Skip to main content
Log in

Individual Actions and Corporate Moral Responsibility: A (Reconstituted) Kantian Approach

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper examines the resources of Kantian ethics to establish corporate moral responsibility. I defend Matthew Altman’s claim that Kantian ethics cannot hold corporations morally responsible for corporate malfeasance. Rather than following Altman in interpreting this inability as a reason not to use Kantian ethics, however, I argue that the Kantian framework is correct: business ethicists should not seek to hold corporations morally responsible. Instead, they should use Kantian (and/or other ethical-theoretical) resources to criticize the actions of individual businesspeople. I set forth a model for decomposing business actions into their individual parts and reconstituting them in a context-specific “maxim” that Kantian ethics can evaluate. The reconstituted form of Kantian ethics that I defend is better able to manage decision-making complexity than traditional interpretations. To demonstrate the usefulness of my approach, I apply it to the recent Wells Fargo bogus-accounts scandal.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The first three claims come from Reckard (2013, pp. 2–3); the last owes to Glazer et al. (2016, p. 2).

  2. Bowie endorses Korsgaard’s claims that the greatest wrongs from a Kantian perspective are fraud and exploitation (or, to use their terms, “deception” and “coercion”) (1999, p. 48).

  3. For a helpful discussion of cases like this, see Sinnott-Armstrong (2005).

  4. For an excellent defense of the alternative view (that a person-centered view of moral responsibility can be extended to corporations), see Goodpaster and Matthews (1982, p. 3).

  5. Altman names Korsgaard, Wood, and Harman as important sources of his interpretation (2014, vi).

  6. The two other important strategies are the “respect for persons” and “ethical community” approaches. For a discussion of these approaches, see Bowie (1999, pp. 41–81 and 82–119).

  7. Cf. Henry Allison’s “Incorporation Thesis” (Allison 1990, pp. 5–6). For an insightful (critical) discussion of this viewpoint, see Wood (2003).

  8. Altman and I have the same conclusion here—Kantian ethics lacks resources to hold corporations morally responsible—but our arguments differ. Altman argues that corporations are not capable of moral responsibility because they lack inclinations and the ability to use reason. I believe that there is good ground to claim that corporations do experience at least one kind of inclination: to maximize profits. As grounds for this claim, I offer that profit maximization is the goal that corporations are created to pursue. Because of possible weaknesses in Altman’s support for his claim, I have decided to provide an alternative argument.

  9. In theory, if every member of a corporation could agree to a maxim and endorse it from their own perspectives, it might be possible to have a corporate maxim, as discussed in Rönnegard (2015). However, this seems highly impractical. Anyway, it would only permit all of the corporate actors to be held individually morally responsible when the corporation is held morally responsible. So there is no practical difference between this unlikely scenario and the scenario in which individual people are held individually responsible for their ethical achievements and shortcomings.

  10. That is not to say that Kantian ethics does not need a concept of collective responsibility. On Kant’s view, the sovereign (the state) has certain responsibilities towards its citizens, though it is constituted by the unified will of its subjects (Kant 1996). For a discussion, see Rauscher (2017).

  11. For an insightful discussion of this problem, see Luban et al. (1992).

  12. Pettit’s grammar here seems suspect; the passive voice obscures that reality that individual people would abuse the lack of corporate moral responsibility—and they would be responsible for the wrongdoing.

  13. A number of similar claims have been discussed by others. Velasquez writes that: “Saying that a corporation is morally responsible for some wrongful act is acceptable only if it is an elliptical way of claiming that there are some people in the corporation who are morally responsible for that act and who should therefore be blamed and punished” (Velasquez 1983, p. 13). He has also referred to this “elliptical” usage as a “fallacy of division” and an “as-if” usage (Velasquez 1983, pp. 546–549). Larry May has written that corporations are “vicarious” agents (May 1987, pp. 84–86). Thomas L. Carson defends a “translatability thesis”: “We can talk in a loose sense about the duties or responsibilities of corporations, provided that we remember that this is only a ‘shorthand way’ of talking about duties or responsibilities of individuals” (Carson 1994, p. 155). Ramie Tuomela and Pekka Antero Mäkelä argue that group agents like corporations are “functional,” but not literal, agents (Tuomela and Mäkelä 2016, p. 299). My “synecdochical” discussion develops these approaches by specifying the way in which the corporation serves as an elliptical, as-if, vicarious, shorthand for an individual, or functional agent within the corporation: the whole stands in for the part.

  14. John D. Bishop’s analysis of executives’ responsibility for corporate malfeasance is relevant here (though not offered from a Kantian perspective). He argues that information typically fails to reach corporate executives in predictable ways, which corporate executives are responsible for managing and mitigating (Bishop 1991).

  15. Altman appears to agree with this point (Altman 2014, p. 229). He discusses the idea that legal responsibility relates only to the corporation’s actions (whether they conform to the law) and not to the corporation’s motivations for meeting legal requirements. Obeying the law does not require corporations to be rational or act on maxims. It does not matter, legally speaking, why corporations have a particular policy or engage in particular practices. What matters is whether these policies and practices conform to legal requirements.

  16. As Velasquez has it: “unlike compensatory liability, th[e]…kind of responsibility [that I call moral responsibility] does not transfer to other parties” (Velasquez 1983, p. 2).

  17. I am here discussing and elaborating Kantian ideas, not interpreting Kant’s own writings. For a helpful discussion of Kant’s own writing about the non-transferability of moral responsibility in the Metaphysics of Morals, see Velasquez (1983, pp. 2–3). The key point, as Velasquez has it, is that “moral responsibility is the kind of responsibility that is attributed to an agent only for those actions that originate in the agent” (emphasis original)(Velasquez 1983, p. 3).

  18. This formulation reflects what has been written about maxims by leading Kantians but is not identical to any other model. O’Neill discusses a variety of possible models. One of the most interesting of these models is “To - - - if…” (O’Neill 1975, 2013, p. 99). Rawls proposes a longer model. His model is structured differently from O’Neill’s: “I am to do X in circumstances C in order to bring about Y unless Z” (2000, p. 168). Korsgaard offers a simpler formulation than Rawls. She writes that: “A maxim of action will usually have the form ‘I will to do action-A in order to achieve purpose-P’ ” (Korsgaard 1996, pp. 57–58).

  19. As suggested by note 17, above, scholars such as Rawls also include the circumstances of an action in their formulations of the maxims that underlie the actions.

  20. For a complete discussion of this process, see Scharding (2016).

  21. Note that these circumstances can (partially) explain why an employee engaged in unethical behavior, on Trevino’s account. These contextual factors do not, though, render such behavior ethical, for her (Trevino 1986, p. 602).

  22. As discussed above, a corporation’s legal responsibility for the consequences of its actions does not depend on regulators’ being able to hold the corporation morally responsible.

  23. For an insightful discussion of some of the problems that arise when corporations blame their employees for corporate wrongdoing, see Warren (2007).

References

  • Allison, H. (1990). Kant’s theory of freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Altman, M. C. (2014). Kant and applied ethics: The uses and limits of Kant’s practical philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D. G., & Bowie, N. E. (2003). Sweatshops and respect for persons. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(2), 221–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. D. (1991). The moral responsibility of corporate executives for disasters. Journal of Business Ethics, 10(5), 377–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borowski, P. J. (1998). Manager-employee relationships: Guided by Kant’s categorical imperative or by Dilbert’s business principle. Journal of Business Ethics, 17(15), 1623–1632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowie, N. E. (1999). Business ethics: A Kantian perspective. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowie, N. E. (2002). A Kantian approach to business ethics. In T. Donaldson, P. H. Werhane & M. Coding (Eds.), Ethical issues in business: A philosophical approach (7th edn., pp. 61–71). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A. (1996). Perfecting imperfect duties: Collective action to create moral obligations. Business Ethics Quarterly, 6(1), 27–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carson, T. L. (1994). Corporate moral agency: A case from literature. Journal of Business Ethics, 13(2), 155–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, A. (2016). How regulation failed with Wells Fargo. The New Yorker (Sep. 12, 2016).

  • De George, R. (1981). Moral responsibility and the corporation. Philosophic Exchange, 12(1), 41–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, P. A. (1979). The corporation as a moral person. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16(3), 207–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glazer, E., Rexrode, C., & Andriotis, A. M. (2016). Wells Fargo is trying to fix its rogue account scandal, one grueling case at a time. The Wall Street Journal (Dec. 27, 2016).

  • Goodpaster, K. E., & Matthews, J. B. Jr. (1982). Can a corporation have a conscience? Harvard Business Review (Jan., 1982).

  • Hasnas, J. (2012). Reflections on corporate moral responsibility and the problem solving technique of Alexander the Great. Journal of Business Ethics, 107(2), 183–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herman, B. (1993). The practice of moral judgement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, T. E. Jr. (1992). Dignity and practical reasoning in Kant’s moral theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1996). On the common saying: That may bee correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice. In M. Gregor (trans. and Ed.), Practical philosophy (pp. 273–210). In The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant in English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Religion within the boundaries of mere reason. In A. Wood & G. Di Giovanni (trans. and Eds.), Religion within the boundaries of mere reason and other writings (pp. 31–192). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2005). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (T.К. Abbott, trans., and L. Denis, trans, and Ed.). Peterboro, ON: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1985). Kant’s formula of universal law. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66(1–2), 24–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). Creating the kingdom of ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2013). Group agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luban, D., Strudler, A., & Wasserman, D. (1992). ‘Moral responsibility in the age of bureaucracy. Michigan Law Review, 90(8), 2348–2392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mansell, S. (2013). Shareholder theory and Kant’s “duty of beneficence. Journal of Business Ethics, 117(3), 583–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, L. (1987). The morality of groups: Collective responsibility, group-based harm, and corporate rights. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (1975, 2013). Acting on principle: An essay on Kantian ethics. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

  • O’Neill, O. (1989, 2003). Constructions of reason: Explorations of Kant’s practical philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Orts, E. W. (2013). Business persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2007). Responsibility incorporated. Ethics, 117(2), 171–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rauscher, F. (2017). Kant’s social and political philosophy. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophyhttps://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/kant-social-political.

  • Rawls, J. (2000). Lectures on the history of morality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reckard, E. S. (2013). Wells Fargo’s pressure-cooker sales culture comes at a cost. LA Times (Dec. 21, 2013).

  • Rönnegard, D. (2015). The fallacy of corporate moral agency. Dordrecht, NL: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scharding, T. (2016). Crafting maxims. Teaching Ethics, 16(1), 37–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2005). It’s not my fault: Global warming and individual moral obligations. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong & R. Howarth (Eds.), Perspectives on climate change: Science, economics, politics (pp. 221–253), Oxford: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strudler, A. (1995). On the ethics of deception in negotiation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 5(4), 805–822.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevino, L. K. (1986). Ethical decision making in organizations: A person-situation interactionist model. The Academy of Management Review, 11(3), 601–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R., & Mäkelä, P. A. (2016). Group agents and their responsibility. Journal of Ethics, 20(1), 299–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velasquez, M. (1983). Why corporations are not morally responsible for anything they do. Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 2(3), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velasquez, M. (2003). Debunking corporate moral responsibility. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(4), 531–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, D. E. (2007). Corporate scandals and spoiled identities: How organizations shift stigma to employees. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(3), 477–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilmot, S. (2001). Corporate moral responsibility: What can we infer from our understanding of organizations? Journal of Business Ethics 30(2), 161–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. W. (1999). Kant’s ethical thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. W. (2003). The good will. Philosophical Topics, 31(1/2), 457–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tobey Scharding.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

Tobey Scharding declares that she has no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Scharding, T. Individual Actions and Corporate Moral Responsibility: A (Reconstituted) Kantian Approach. J Bus Ethics 154, 929–942 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-018-3889-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-018-3889-z

Keywords

Navigation