the purpose which allegedly justifies them, and their justification is only contingent, depending upon the prevailing empirical situation. The account of local traits I defend posits local traits that are traits of character rather than behavioral dispositions, local traits that are necessary to satisfy one of their central purposes, and local traits whose justification is dependent upon theoretical rather than empirical considerations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an excellent compilation of this research, see Ross and Nisbett (1991).

  2. Hereafter, I refer simply to trait-relevant behavior as a condensed way of referring to trait-relevant behavior, attitudes, and judgment.

  3. See Harman (1999, 2000), Athanassoulis (1999), Kamtekar (2004), Kupperman (2001), Miller (2003), Sreenivasan (2002), and Vranas (2005).

  4. See, for example, Annas (2003, p. 24), Anscombe (1997, pp. 40–42), Aristotle (1990, 1106a16–24, 1100b35–1101a7, 1115a26–27), Foot (2002, p. 16), Hume (1975, pp. 169, 231), Hursthouse (1999, pp. 10–11, 20), Kupperman (1991, p. 9), MacIntyre (1985, pp. 179, 185), McDowell (1979, pp. 331, 332), Plato (1992), Railton (1995, p. 93), Swanton (2003, p. 21).

  5. If courage involves overcoming fear, then fear might be one of the mental features that grounds courage. I ignore the question whether negatively-tinged struggle-producing mental features are part of a virtue’s mental grounding, that is, whether they are necessary for possessing certain virtues, since my account of character traits is consistent with either option.

  6. For a useful discussion of the content of struggle-producing mental features and their impact on the possession of virtue, see Hursthouse (1999, pp. 91–99).

  7. It is irrelevant to my defense of local traits whether traditionally-conceived traits should guarantee, or whether they should probabilify, virtuous behavior. For the sake of encouraging simplicity, I assume that a trait’s dynamism should guarantee virtuous behavior.

  8. Views about the proper understanding of how many, and which, situations constitute a broad range of situations diverge. According to Annas, virtue requires that we behave virtuously in every situation we encounter. See Annas (2003, p. 33): “It is hard to see how any situation could be excluded.” An alternative view holds that virtue requires that we behave virtuously only in most of the situations that we encounter. I ignore this discussion, as it is irrelevant to my defense of local character traits.

  9. A descriptive account of normal situations might hold that normal situations are those that are statistically commonplace. And in a particular individual’s case, severe, chronic depression might be statistically commonplace. If we accept this descriptive account of normal situations, then if someone fails to behave compassionately because of a prevailing depression, she is simply not a compassionate person. Intuitively, however, this account gets things wrong. Provided the victim of depression possesses the mental features appropriate to compassion, her depression mitigates her non-compassionate behavior.

  10. At least four specific experiments exemplify the structure and outcome of experiment that I here discuss. See Austin (1979, pp. 2110–2120), Moriarty (1975, pp. 370–376), Schwartz and Gottlieb (1980), and Shaffer et al. (1975).

  11. I do not explore in any further detail the claim that behavior is locally-dependent, as several other writers have executed this task sufficiently. See, for example, Ross and Nisbett (1991). See also Vranas (2005).

  12. See Cunningham (1979), Fried and Berkowitz (1979), Piliavin and Piliavin (1975), and Latane and Darley (1970).

  13. Doris offers no less than five distinct arguments for the conclusion that local trait attributions produce better-functioning moral agents, but none of these arguments should lead us to accept local traits. See Upton (2005).

  14. See, for example, Kamtekar (2004) and Sreenivasan (2002).

  15. If the virtues are unified, then my ability accurately to predict behavior given accurate trait attributions is compromised. If my friend is generous and the virtues are unified, then she possesses every virtue, including the virtue of justice. And it is consistent with my friend’s being generous that she only infrequently donates money since, in my friend’s case, the demands of justice might typically trump the demands of justice.

  16. Sam’s failure to behave virtuously does not stem from any grossly immoral beliefs, such as those embodied by racist, cruel, or selfish people. Hence, Sam’s meriting moral credit is consistent with Hursthouse’s claim that agents whose better moral tendencies are fragmented by grossly immoral mental states have no virtues at all. See Hursthouse (1999, pp. 146–147).

  17. See, for example, Ross and Nisbett (1991, p. 101), Wright and Mischel (1987), Shoda et al. (1994, pp. 681–683).

  18. Hursthouse appears to endorse a related strategy for appraising psychologically complex agents. Such agents “can be accommodated by suitably qualified ascriptions of virtue…” See Hursthouse (1999, p. 149).

  19. Intuitively, more than three situations must comprise the broad range of situations in which an agent should behave virtuously, since possessing the virtues is supposed to enable an agent to flourish. I construct the case of Jan, who should behave justly in three kinds of situation, solely for the purpose of argumentative simplicity.

References

  • Annas, J. 2003. Virtue ethics and social psychology. A Priori 2: 20–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G.E.M. 1997. Modern moral philosophy. In Virtue ethics, ed. R. Crisp, and M. Slote, 26–44. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle, 1990. Nicomachean ethics (Trans: Ross, David). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Athanassoulis, N. 1999. A response to Harman: Virtue ethics and character traits. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100: 215–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, W. 1979. Sex differences in bystander intervention in a theft. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 37: 2110–2120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, M. 1979. Weather, mood, and helping behavior: Quasi experiments with the sunshine samaritan. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 37: 1947–1956.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. 1998. Persons, situations, and virtue ethics. Nous 32: 504–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. 2002. Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. 2002. Virtues and vices. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fried, R., and L. Berkowitz. 1979. Music hath charms… and can influence helpfulness. Journal of Applied Social Psychology 9: 199–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1999. Moral philosophy meets social psychology: Virtue ethics and the fundamental attribution error. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99: 315–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 2000. The nonexistence of character traits. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100: 223–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1975. Enquiry concerning the principles of morals, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge, 3rd edn, ed. P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Hursthouse, R. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamtekar, R. 2004. Situationism and virtue ethics on the content of our character. Ethics 114: 458–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kupperman, J. 1991. Character. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kupperman, J. 2001. The indispensability of character. Philosophy 76: 239–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latane, B., and J. Darley. 1970. The unresponsive bystander: Why doesn’t he help? New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, M. 1985. After virtue. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1979. Virtue and reason. Monist 62: 331–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, C. 2003. Social psychology and virtue ethics. The Journal of Ethics 7: 365–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, T. 1975. Crime, commitment, and the responsive bystander: Two field experiments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 31: 370–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piliavin, I., and J. Piliavin. 1975. Costs, diffusion, and the stigmatized victim. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 32: 429–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato, 1992. Republic (Trans: Grube, G.M.A, Rev: Reeve, C.D.C.). Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Railton, P. 1995. Made in the shade: Moral compatibilism and the aims of moral theory. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21(Supp): 79–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L., and R. Nisbett. 1991. The Person and the situation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S., and A. Gottlieb. 1980. Bystander anonymity and reactions to emergencies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 39: 418–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaffer, D., M. Rogel, and C. Hendrick. 1975. Intervention in the library: The effect of increased responsibility on bystanders’ willingness to prevent a theft. Journal of Applied Social Psychology 5: 303–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoda, Y., M. Mischel, and J. Wright. 1994. Intraindividual stability in the organization and patterning of behavior: Incorporating psychological situations into the idiographic analysis of personality. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 67: 681–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sreenivasan, G. 2002. Errors about errors: Virtue theory and trait attribution. Mind 111: 47–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swanton, C. 2003. Virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Upton, C. 2005. Review of John Doris’s lack of character. Journal of Value Inquiry 39: 507–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vranas, P. 2005. The indeterminacy paradox: Character evaluations and human psychology. Nous 39: 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, J., and W. Mischel. 1987. A conditional approach to dispositional constructs: The local predictability of social behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 53: 1159–1177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Candace L. Upton.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Upton, C.L. The Structure of Character. J Ethics 13, 175–193 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-009-9047-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-009-9047-1

Keywords

Navigation