Skip to main content
Log in

Two Notions of Naturalness

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

My aim in this paper is twofold: (i) to distinguish two notions of naturalness employed in beyond the standard model (BSM) physics and (ii) to argue that recognizing this distinction has methodological consequences. One notion of naturalness is an “autonomy of scales” requirement: it prohibits sensitive dependence of an effective field theory’s low-energy observables on precise specification of the theory’s description of cutoff-scale physics. I will argue that considerations from the general structure of effective field theory provide justification for the role this notion of naturalness has played in BSM model construction. A second, distinct notion construes naturalness as a statistical principle requiring that the values of the parameters in an effective field theory be “likely” given some appropriately chosen measure on some appropriately circumscribed space of models. I argue that these two notions are historically and conceptually related but are motivated by distinct theoretical considerations and admit of distinct kinds of solution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. One sometimes calls this problem the “little Hierarchy problem,” reserving the title “Hierarchy problem” for the problem of the hierarchy between the EWSB scale and the Planck scale. Nothing hinges on this distinction in this paper.

  2. I neglect here the position that advocates simply staying the course, preserving the emphasis that has been placed on naturalness at the expense of focusing on more complicated natural extensions of the Standard Model.

  3. This position is also described in [7, 11, 64], among others.

  4. Like many such calculations in the 1930s, Weisskopf made use of the hole-theoretic formalism of Dirac; see [56, Chap. 2] for calculational methods in the 1930s.

  5. Weisskopf is here considering a theory to be inconsistent if the series expansion of the self-energy contribution W does not converge.

  6. This is not to suggest that Weisskopf’s treatment of the scalar theory is unique in this regard; as shown above, he makes a similar argument in the case of the purely fermionic theory.

  7. For example, see [9, 10, 50, 52, 62, 72].

  8. See [70, pp. 1825–6] for the assumptions about the behavior of the \(\beta \)-function underlying his analysis. He notes that “there is no way of knowing whether these assumptions are true for quantum electrodynamics or any other given field theory.”

  9. Of course, we now recognize this was a mistake. Quantum chromodynamics, the theory of the strong interaction, is asymptotically free, while quantum electrodynamics is not.

  10. In terminology that is now familiar, but which Wilson introduces immediately prior to this discussion, this is just to say that \(x_1\) is an ultraviolet stable fixed point.

  11. Wilson also cites [35] and [14] in support of the quotation below.

  12. Wilson has elsewhere defined the “renormalized charge” as the charge renormalized at \(\lambda = 0\).

  13. Indeed, ’t Hooft’s emphasis on the role of symmetry in his notion of naturalness has led Grinbaum to suggest that “based upon ’t Hooft’s definition, [naturalness] could have received a...conceptual foundation similar to that of symmetry” [41, p. 616]; see also [43] in which the “conventional” approach to naturalness is described akin to a symmetry principle. I do not think this kind of justification for naturalness is compelling, but these remarks illustrate the extent to which ’t Hooft’s notion of naturalness has become identified with his remarks about symmetries.

  14. Wells offers an interesting counterfactual history that argues strict insistence on Absolute Naturalness could have grounded a series of inferential steps leading from quantum electrodynamics to the Standard Model.

  15. This understanding of naturalness is also advocated in [11, 36,37,38].

  16. What follows is not primarily aimed at historically accurate exigesis: whether Susskind or ’t Hooft, or others actually were motivated by an autonomy of scales expectation is not of primary importance here. That said, I think there is fairly good evidence that they were, some of which will be briefly presented here.

  17. ’t Hooft assumes that all the gauge theories he is investigating in [60] have a UV cutoff, which he refers to as the “Naturalness Mass Breakdown Scale” and estimates to be at about 1 TeV.

  18. A referee suggests that ’t Hooft’s claim that the smallness of a parameter must be accounted for with a symmetry was motivated by reflection on the central methodological role that symmetries occupy in constructing quantum field theories. I think this would have been a strong argument for ’t Hooft to have given, but I am unable to find textual support for it in [60]. However, I think it is an interesting and plausible conjecture about ’t Hooft’s attitude toward quantum field theories at the time and I mention it here as an invitation for interested parties to take up the question.

  19. See [26] for a complementary discussion of the way that dimensional analysis informs intuitions about naturalness.

  20. The claim that all couplings of the Standard Model except the Higgs boson mass are natural is false if one is inclined to consider the cosmological constant as a Standard Model coupling.

  21. In [20, Chap. 8], for example, a pedagogical proof of the decoupling theorem is proven using a scalar field theory in which the couplings in the low-energy effective theory are quadratically sensitive to the high-energy physics that is integrated out.

  22. Recall Zee’s somewhat relaxed attitude on this score; see also [68, p. 103] for a similarly relaxed attitude.

  23. The reader is encouraged to see Grinbaum [41, Sect. 3] for a complementary discussion of the evolution of quantitative measures of naturalness and how the concept of naturalness itself underwent modifications through this process.

  24. In the original example, the low-energy observable is \(M_Z\), standing in for the scale of EWSB, and they consider variations of parameters \(\alpha _i\) related to the scale at which supersymmetry is broken in a given model. The prefactor \(\frac{\alpha _i}{{\mathcal {M}}}\) is included to remove an overall dependence on the scale of \(\alpha _i\) and \({\mathcal {M}}\).

  25. See, for example, [2,3,4, 8, 19, 23].

  26. A number of such choices have to be made in any attempt to construct a quantitative measure of naturalness, as is discussed in some detail in [34] and [21]. As I said above, I think there is a plausible argument to be made that this inevitable sense that one is making arbitrary choices stems from trying to impose unwarranted mathematical precision on an imprecise physical heuristic.

  27. Anderson recalls that their understanding of naturalness at the time was that “if you imagine that the fundamental (Lagrangian) parameters had some smooth probability distribution, an observable parameter would be unnatural if the measured value of that parameter was only within some characteristic range around the measured value for an unusually small part of the parameter space relative to other values” (personal communication). This has no essential connection to a notion of interscale sensitivity.

  28. For pedagogical discussion of the details of compactification mechanisms and the origin of the landscape, see [46] or [24].

  29. My thanks to a referee for urging me to address this.

  30. See also [55] for a discussion of this problem that is more directly focused on the string landscape.

  31. See also [1] for an early investigation of the properties an effective field theory should satisfy in order to have a UV completion.

  32. For what it is worth, the attitude expressed by [6] seems to me quite reasonable: “One might think that low-energy SUSY with \(m_S\sim \text {TeV}\) is preferred, since this does not entail a large fine-tuning to keep the Higgs light. However, this conclusion is unwarranted\(\ldots \) without a much better understanding of the structure of the landscape, we can’t decide whether low-energy SUSY breaking is preferred to SUSY broken at much higher energies.”

  33. My thanks to a referee for offering this objection.

References

  1. Adams, A., Arkani-Hamed, N., Dubovsky, S., Nicolis, A., Rattazzi, R.: Causality, analyticity, and an IR obstruction to UV completion. JHEP 2006, 014 (2006)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  2. Anderson, G.W., Castaño, D.J., Riotto, A.: Naturalness lowers the upper bound on the lightest higgs boson mass in supersymmetry. Phys. Rev. D 55, 2950–54 (1997)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  3. Anderson, G.W., Castaño, D.J.: Measures of fine tuning. Phys. Lett. B 347, 300–08 (1995)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  4. Anderson, G.W., Castaño, D.J.: Naturalness and superpartner masses or when to give up on weak scale supersymmetry. Phys. Rev. D 52, 1693–1700 (1995)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  5. Appelquist, T., Carazzone, J.: Infrared singularities and massive fields. Phys. Rev. D 11, 2856–61 (1975)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  6. Arkani-Hamed, N., Dimopolous, S.: Supersymmetric unification without low energy supersymmetry and signatures for fine-tuning at the LHC. JHEP 2005, 073 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Arvanitaki, A., Baryakhtar, M., Huang, X., Van Tilburg, K., Villadoro, G.: The last vestiges of naturalness. JHEP 2014, 22 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Athron, P., Miller, D.J.: New measure of fine-tuning. Phys. Rev. D 76, 07510 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Baer, H., Tata, X.: Weak Scale Supersymmetry: From Superfields to Scattering Events. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2006)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. Banks, T.: Modern Quantum Field Theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2008)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  11. Barbieri, R.: Electroweak theory after the first LHC phase. http://arxiv.org/abs/1309.3473 (2013)

  12. Barbieri, R., Guidice, G.F.: Upper bounds on supersymmetric particle masses. Nucl. Phys. B 306, 63–76 (1988)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  13. Barbieri, R., Strumia, A.: About the fine-tuning price of LEP. Phys. Lett. B 433, 63–66 (1998)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  14. Bogoliubov, N.N., Shirkov, D.V.: Introduction to the theory of quantized fields. Interscience, New York (1959)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Brennan, D., Carta, F., Vafa, C.: The String landscape, the Swampland, and the missing corner. arXiv:1711.00864 (2017)

  16. Carroll, S.: Is our Universe natural? Nature 440, 1132 (2006)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  17. Chankowski, P.H., Ellis, J., Pokorski, S.: The fine-tuning price of LEP. Phys. Lett. B 423, 327–336 (1998)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  18. Christ, N.: Renormalizable theory of the weak interactions. Phys. Rev. 176, 2086 (1968)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  19. Ciafaloni, P., Strumia, A.: Naturalness upper bounds on gauge-mediated soft terms. Nucl. Phys. B 494, 41–53 (1997)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  20. Collins, J.: Renormalization: an introduction to renormalization, the renormalization group and the operator-product expansion. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1984)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. Craig, N.: The state of supersymmetry after run I of the LHC. http://arxiv.org/abs/1309.0528 (2013)

  22. Dawson, S.: Introduction to electroweak symmetry breaking. In: Masiero, A., Senjanovic, G., Smirnov, A. (eds.) ICTP High Energy Physics and Cosmology. Cornell University, New York (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  23. De Carlos, B., Casas, J.A.: One-loop analysis of the electroweak breaking in supersymmetric models and the fine-tuning problem. Phys. Lett. B 309, 320–328 (1993)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  24. Denef, F.: Les Houches lectures on constructing string vacua. http://arxiv.org/abs/0803.1194 (2008)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  25. Denef, F., Douglas, M.R.: Distributions of flux vacua. JHEP 2004, 072 (2004)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Dine, M.: Naturalness under stress. Annu. Rev. Nucl. Part. Sci. 65, 43–62 (2015)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  27. Dine, M., Gorbatov, E., Thomas, S.: Low energy supersymmetry from the landscape. JHEP 2008, 098 (2008)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  28. Dirac, P.A.M.: The cosmological constants. Nature 139, 323 (1937)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  29. Douglas, M.R.: The statistics of string/M theory vacua. JHEP 2003, 046 (2003)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  30. Douglas, M.R.: Basic results in vacuum statistics. Comptes Rendus Phys. 5, 965–977 (2004)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  31. Douglas, M.R.: The string landscape and low energy supersymmetry. In: Rebhan, A., et al. (eds.) Strings, Gauge Fields, and the Geometry Behind: The Legacy of Maximilian Kreuzer, pp. 261–288. World Scientific, Singapore (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  32. Douglas, M.R., Kachru, S.: Flux compactification. Rev. Mod. Phys. 79, 733 (2007)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  33. Farina, M., Pappadopulo, D., Strumia, A.: A modified naturalness principle and its experimental tests. JHEP 2013, 22 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  34. Feng, J.L.: Naturalness and the status of supersymmetry. Annu. Rev. Nucl. Part. Sci. 63, 351–382 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  35. Gell-Mann, M., Low, F.E.: Quantum electrodynamics at small distances. Phys. Rev. 95, 1300 (1954)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  36. Giudice, G.F.: Naturally speaking: the naturalness criterion and physics at the LHC. In: Kane, G., Pierce, A. (eds.) Perspectives on LHC Physics, pp. 155–178. Cornell University, New York (2008)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  37. Giudice, G.F.: Naturalness after LHC8. http://arxiv.org/abs/1307.7879 (2013)

  38. Giudice, G.F.: The dawn of the post-naturalness era. http://arxiv.org/abs/1710.07663 (2017)

  39. Giudice, G.F., Romanino, A.: Split supersymmetry. Nucl. Phys. B 699, 65–89 (2004)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  40. Giusti, L., Romanino, A., Strumia, A.: Natural ranges of supersymmetric signals. Nucl. Phys. B 550, 3–31 (1999)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  41. Grinbaum, A.: Which fine-tuning arguments are fine? Found. Phys. 42, 615–631 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  42. Guth, A.: Eternal inflation and its implications. J. Phys. A 40, 6811 (2007)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  43. Hall, L.J., Nomura, Y.: Evidence for the multiverse in the standard model and beyond. Phys. Rev. D 78, 035001 (2008)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  44. Hossenfelder, S.: To understand the foundations of physics, study numerology. http://backreaction.blogspot.com/2017/06/to-understand-foundations-of-physics.html (2017)

  45. Hossenfelder, S.: Screams for Explanation: Finetuning and Naturalness in the Foundations of Physics. https://arxiv.org/abs/1801.02176 (2018)

  46. Ibáñez, L.E., Uranga, A.M.: String Theory and Particle Physics: An Introduction to String Phenomenology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2012)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  47. Kummer, W., Segre, G.: A model of weak interactions mediated by scalar bosons. Nucl. Phys. 64, 585–592 (1965)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Landsman, N.P.: Large-mass and high-temperature behaviour in perturbative quantum field theory. Commun. Math. Phys. 125, 643–660 (1989)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  49. Manoukian, E.B.: Renormalization. Academic Press, Cambridge (1983)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  50. Murayama, H.: Supersymmetry Phenomenology. http://arxiv.org/abs/hep-ph/0002232 (2000)

  51. Ooguri, H., Vafa, C.: On the geometry of the string landscape and the swampland. Nucl. Phys. B 766, 21–33 (2007)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  52. Peskin, M.E., Schroeder, D.V.: An Introduction to Quantum Field Theory. Westview Press, Boulder (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  53. Richter, B.: Theory in particle physics: theological speculation versus practical knowledge. Phys. Today 59, 8–9 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Rosaler, J., Harlander, R.: Naturalness, Wilsonian Renormalization, and “Fundamental Parameters” in Quantum Field Theory (2018)

  55. Schellekens, A.N.: Life at the interface of particle physics and string theory. Rev. Mod. Phys. 85, 1491 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  56. Schweber, S.S.: QED and the Men Who Made It: Dyson, Feynman, Schwinger, and Tomonaga. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1994)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  57. Silverstein, E.: Counter-intuition and scalar masses. http://arxiv.org/abs/hep-th/0407202 (2004)

  58. Susskind, L.: Dynamics of spontaneous symmetry breaking in the Weinberg–Salam theory. Phys. Rev. D 20, 2619–25 (1979)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  59. Susskind, L.: Supersymmetry breaking in the anthropic landscape. In: Shifman, M., Vainshtein, A., Wheater, J. (eds.) From Fields to Strings: Circumnavigating Theoretical Physics: Ian Kogan Memorial Collection, pp. 1745–1749. World Scientific, Singapore (2005)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  60. ’t Hooft, G.: Naturalness, chiral symmetry, and spontaneous chiral symmetry breaking. In: ’t Hooft, G., Jaffe, A., Itzykson, C., Lehmann, H., Singer, P.K., Singer, I., Stora, R. (eds.) Recent Developments in Gauge Theories, pp. 135–157. Springer, Boston (1980)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  61. Vafa, C.: The string landscape and the swampland, arXiv preprint arXiv:hep-th/0509212 (2005)

  62. Terning, J.: Modern Supersymmetry: Dynamics and Duality. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2006)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  63. Veltman, M.: The infrared-ultraviolet connection. Acta Phys. Pol. B12, 437 (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  64. Weinberg, S.: Living in the multiverse. In: Carr, B. (ed.) Universe or Multiverse?, pp. 29–42. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2007)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  65. Weisskopf, V.F.: On the self-energy and the electromagnetic field of the electron. Phys. Rev. 56, 72 (1939)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  66. Wells, J.D.: Implications of Supersymmetry Breaking with a Little Hierarchy between Gauginos and Scalars. https://arxiv.org/abs/hep-ph/0306127 (2003)

  67. Wells, J.D.: PeV-scale supersymmetry. Phys. Rev. D 71, 015013 (2005)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  68. Wells, J.D.: The utility of naturalness, and how its application to quantum electrodynamics envisages the standard model and Higgs boson. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B 49, 102–108 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  69. Williams, P.: Naturalness, the autonomy of scales, and the 125 GeV Higgs. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B 51, 82–96 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  70. Wilson, K.G.: Renormalization group and strong interactions. Phys. Rev. D 3, 1818–46 (1971)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  71. Wilson, K.G.: The origins of lattice gauge theory. Nucl. Phys. B 140, 3–19 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  72. Zee, A.: Quantum Field Theory in a Nutshell. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2010)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Tony Duncan, Michael Miller, and an insightful referee for this journal for helpful comments on an earlier draft, and Greg Anderson and Diego Castaño for helpful correspondence about the motivation for the notion of naturalness they introduced in [3]. I would also like to thank audiences at the Aachen workshop “Naturalness, Hierarchy, and Fine-tuning,” the University of Michigan workshop “Foundations of Modern Physics: the Standard Model after the Discovery of the Higgs Boson,” and at Balliol College, Oxford for their valuable feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Porter Williams.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Williams, P. Two Notions of Naturalness. Found Phys 49, 1022–1050 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-018-0229-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-018-0229-1

Keywords

Navigation