Skip to main content
Log in

The time limit on copyright: an unlikely tragedy of the intellectual commons

  • Published:
European Journal of Law and Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

With their “tragedy of the commons” paradigm for intellectual property, Landes and Posner argue that the most important benefit of intellectual property rights is not that they generate incentives to create new works, but that they ensure the efficient exploitation of existing intellectual works. This alternative economic case for IP notably relies on the argument that allowing the copyright on certain massively popular works to expire could lead to their overexploitation, generating negative externalities similar to congestion externalities. This article will assess in detail the plausibility of this effect, by reviewing its most plausible interpretations: a boredom effect, a “blurring” or “tarnishment” effect, a snob effect, or a decrease in product diversity. I will argue that while Landes and Posner’s argument is ultimately inconclusive and unverified by the current state of empirical research, it also raises greater challenges than has usually been thought. Moreover, taking their argument seriously can also contribute to a better understanding of the purposes and limits of an intellectual property regime.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here I will use the expression “intellectual property” to denote only the exclusive rights in information such as copyright, patents and trademarks, and not the subject-matter itself.

  2. Cf. for example Sterk (2005), or Netanel (2003).

  3. Let us note that the various chapters of the Economic Structure of Intellectual property make no particular mention of Posner’s controversial wealth maximization theory, but borrows from on a more conventional welfarist language, which I shall likewise adopt in this paper for the sake of the discussion.

  4. For other skeptical takes on these theories, see notably: Waldron (1993), Schroeder (2005), Attas (2008), Lambrecht (2015).

  5. Cf. Posner (1998, 37) citing W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England (1766), p. 7: «who would be at the pains of tilling [the earth], if another might watch an opportunity to seize upon and enjoy the product of his industry, art, and labour? Had not therefore a separate property in lands, as well as moveables, been vested in some individuals, the world must have continued a forest, and men have been mere animals of prey».

  6. In his seminal article “Toward a Theory of Property Rights”, Demsetz introduce the idea that the primary function of property rights is to guide incentives to internalize of externalities, and develops a positive theory of the emergence of property rights, based on the anthropological account of the link between the development of property rights and the emergence of the fur trade among the Montagnais-Naskapi native people in the North of Québec.

  7. In this landmark case, the US Supreme court famously upheld the constitutionality of the 1998 Copyright Term Extension Act: US Supreme Court, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186.

  8. Besides from the congestion externalities, they also put forward a second argument, which I will not discuss here, arguing that IP rights can be useful generate proper incentives for the maintenance of existing works.

  9. Somewhat surprisingly, Landes and Posner also argue that public domain works could also suffer from the opposite phenomenon, namely under-exploitation. We will not consider this argument in this paper, as it has already been more than adequately discussed in previous works. See e.g. Heald (2008), or Lemley (2004), p. 136: “Is there some greater need to subsidize the making of more copies Ulysses than the making of more paper clips? It is hard to see why; in both cases, once an intellectual property right expires, many companies can compete to make the good, and they will do so only so long as they can manufacture and distribute it for less money than people will pay to buy it. This doubtless means that some inefficient manufacturers will stop selling Ulysses (or paper clips), but that should not worry us. Indeed, if we believe in the market economy, it should delight us”.

  10. In the same sense, cf. also Buccafusco and Heald (2013, 32).

  11. Although individual patterns often largely differ from this average pattern (Hunter 2011, 49), but these variations are not directly relevant from the perspective of aggregate welfare.

  12. Admittedly, such adjustment will be less immediate than the “good husbandry” of the IP owner, but this only underlines the difference in output planning under competition or under monopoly.

  13. This point is emphasized by Karjala (2005, 1072).

  14. See above, Sect. 3.

  15. Cf. references in Landes and Posner (2003, 223 p. 226 and p. 159, note 24).

  16. Such as the famous Air Pirates comic strips, at the center of the US case “Walt Disney Productions v. Air Pirates”, 581 F.2d 751 (9th Cir. 1978).

  17. This argument has been made to criticize the ruling (against) Air Pirates: “Air Pirate Funnies is an adult magazine with a clearly different purpose and audience than Disney’s. Someone interested in reading a Disney comic book would not turn to Air Pirate Funnies instead, and vice versa. Both publications perform different functions and have different markets. Therefore, the fair use defense should be permitted” (Totah 1987). Cf. also Hughes (1998, 985).

  18. Although it is unclear whether these illustrations are intended to exemplify the tarnishment effect or the boredom effect.

  19. This is inspired by an argument made by Buccafusco and Heald (2013, 45).

  20. Liebowitz and Margolis (2005, 450).

  21. Let us note that they also discuss the converse underuse hypothesis made by Landes and Posner, but as we already stated supra, note 9, this paper is only interested in the “overgrazing” argument.

  22. Cf. notably Breyer (1970), Abramowicz (2011), Merges (2011).

  23. Cf. Landes and Posner (2003, pp. 16–21).

References

  • Abramowicz, M. (2011). A new uneasy case for copyright. George Washington Law Review, 79(6), 2013–2087.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aldred, J. (2010). Copyright and the limits of law-and-economics analysis. In L. Bently, J. Davis, & J. C. Ginsburg (Eds.), Copyright and piracy: An interdisciplinary critique. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, C. (2008). The long tail (Revised ed.). Paris: Hachette Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Attas, D. (2008). Lockean justifications of intellectual property. Intellectual Property and Theories of Justice (pp. 29–56). Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benkler, Y. (1999). Free as the air to common use: First amendment constraints on enclosure of the public domain. New York University Law Review, 74, 354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boldrin, M., & Levine, D. K. (2009). Market structure and property rights in open source industries. Washington University Journal of Law and Policy, 30, 325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bornstein, R. F. (1989). Exposure and affect: Overview and meta-analysis of research, 1968–1987. Psychological Bulletin, 106(2), 265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breyer, S. (1970). The uneasy case for copyright: A study of copyright in books, photocopies, and computer programs. Harvard Law Review, 84(2), 281–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bu, W., Buccafusco, C., & Heald P. J. (2016). Testing tarnishment in trademark and copyright law: The effect of pornographic versions of protected marks and works. University Washington Law Review.

  • Buccafusco, C., & Heald, P. J. (2013). Do bad things happen when works enter the public domain: Empirical tests of copyright term extension. Berkeley Technology Law Journal, 28, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D., & Picciotto, S. (2006). The acceptable face of intervention: intellectual property in Posnerian law and economics. Social and Legal Studies, 15(3), 455–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demsetz, H. (1967). Toward a theory of property rights. The American Economic Review, 57(2), 347–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demsetz, H. (1969). Information and efficiency: Another viewpoint. Journal of Law and Economics, 12(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eveleth, R. (2014). The Star Wars George Lucas Doesn't Want You To See. The Atlantic. Aug. 27. http://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2014/08/the-star-wars-george-lucas-doesnt-want-you-tosee/379184/.

  • Federation of European Publishers. (2015). European Book Publishing Statistics 2013. http://www.fep-fee.eu/European-Book-Publishing-636

  • Frischmann, B. M. (2008). Evaluating the Demsetzian trend in copyright law. Review of Law and Economics, 3(3), 649–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, P. (1994). Copyright’s highway. New York: Hill & Wang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162(3859), 1243–1248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hargreaves, I. (2011). Digital opportunity: A review of intellectual property and growth: An independent report. London: UK Intellectual Property Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heald, P. J. (2008). Property rights and the efficient exploitation of copyrighted works: An empirical analysis of public domain and copyrighted fiction bestsellers. Minnesota Law Review, 92(4), 1031–1063.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heald, P. J. (2009). Does the song remain the same? An empirical study of bestselling musical compositions (1913–1932) and their use in cinema (1968–2007). Case Western Reserve Law Review, 60(1), 1–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Himma, K. (2013). The legitimacy of protecting intellectual property rights: The irrelevance of two conceptions of an information commons. Journal of Information, Communication and Ethics in Society, 11(4), 210–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, J. (1998). Recoding intellectual property and overlooked audience interests. Texas Law Review, 77, 923.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunter, P. G. (2011). The malleability of music preferences: Effects of individual differences and the listening context (Doctoral dissertation, University of Toronto).

  • Karjala, D. S. (1998). Statement of Copyright and Intellectual Property Law Professors in Opposition to H.R. 604, H.R. 2589, and S. 505, The Copyright Term Extension Act, Sub-mitted to the Joint Committees of the Judiciary. http://www.public.asu.edu/jdkarjala/legmats/1998statement/html

  • Karjala, D. S. (2005). Congestion externalities and extended copyright protection. Georgetown Law Journal, 94, 1065.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitch, E. W. (1977). The nature and function of the patent system. The Journal of Law and Economics, 20(2), 265–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F. (1924). Some fallacies in the interpretation of social cost. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 38(4), 582–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laffont, J.-J. (2008). Externalities. In S. N. Durlauf & L. E. Blume (Eds.) The New Palgrave dictionary of economics (2nd ed.). Palgrave Macmillan. http://www.dictionaryofeconomics.com/article?id=pde2008_E000200. Accessed 24 Mar 2016.

  • Lambrecht, M. (2015). On water drinkers and magical springs: Challenging the Lockean proviso as a justification for copyright. Ratio Juris, 28(4), 504–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landes, W. M., & Posner, R. A. (1989). An economic analysis of copyright law. The Journal of Legal Studies, 18(2), 325–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landes, W., & Posner, R. A. (2003). The economic structure of intellectual property. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemley, M. A. (2004) Ex ante versus ex post justifications for intellectual property. The University of Chicago Law Review, 71(1), 129–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemley, M. A. (2005). Property, intellectual property, and free riding. Texas Law Review, 83, 1031–1075.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liebowitz, S. J., & Margolis, S. E. (2005). Seventeen famous economists weigh in on copyright: The role of theory, empirics, and network effects. Harvard Journal of Law and Technology, 18(2), 435–457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merges, R. P. (2011). Justifying intellectual property. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Netanel, N. W. (1996). Copyright and a democratic civil society. The Yale Law Journal, 106(2), 283–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Netanel, N. W. (2003). Impose a noncommercial use levy to allow free peer-to-peer file sharing. As published in Harvard Journal of Law & Technology, 17.

  • Posner, R. A. (1998). Economic analysis of law (5th ed.). New York: Aspen Law & Business.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. A. (2005). Intellectual property: The law and economics approach. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19(2), 57–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, E. G., Peretz, I., & Vieillard, S. (2008). Liking for happy-and sad-sounding music: Effects of exposure. Cognition and Emotion, 22(2), 218–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, J. L. (2005). Unnatural rights: Hegel and intellectual property. University of Miami Law Review, 60, 453.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterk, S. E. (2005). Intellectualizing property: The tenuous connections between land and copyright. Washington University Law Quarterly, 83, 417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorpe, J. (2004). Some challenges for copyright-related quantification. Review of Economic Research on Copyright Issues, 1(1), 41–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Totah, S. J. (1987). Copyright law-in defense of parody. Golden Gate University Law Review, 17, 57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tushnet, R. (1997). Legal fictions: Copyright, fan fiction, and a new common law. Loyola of Los Angeles Entertainment Law Journal, 17, 651.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tushnet, R. (2005) Indefinitely Renewable Copyright: Batman versus the Utility Monster. Rebecca Tushnet’s 43(B)log. http://tushnet.blogspot.be/2005/08/indefinitely-renewable-copyright.html

  • Waldron, J. (1993). From authors to copiers: Individual rights and social values in intellectual property. Chicago-Kent Law Review, 68, 841–887.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zajonc, R. B., Crandall, R., Kail, R. V., & Swap, W. (1974). Effect of extreme exposure frequencies on different affective ratings of stimuli. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 38(2), 667–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author wishes to thank Alain Marciano for his precious feedback on an earlier draft of this article, Tim Meijers and Thomas Ferretti for their helpful comments and careful reading, and the anonymous peer reviewers for their constructive criticisms and excellent suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maxime Lambrecht.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lambrecht, M. The time limit on copyright: an unlikely tragedy of the intellectual commons. Eur J Law Econ 43, 475–494 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-016-9538-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-016-9538-z

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation