Skip to main content
Log in

Attunement in the Modern Age

  • Research Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This contribution starts from Max Scheler’s claim that modern philosophy holds two differing views on feelings. The first view, which Scheler attributes to René Descartes, presents them in their intentional role but rejects their independence; the other view, which Scheler attributes to Immanuel Kant, holds that they cannot be reduced to the rational part of the soul and thus affirms their independence, but deprives them of all cognitive powers. After considering both views, I discuss the views of Franz Brentano and Edmund Husserl. Husserl takes an ambivalent approach to attunement, which opens the possibility of understanding Martin Heidegger’s thought of fundamental attunement.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The basic problem with providing a unified expression for feeling is that the very search for a unified term is itself misleading. The reason for this is that every thinker uses their expressions within their own mental framework. I can thus find already in Aristotle expressions such as pathos (Gr. pathos), attunement (Gr. diathesis). In the Middle Ages two terms emerge, affections (affectiones) and passions (passiones), which are taken over by Descartes (1951, 1989). According to Heidegger, the latter two bring before us a fundamentally different truth of what it is to be human. Later, Kant distinguished affects from passions and feeling. Feeling and disposition (Ger. Gefühl und Gemüt) are German words, which prevailed in the 17th and 18th centuries (Kaufmann 1992). In Heidegger, the expressions for affectivity are mood and attunement (Ger. Stimmung und Befindlichkeit). This is why I have decided to use the term attunement as a unifying expression in the title of my contribution, and in individual paragraphs the terms related to individual thinkers, indicating the basic thread of my thought, seeking to meet the demand for “Begriffsgeschichtlichkeit”.

  2. In this aspect of the later Descartes, Michael Allen Gillespie (1996) recognizes the basic trait of thinking which was of decisive importance for later philosophy, placing more and more importance on the primacy of willing, all the way to Nietzsche and his will to power.

References

  • Brentano, F. (1874/1995). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. (L. L. McAlister, A. Rancurello & D. B. Terrell, Trans.). London: Routledge.

  • Coriando, P.-L. (2002). Affektenlehre und phänomenologie der stimmungen. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1641/1951). Meditations on first philosophy. (L. J. Lafleur, Trans.). New York: Bobbs-Merrill.

  • Descartes, R. (1649/1989). The passions of the soul. (S. Voss, Trans.). Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Gillespie, M. A. (1996). Nihilism before Nietzsche. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1927/1962). Being and time. (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

  • Heidegger, M. (1989/1999). Contributions to philosophy (From enowning). (P. Emad & K. Maly, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1901/2001). The shorter logical investigations. (M. A. E. Dummett, J. N. Findlay & D. Moran, Trans.). London: Taylor & Francis Group.

  • Husserl, E. (1928/1964). Phenomenology of internal time-consciousness. (J. S. Churchill, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1931/1982). Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology. (D. Cairns, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. (1936/1970). The Crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology: An introduction to phenomenological philosophy. (D. Carr, Trans.). Chicago: Northwestern University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1970/2001). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic. (A. J. Steinbock, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Kant, I. (1788/1922). Critique of practical reason. (F. M. Müller, Trans.). London: Macmillan & Co, Ltd.

  • Kant, I. (1790/1914). Critique of judgement, (J. H. Bernard, Trans.). London: Macmillan & Co, Ltd.

  • Kaufmann, P. (1992). Gemüt und Gefühl als Komplement der Vernunft. Eine Auseinandersetzung mit der Tradition und der phänomenologischen Ethik, besonders Max Schelers. (Disposition and feeling as complement of reason. Examination of tradition and phenomenological ethics, especially Max Scheler’s). Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.

  • Levinas, E. (1930/1973). The theory of intuition in Husserl’s phenomenology. (A. Orianne, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Scheler, M. (1916/1973). Formalism in ethics and non-formal ethics of values: A new attempt toward the foundation of an ethical personalism. (M. S. Frings & R. L. FunkHalle, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Smith, A. D. (2003a). Husserl and the Cartesian meditations. London: Taylor & Francis e-Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. A. (2003b). Qualitative psychology: A practical guide to research methods. London: Sage House Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Janko M. Lozar.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lozar, J.M. Attunement in the Modern Age. Hum Stud 32, 19–31 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-009-9107-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-009-9107-3

Keywords

Navigation