Skip to main content
Log in

Causal Categories: Relativistically Interacting Processes

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A symmetric monoidal category naturally arises as the mathematical structure that organizes physical systems, processes, and composition thereof, both sequentially and in parallel. This structure admits a purely graphical calculus. This paper is concerned with the encoding of a fixed causal structure within a symmetric monoidal category: causal dependencies will correspond to topological connectedness in the graphical language. We show that correlations, either classical or quantum, force terminality of the tensor unit. We also show that well-definedness of the concept of a global state forces the monoidal product to be only partially defined, which in turn results in a relativistic covariance theorem. Except for these assumptions, at no stage do we assume anything more than purely compositional symmetric-monoidal categorical structure. We cast these two structural results in terms of a mathematical entity, which we call a causal category. We provide methods of constructing causal categories, and we study the consequences of these methods for the general framework of categorical quantum mechanics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In turn, the work by Hardy in [27, 28] and Chiribella-D’Ariano-Perinotti in [15, 16] is strongly influenced by CQM; in particular, by taking a diagrammatic language for processes as their starting point.

  2. The term ‘type’ reflects the application of category theory to theoretical computer science [5].

  3. On the other hand, their mathematical representations typically form non-strict symmetric monoidal categories; see again [21] for a discussion of this point.

  4. The symbolic language we define here is known as the internal language of a category. This involves using type theory to define the allowed syntactical constructs; see for example http://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/type+theory#CategoricalSemantics.

  5. Note that there is no ambiguity in our use of ‘σ’, since the generalized symmetry morphism σ is not annotated with objects (which are instead inferred from the composition in which they appear), unlike the symmetry isomorphism σ A,B .

References

  1. Abramsky, S.: No-cloning in categorical quantum mechanics. In: Mackie, I., Gay, S. (eds.) Semantic Techniques for Quantum Computation, pp. 1–28. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2009). arXiv:0910.2401

    Google Scholar 

  2. Abramsky, S., Coecke, B.: A categorical semantics of quantum protocols. In: Proceedings of 19th IEEE Conference on Logic in Computer Science, pp. 415–425. IEEE Press, New York (2004). arXiv:quant-ph/0402130

    Google Scholar 

  3. Abramsky, S., Tzevelekos, N.: Introduction to categories and categorical logic. In: Coecke, B. (ed.) New Structures for Physics. Lecture Notes in Physics, pp. 3–89. Springer, Berlin (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Aharonov, Y., Bergmann, P.G., Lebowitz, J.L.: Time symmetry in the quantum process of measurement. Phys. Rev. 134, B1410 (1964)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  5. Asperti, A., Longo, G.: Categories, Types, and Structures: an Introduction to Category Theory for the Working Computer Scientist. MIT Press, Cambridge (1991)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Baez, J.C.: Quantum quandaries: a category-theoretic perspective. In: Rickles, D., French, S., Saatsi, J.T. (eds.) The Structural Foundations of Quantum Gravity, pp. 240–266. Oxford University Press, London (2006). arXiv:quant-ph/0404040

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  7. Baez, J.C., Dolan, J.: Higher-dimensional algebra and topological quantum field theory. J. Math. Phys. 36, 6073–6105 (1995). arXiv:q-alg/9503002

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Baez, J.C., Stay, M.: Physics, topology, logic and computation: a Rosetta stone. In: Coecke, B. (ed.) New Structures for Physics. Lecture Notes in Physics, vol. 813, pp. 95–172. Springer, Berlin (2011). arXiv:0903.0340

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  9. Birkhoff, G., von Neumann, J.: The logic of quantum mechanics. Ann. Math. 37, 823–843 (1936)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Blute, R., Ivanov, I.T., Panangaden, P.: Discrete quantum causal dynamics. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 42, 2025–2041 (2003). arXiv:gr-qc/0109053

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Bohm, D.J.: Time, the implicate order and pre-space. In: Griffin, D.R. (ed.) Physics and the Ultimate Significance of Time, pp. 172–208. SUNY Press, Albany (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Bohm, D.J., Hiley, B.J.: Generalization of the twistor to Clifford algebras as a basis for geometry. In: Volume Especial, Os 70 anos de Mario Schönberg, pp. 1–26 (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Bohm, D.J., Davies, P.G., Hiley, B.J.: Algebraic quantum mechanics and pre-geometry, draft paper (1982). Was published In: Adenier, G., Krennikov, A.-Y., Nieuwenhuizen, T.M. (eds.) Quantum Theory: Reconsiderations of Foundations, vol. 3, pp. 314–324, Växjö, Sweden. AIP, New York (2006)

  14. Bohr, N.: Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge. Science Editions, New York (1961)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Chiribella, G., D’Ariano, G.M., Perinotti, P.: Probabilistic theories with purification. Phys. Rev. A 81, 062348 (2010). arXiv:0908.1583

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  16. Chiribella, G., D’Ariano, G.M., Perinotti, P.: Informational derivation of quantum theory. Phys. Rev. A 84, 012311 (2011). arXiv:1011.6451

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  17. Choi, M.-D.: Completely positive maps on complex matrices. Linear Algebra Appl. 10, 285–290 (1975)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Coecke, B.: Quantum picturalism. Contemp. Phys. 51, 59–83 (2010). arXiv:0908.1787

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  19. Coecke, B.: A universe of processes and some of its guises. In: Halvorson, H. (ed.) Deep Beauty: Understanding the Quantum World through Mathematical Innovation, pp. 128–186. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2011). arXiv:1009.3786

    Google Scholar 

  20. Coecke, B., Duncan, R.: Interacting quantum observables: categorical algebra and diagrammatics. New J. Phys. 13, 043016 (2011). arXiv:0906.4725

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  21. Coecke, B., Paquette, E.O.: Categories for the practicing physicist. In: Coecke, B. (ed.) New Structures for Physics. Lecture Notes in Physics, vol. 813, pp. 173–286. Springer, Berlin (2011). arXiv:0905.3010

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  22. Coecke, B., Pavlovic, D.: Quantum measurements without sums. In: Chen, G., Kauffman, L., Lamonaco, S. (eds.) Mathematics of Quantum Computing and Technology, pp. 567–604. Taylor & Francis London (2007). arXiv:quant-ph/0608035

    Google Scholar 

  23. Coecke, B., Perdrix, S.: Environment and classical channels in categorical quantum mechanics. In: Proceedings of the 19th EACSL Annual Conference on Computer Science Logic (CSL). Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 6247. Springer, Berlin (2010). arXiv:1004.1598

    Google Scholar 

  24. Coecke, B., Edwards, B., Spekkens, R.W.: Phase groups and the origin of non-locality for qubits. Electron. Notes Theor. Comput. Sci. 270(2), 15–36 (2010). arXiv:1003.5005

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Duncan, R., Perdrix, S.: Rewriting measurement-based quantum computations with generalised flow. In: Proceedings of the 37th International Colloquium on Automata, Languages and Programming (ICALP). Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 6199. Springer, Berlin (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Haag, R., Kastler, D.: An algebraic approach to quantum field theory. J. Math. Phys. 5, 848–861 (1964)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Hardy, L.: 2010, A formalism-local framework for general probabilistic theories including quantum theory. arXiv:1005.5164

  28. Hardy, L.: Foliable operational structures for general probabilistic theories. In: Halvorson, H. (ed.) Deep Beauty: Understanding the Quantum World Through Mathematical Innovation, pp. 409–442. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2011). arXiv:0912.4740

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  29. Hiley, B.J.: Process, distinction, groupoids and Clifford algebras: an alternative view of the quantum formalism. In: Coecke, B. (ed.) New Structures for Physics. Lecture Notes in Physics, vol. 813, pp. 705–752. Springer, Berlin (2010).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  30. Isham, C.: 2002, Some Reflections on the status of conventional quantum theory when applied to quantum gravity. Talk presented at Stephen Hawking’s 60th birthday symposium. arXiv:quant-ph/0206090

  31. Jamiolkowski, A.: Linear transformations which preserve trace and positive semidefiniteness of operators. Rep. Math. Phys. 3(4), 275–278 (1972)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  32. Johnstone, P.T.: The point of pointless topology. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 8, 41–53 (1983)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  33. Joyal, A., Street, R.: The geometry of tensor calculus I. Adv. Math. 88, 55–112 (1991)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Kelly, G.M., Laplaza, M.L.: Coherence for compact closed categories. J. Pure Appl. Algebra 19, 193–213 (1980)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  35. Kronheimer, E.H., Penrose, R.: On the structure of causal spaces. Math. Proc. Camb. Philos. Soc. 63, 481–501 (1967)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  36. Lal, R., Panangaden, P.: (in preparation) A category of Feynman propagators

  37. Lambek, J., Scott, P.J.: Higher Order Categorical Logic. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1986)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  38. Ludwig, G.: An Axiomatic Basis of Quantum Mechanics. 1. Derivation of Hilbert Space. Springer, Berlin (1985)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  39. Ludwig, G.: An Axiomatic Basis of Quantum Mechanics. 2. Quantum Mechanics and Macrosystems. Springer, Berlin (1987)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  40. Mackey, G.W.: Quantum mechanics and Hilbert space. Am. Math. Mon. 64, 45–57 (1957)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  41. Malament, D.B.: The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime. J. Math. Phys. 18, 1399–1404 (1977)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  42. Marcovitch, S., Reznik, B., Vaidman, L.: Quantum-mechanical realization of a Popescu-Rohrlich box. Phys. Rev. A 75, 022102 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  43. Markopoulou, F.: Quantum causal histories. Class. Quantum Gravity 17, 2059–2077 (2000). arXiv:hep-th/9904009

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  44. Martin, K., Panangaden, P.: A domain of spacetime intervals in general relativity. Commun. Math. Phys. 267, 563–586 (2006)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  45. Penrose, R.: Applications of negative dimensional tensors. In: Welsh, D. (ed.) Combinatorial Mathematics and Its Applications, pp. 221–244. Academic Press, New York (1971)

    Google Scholar 

  46. Rédei, M.: Why John von Neumann did not like the Hilbert space formalism of quantum mechanics (and what he liked instead). Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 27, 493–510 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Schrödinger, E.: Discussion of probability relations between separated systems. Proc. Camb. Philos. Soc. 31, 555–563 (1935)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  48. Selinger, P.: Dagger compact closed categories and completely positive maps. Electron. Notes Theor. Comput. Sci. 170, 139–163 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  49. Selinger, P.: A survey of graphical languages for monoidal categories. In: Coecke, B. (ed.) New Structures for Physics. Lecture Notes in Physics, vol. 813, pp. 289–356. Springer, Berlin (2011). arXiv:0908.3347

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  50. Selinger, P.: Finite dimensional Hilbert spaces are complete for dagger compact closed categories. Electron. Notes Theor. Comput. Sci. 270(2), 113–119 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Sorkin, R.D.: Causal sets: discrete gravity (notes for the Valdivia summer school). In: Gomberoff, A., Marolf, D. (eds.) Lectures on Quantum Gravity (Proceedings of the Valdivia Summer School). Plenum, New York (2005). arXiv:gr-qc/0309009

    Google Scholar 

  52. Vicary, J.: A categorical framework for the quantum harmonic oscillator. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 47, 3408–3447 (2008). arXiv:0706.0711

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  53. von Neumann, J.: Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik. Springer, Berlin (1932) (English translation: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press (1955))

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  54. Whitehead, A.N.: Process and Reality. Harper & Row, New York (1957)

    Google Scholar 

  55. Zeeman, E.C.: Causality implies the Lorentz group. J. Math. Phys. 5, 490–493 (1964)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bob Coecke.

Appendix

Appendix

In this Appendix we expand on the assumptions made at the end of Sect. 2.1, that symbolic formulae are stated up to equivalence in the diagrammatic calculus. Our aim is to show how connectedness in the graphical language can be formalised symbolically.

The motivation for this is as follows. Firstly we recall from Sect. 2.1 that graphical connectedness distinguishes the two modes of composition symbolically, except when the tensor unit is involved. However, the two modes of composition have different, complementary, physical interpretations: parallel composition means independence. But, as we showed in Sect. 3.1, graphical disconnectedness also means independence. Since graphical disconnectedness subsumes parallel composition (as we just described), it also is the primary concept of independence. But the graphical language arose in a formal way from considering SMCs (see Theorem 4), which is usually defined symbolically. Hence it is desirable to understand what kind of symbolic language corresponds to this graphical language of connectedness: this will provide a ‘syntax for information flow’.

In other words, we want to ‘fix’ the language so that formulae faithfully reflect the connectedness of a corresponding diagram.

Standing Assumptions About Formulae

Since it is the non-atomic morphisms that would allow one to ‘hide’ disconnectedness, our two key standing assumptions in Sect. 2.1 were:

  1. 1.

    all morphism formulae contain only atomic morphisms;

  2. 2.

    a morphism is expressed as a formula using ⊗ instead of ∘ whenever possible.

This corresponds to:

  1. 1.

    ensuring that the ‘atoms’ of our language are connected morphisms, so that sequential composition corresponds to genuine information-flow

  2. 2.

    revealing genuine disconnectedness of a morphism in its corresponding formula (i.e. a formula reveals non-atomicity of the morphism).

In short, we force the syntax of the morphism language to faithfully represent the topology of the graphical language.

Remark 21

(Morphism language formulae containing only atomic morphisms)

Note that the assumption that all formulae contain only atomic morphisms can be made without any loss of generality, because we only consider protocols that involve a finite number of systems. An arbitrary formula can be turned into one made up of atomic morphisms simply by substituting all non-atomic morphisms by a non-trivial parallel composition, and repeat this procedure until all morphisms are atomic. Without finiteness this procedure may not terminate. This can be seen as a formally distinguishing between the following two views on the relation between a system and its subsystems. This first view is ‘compositional’: we describe a system by considering jointly its subsystems, and the latter are conceptually prior. Conversely, the second view is ‘decompositional’: Nature appears to us as a single entity, and we can tractably do physics by decomposing it into subsystems; now the global system is conceptually prior.

Definition 49

(‘Disconnectedness’ for symbolic language)

We say that a symbolic language expression \(\mathcal{F}:\mathcal {A}\rightarrow\mathcal{B}\) factors through ⊗ if, by pre- and post-composition of generalized symmetry morphisms and by using the axioms of SMCs, \(\mathcal{F}\) cannot be rewritten as a symbolic language expression \(\mathcal{F}_{1}\otimes\mathcal{F}_{2}\).

For example, given ⊤:BI and ψ:IB, the expression (gf)⊗(ψ⊗⊤) does not factor through ⊗, whereas the expression (1 I ψ)∘(⊤⊗1 I ) does, because the axioms of SMCs ensure that

$$(1_I\otimes\psi)\circ(\top\otimes1_I) =(1_I\circ\top)\otimes(\psi\circ1_I).$$

Note that Definition 49 captures a notion that is distinct from non-atomicity, since the latter refers to whether a morphism is equal to the tensor of two other morphisms (and is therefore about the contingent equations of the category), whereas the former refers to whether a morphism formula can be manipulated syntactically to a particular form, using the axioms of symmetric monoidal categories. The requirement of pre- and post-composition in Definition 49 is included because of morphisms such as the symmetry isomorphism σ A,B :ABBA. This will be symbolically disconnected because post-composition with σ B,A yields 1 A ⊗1 B .

Theorem 50

(Relationship between symbolic and graphical connectedness)

Given the standing assumptions above, the topological disconnectedness of a morphism in the graphical language is equivalent to its corresponding symbolic language expression factoring through ⊗.

Proof

This follows by Theorem 4 [33], which states that the graphical calculus corresponds fully and faithfully to the syntactic manipulations of the corresponding symbolic language expressions. □

The significance of Theorem 50 is that it provides a formal expression of ‘reading the topology from the syntax’, i.e. with the assumptions above, the syntax of ⊗ in an expression in the symbolic language corresponds to topological disconnectedness when translated to the graphical language.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Coecke, B., Lal, R. Causal Categories: Relativistically Interacting Processes. Found Phys 43, 458–501 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-012-9646-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-012-9646-8

Keywords

Navigation