Skip to main content
Log in

Codecision procedure biais: the European legislation game

  • Published:
European Journal of Law and Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The European Union’s codecision procedure is analyzed as a bargaining game between the Council and the European Parliament. The model shows that the policy outcome is biased towards the ideal point of the institution that is closest to the status quo, when the negotiation leads to an agreement. If the Council’s ideal policy is closer to the status quo, as is the case for example concerning the duration of maternity leave, the resulting policy will remain closer to the Council’s than to the European Parliament’s position. Furthermore, the result of the codecision procedure is Kaldor–Hicks inefficient. The developments of common policies concerning asylum, fishery and maternity leave illustrate both the possibility of the failure of negotiations and the influence of the Council on the outcome.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Treaty of the Functioning of the European Union, TFEU, Article 294. Codecision between the European Parliament and the Council of Ministers was initially established by the Maastricht Treaty (entered into force on 1 November 1993) and extended and adapted by the Treaty of Amsterdam (entered into force on 1 May 1999) and the Treaty of Nice (entered into force on 1 February 2003).

  2. For a review of power indices, see Napel and Widgrén (2011) and B. Steunenberg, D. Schmidtchen, On the Possibility of a Preference-based Power Index: The Strategic Power Index Revisited, paper presented at the Leverhulme Trust sponsored Voting Power in Practice Symposium held at the London School of Economics, 20–22 March 2011. Available at http://www2.lse.ac.uk/CPNSS/projects/VPP/VPPpdf/VPPpdf_Symposium2011/Schmidtchen.pdf.

  3. See for example Widgrén (2009); Napel and Widgrén (2006) and Barr and Passarelli (2009).

  4. For a review of the spatial models, see Hoerl et al. (2005).

  5. See Farrel and Héritier (2003), Shackleton and Tapio (2003) and Häge and Kaeding (2007). In its activity report, the European Parliament also finds that the Parliament benefits from the conciliation procedure: it gains bargaining power because it has a stable leadership, whereas the Council delegation’s leadership rotates. See European Parliament (2009) Activity Report 1 May to 13 July 2009 (6th parliamentary term) of the delegations to the Conciliation Committee. Available at http://www.europarl.europa.eu.

  6. B. Steunenberg, A. Dimitrova, Interests, Legitimacy, and Constitutional Choice: The extension of the codecision procedure in Amsterdam, Mimeo, 1999. Available at http://www.essex.ac.uk/ecpr/events/jointsessions/paperarchive/mannheim/w27/Steunenberg.PDF.

  7. See for example Kasack (2004) and Tsebelis and Yataganas (2002), Tsebelis (2002) and Giuriato (2009).

  8. See Official Journal of the European Union, Joint declaration on practical arrangements for the codecision procedure (Article 251 of the EC Treaty), 2008/C 115/47, 09.05.2008.

  9. See Official Journal (2007), Joint declaration on practical arrangements for the codecision procedure (Article 251 of the EC Treaty), (2007/C 145/02), 30.6.2007, point 7. In particular, trilogues take place after the EP first reading vote and before the adoption of the Council position. In the case of success, the Council position can be adopted at the second reading by the EP without further amendments (“early second reading agreement”).

  10. See also Farrel and Héritier (2003) on the greater vulnerability of the Council to political failures.

  11. For a discussion of the Council position, see Napel and Widgrén (2008).

  12. Note that all other things equal, the optimal standard \(x_{CM}^{\ast}\) of CM corresponds to the standard that would have been adopted by the Council under the former decision making procedure. However, this does not imply that x CM  = q, because the Council composition can have changed over time, and because q might result from a former codecision procedure.

  13. There is no time limit on the first reading stage.

  14. See Commission of the European Union (2009), The Co-decision procedure (art.251 TEU): Analysis and statistics of the 2004–2009 Legislature. Available at http://ec.europa.eu/codecision/statistics/docs/report_statistics_public%_draft_en.pdf. This can be interpreted as an anticipation of the conciliation outcome.

  15. Unanimity is required in the special case in which the Commission cannot accept the amendment introduced into its proposal.

  16. This is also the hypothesis made by Napel and Widgrén (2006).

  17. Recall that q is not defined on \([x_{CM}^{\ast},x_{EP}^{\ast}]\) since for any q on \([x_{CM}^{\ast},x_{EP}^{\ast}]\) there is no bargaining set.

  18. With ϕ CM  = 0.6 and ϕ EP  = 0.7.

  19. We have not assumed that making a proposal implies a cost for EC. Also, we have not taken possible gains from launching the procedure, such as reputational gains, into account.

  20. See for example Cooter and Drexl (1994) and Tsebelis and Yataganas (2002).

  21. For example, Cyprus’ Interior Minister Neoklis Sylikiotis is quoted as saying that “ if EU members refused to work together, the European Court of Justice would be left to wade into asylum issues” ECRE (2012). The ECJ has indeed passed judgements invalidating EU asylum law. See Court of Justice of the European Union (2011), Press Release No. 140/11.

References

  • Banzhaf, J. F. (1965). Weighted voting doesn’t work: A mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Review, 19, 317–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barr, J., & Passarelli F. (2009). Who has power in the EU?. Mathematical Social Sciences, 57, 339–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K., Rubinstein, A., Wolinsky, A. (1986). The nash bargaining solution in economic modelling. The RAND Journal of Economics, 17(2), 176–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooter, R., & Drexl, J. (1994). The logic of power in the emerging european constitution: Game theory and the division of powers. International Review of Law and Economics, 14, 307–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crombez, C. (2000). Institutional reform and codecision in the European Union. Constitutional Political Economy, 11(1), 41–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ECRE (2012). Ecre weekly bulletin. 27 January 2012.

  • Farrel, H., & Héritier, A. (2003). Codecision and institutional change. West European Politics, 30(2), 285–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, G., & Tsebelis G. (2001). Understanding better the EU legislative process. European Union Politics, 2(3), 353–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giuriato, L. (2009). Reforming the EU budgetary procedure: Is codecision a step forward?. CESifo Economic Studies, 55(1), 57–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Häge, F., & Kaeding, M. (2007). Reconsidering the European Parliament’s legislative influence: Formal versus informal procedures. European Integration, 29(3), 341–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl, B., Warntjen, B. A., & Wonka, A. (2005). Built on quicksand? A decade of procedural spatial models on EU legislative decision-making. Journal of European Public Policy, 12(3), 592–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kasack, C. (2004). The legislative impact of the European Parliament under the revised co–decision procedure. European Union Politics, 5(2), 241–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • König, T., Lindberg, B., Lechner, S., Pohlmeier, W. (2007). Bicameral conflict resolution in the European Union: An empirical analysis of conciliation committee bargains. British Journal of Political Science, 37, 281–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mattila, T. M., & J. -E. Lane (2001). Why unanimity in the Council? A roll call analysis of council voting. European Union Politics, 2, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muthoo, A. (1999). Bargaining theory with applications. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Napel, S., & Widgrén, M. (2004). Power measurement as sensitivity analysis—a unified approach. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 16(4), 517–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Napel, S. & Widgrén, M. (2005). The possibility of a preference-based power index. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 17(3), 377–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Napel, S., & Widgrén, M. (2006). The inter-institutional distribution of power in EU codecision. Social Choice and Welfare, 27(1), 129–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Napel, S. & Widgrén, M. (2008). The European Commission—appointment, preferences and institutional relations. Public Choice, 137(1), 21–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Napel, S., & Widgrén, M. (2011). Strategic versus non-strategic voting power in the EU Council of Minister: The consultation procedure. Social Choice and Welfare, 37(3), 511–541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Passarelli, F., & Barr, J. (2007). Preferences, the agenda setter, and the distribution of power in the EU. Social Choice and Welfare, 28, 41–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shackleton, M., & Tapio, R. (2003). Codecision since amsterdam: A laboratory for institutional innovation and change. Journal of European Public Policy, 10(2), 171–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley, L.S., & Shubik, M. (1954). A method for evaluating the distribution of power in a committee system. American Political Science Review, 48(2), 787–792.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steunenberg, B., Schmidtchen, D., Koboldt, C. (1999). Strategic power in the European Union: Evaluating the distribution of power in policy games. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 11(3), 339–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsebelis, G. (2002). Veto players: How political institutions work. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsebelis, G., & Garrett, G. (1996). Agenda setting power, power indices and decision making in the European Union. International Review of Law and Economics, 16, 345–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsebelis, G. & Garrett, G. (2000). Legislative politics in the European Union. European Union Politics, 1(1), 9–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsebelis, G., & Yataganas, X. (2002). Veto players and decisionmaking in the EU after Nice: Policy stability and judicial/bureaucratic discretion. Journal of Common Market Studies, 40(2), 283–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Widgrén, M. (2009). The impact of council voting rules on EU decision-making. CESifo Economic Studies, 55(1), 30–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank François Fontaine, Nuno Garoupa, Pierre Picard, the partcipants of the RESET seminar at the University of Luxembourg, Dieter Schmidtchen, the audiences at the annual meeting of the European Association of Law and Economics (Paris, 2010) and at the annual meeting of the European Public Choice Society (Rennes 2011) for insightful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marie Obidzinski.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of proposition 1

Solving the program (1) is equivalent to solving the following equation:

$$ A {{}^2} {x {{}^2} +(2AC-B {{}^2} )x+C {{}^2} =0} $$
(2)

with

$$ \begin{aligned} A &=2\phi _{EP}\phi _{CM} \\ B &=(\phi _{EP}+\phi _{CM})\frac{3}{2}-2\phi _{EP}\phi _{CM}\sqrt{q}\\ C &=1-\frac{\phi _{EP}+\phi _{CM}}{2}\sqrt{q}\\ \end{aligned} $$

The determinant of the equation is positive for all \(q\varepsilon \lbrack 0,x_{CM}^{\ast}]\cup \lbrack x_{EP}^{\ast},1]\) with \(x_{CM}^{\ast}=\frac{1}{4\phi _{CM}^{2}}\) and \(x_{EP}^{\ast}=\frac{1}{4\phi _{EP}^{2}}.\)

$$ \bar{x}_{1}=\frac{-{2AC+B {{}^2} (1}-\sqrt{(B^{2}-4AC)})}{2A {{}^2}} $$
(3)

Therefore, Eq. (3) has two solutions. The relevant one necessarily belongs to the bargaining set \(S=[x_{CM}^{\ast},x_{EP}^{\ast}]\). For all \(q<x_{CM}^{\ast},\) we find that \(\bar{x}_{1}=\frac{-(2AC-B{{}^2})-\sqrt{\Updelta}}{2A{{}^2}}\) is always the relevant solution. For all \(q>x_{EP}^{\ast},\) \(\bar{x}_{2}=\frac{-(2AC-B{{}^2})+\sqrt{\Updelta}}{2A{{}^2}}\) is always the relevant solution.

We show that \(x_{EP}^{\ast}+x_{CM}^{\ast}-2\bar{x}_{1}>0\) when q = 0. In other words, \(\bar{x}_{1}\) is lower than the middle of the interval \([x_{CM}^{\ast},x_{EP}^{\ast}].\) Furthermore, we know that \(\bar{x}_{1}=x_{CM}^{\ast}\) if \(q=x_{CM}^{\ast}.\) Deriving \(\bar{x}_{1}\) with respect to q, we show that \(\frac{d\bar{x}_{1}}{dq}<0\) on [0,1].

Indeed,

$$ \frac{d\bar{x}_{1}}{dq}=\frac{1}{32c {{}^2} e {{}^2} }[\frac{2ec(E+4ce\sqrt{q}-3c-3e)(E-4ce\sqrt{q}-c-e)}{\sqrt{q}E}] $$

with \(E=\sqrt{16c{{}^2}e{{}^2}q-8c{{}^2}e \sqrt{q}+9c{{}^2}-8ce{{}^2}\sqrt{q}-14ce+9e{{}^2}},\) and \(E+4ce\sqrt{q}-3c-3e<0\) and \(E+4ce\sqrt{q}-c-e>0\) for all \(q\in \lbrack 0,1],0<e<c<1\).

Furthermore, we obtain that \(x_{EP}^{\ast}+x_{CM}^{\ast}-2\bar{x}_{2}>0\) when q = 1 and

$$ \frac{d\bar{x}_{2}}{dq}=\frac{1}{32c {{}^2} e {{}^2}} [-\frac{2ec(-E+4ce\sqrt{q}-3c-3e)(-E-4ce\sqrt{q}-c-e)}{\sqrt{q}E}] $$

with \(-E+4ce\sqrt{q}-3c-3e<0\) and \(-E+4ce\sqrt{q}-c-e<0\) for \(q\in \lbrack 0,1],0<e<c<1\).

Even at the extremities q = 0 and q = 1, there exists a biais toward q. □

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Helstroffer, J., Obidzinski, M. Codecision procedure biais: the European legislation game. Eur J Law Econ 38, 29–46 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-013-9383-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-013-9383-2

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation