Skip to main content
Log in

In Search of Individual Responsibility: The Dark Side of Organizations in the Light of Jansenist Ethics

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In showing how the bureaucratic space negatively influences the moral conscience of managers, Robert Jackall’s sociological writings have pointed up one of the darkest sides of organizations. In fact, in the business ethics literature there is much to support Jackall’s pessimistic contentions, suggesting that bureaucracy can rob individual managers of their sense of responsibility. How then can this space for individual freedom, so essential in re-establishing responsible management, be recreated? In order to answer this question, we propose to interpret Jackall’s Moral Mazes (1988) from the standpoint of Blaise Pascal’s Jansenist ethics and conception of humankind. Our discussion here of Pascal’s “reason of effects,” his theory of “double thought” and his distinction between respect and esteem takes Jackall’s analysis forward and opens new lines of thought about managerial responsibility. The article concludes with some thoughts on further research in the field of business ethics arising from Pascalian anthropology or what we call here “skeptical humanism.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The quotations from Pascal’s Pense´es refer to the English translation by W.F. Trotter, New York: E.P Dutton, Pascal (1958), which uses the Brunschvicg numbering system.

  2. A Professor of Sociology & Public Affairs at Williams College in Massachussets.

  3. E.g. the work of Alvesson.

  4. MM: Moral Mazes, The World of Corporate Managers, Oxford University Press.

  5. As a sociologist, Jackall acknowledges Weber, at least indirectly, with the frequent use of the term bureaucracy. Jackall admits the validity of a Weberian analysis even in the world of late Twentieth century American business organizations, where all references to transcendence (“A calvinist world without a Calvinism God”), and indeed to any body of doctrine whatsoever, have disappeared entirely. The “Calvinism” analyzed by Jackall is of a post-modern variety which can be situated on a plane of immanence characteristic of capitalism: a movement without a cause, requiring no further justification; its only choice is to intensify in order to endure.

  6. "The morality is Machiavellian" (Van Maanen 1989, p. 314; see also Nelson and Gilbertson who compare managers to "little princes" in their "small-scale fiefdoms" 1991, p. 634).

  7. See D’Andrade (1993); Galie and Bopst (2006).

  8. Though the Jansenist experiment was stopped in its tracks when Louis XIV had Port-Royal razed in 1710, its intellectual, literary, epistemological, and theological legacy remained intact and its influence in France and abroad made it one of the great intellectual adventures of the “Grand Siècle.” Its reputation flourished through such renowned authors and thinkers as Jean Racine, Saint-Simon, de la Rochefoucauld, and Boisguibert, who trained at the Petite Ecole de Port-Royal and is considered to be the first liberal economist in France.

  9. He wrote essays on vacuum and “conics” and also invented a mechanical calculator.

  10. See in particular Chapter 7, “The Magic Lantern”.

  11. An other adds: "In the world of public relations, there is no such thing as a notion of truth; there are only stories, perspectives, or opinions." (id., p. 172).

  12. "I offer no program for reform, should one think that reform is necessary". (MM, p. 6).

  13. According to Nicole, "that there was nothing he wanted to contribute to more (referring to the education of a prince), if he were called on to do it and that he would gladly give his life for such an important thing" (1004/quote from Lafuma Edition).

  14. As Marin explains, both Nicole and Pascal consider a "great man" to be "essentially an owner of goods: the great man is a rich man whose holdings determine his being" (1981, p. 265).

  15. I, 8: First Discourse, paragraph 8. The numerals II and III correspond to the second and third discourses. The number that follows corresponds to the paragraph.

  16. As Marin comments, "what the Machiavellians and tacticians of the century call the secret of the prince, state secrets, the arcana imperii to characterize the absoluteness of power, we see how Pascal turns it around and inverts it in the ethical secret" (1981, pp. 287–288).

  17. Concupiscence’ (intense desire) in the original French has been rendered as ‘lust’ in English translations of the Pensées. In French, however, the term is broader than physical desire; it also encompasses the desire to possess worldly goods.

  18. Pascal uses the term ‘l'homme' which has been rendered as ‘Man’ in contemporary English translations of his work. We prefer to use ‘humankind’ here, even if this translation, like human being tend to suggest the collective rather than the individual.

  19. Can it be agreed that a clear relationship to oneself is a possibility? In his conflict with his contemporary Descartes, Pascal would have applied the criticism of a ‘transparent self’ to himself, like the critics of traditional humanism. The transparent self is little more than a product of custom (a ‘second-level nature’, unless nature itself is simply a ‘first-level custom’), a self which sees itself placarded with imaginary attributes. Man is subject to the constraints of time, place and applicable norms. He is “embedded” in a particular context, and only a relation-to-self will enable him to realize this.

  20. Even if he could not imagine its extension to more or less all layers of society as a quasi established form of a “right of desires”.

  21. Here, humanism can be defined as the belief that human nature is basically good and hence worthy of protection as an end in itself. Proponents view the human as something which should be cultivated as an essence that sets human beings apart from other beings and entities.

  22. "The greatness of mankind even in his lust, to have known how to extract from it a wonderful code, and to have drawn from it a picture of benevolence." (Pensées 402).

  23. His interest in Pascal is well-known (Léveillé-Mourin 1978).

References

  • Bauman, Z. (2002). La société assiégée. Paris: Hachette Littératures.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benichou, P. (1948). Morales du Grand Siècle. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bevan, D., & Corvellec, H. (2007). The impossibility of corporate ethics: for a Levinasian approach to managerial ethics. Business Ethics: A European Review, 16(3), 208–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, L.-J. (1991). Moral mazes: The world of corporate managers, a book review. Journal of Business Ethics, 10(4), 302–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Card, R. (2005). Individual responsibility within organizational contexts. Journal of Business Ethics, 62(4), 397–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carr, Z.-A. (1968). Is bluffing ethical ? Harvard Business Review, 46(1), 143–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Comte-Sponville, A. (2004). Le capitalisme est-il moral?. Paris: Editions Albin Michel.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’andrade, K. (1993). Machiavelli’s Prince as CEO. Business Ethics Quarterly, 3(4), 396–404.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Leede, J., Nijhof, A., & Fissher, O. (1999). The Myth of Self-Managing Teams: a reflection on the allocation of responsabilities between individuals, teams and the organisation. Journal of Business Ethics, 21(2/3), 203–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (2001). Dits et écrits II. Paris: Quarto Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galie, P. J., & Bopst, C. (2006). Machiavelli and modern business: Realist thought in contemporary corporate leadership manuals. Journal of Business Ethics, 65(3), 234–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldmann, L. (1959). Le Dieu caché. Paris: Tel Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodpaster, K. (1983). The concept of corporate responsibility. Journal of Business Ethics, 2(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gouhier, H. (2005). L’Anti-Humanisme au XVIIème. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackall, R. (1988). Moral Mazes, the world of corporate managers. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laroche, H. (2005). Moral Mazes–The world of corporate managers. European Management Journal, 24(6), 439–448.

    Google Scholar 

  • Léveillé-Mourin, G. (1978). Le langage chrétien anti-chrétien de la transcendance: Pascal-Nietzsche. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loacker, B., & Muhr, S. L. (2009). How can i become a responsible subject? Towards a practice-based ethics of responsiveness. Journal of Businesss Ethics, 90(2), 265–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnard, P. (1980). Nature et histoire dans l’apologétique de Pascal. Dijon: Société Les Belles Lettres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. (2001). Responsibility in organizational context. Business Ethics Quarterly, 11(3), 431–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marin, L. (1981). Le portrait du roi. Paris: Les Editions de minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marin, L. (1997). Pascal et Port-Royal. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melé, D. (2003). The challenge of humanistic management. Journal of Business Ethics, 44(1), 77–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melé, D., Argandona, A., & Sanchez-Runde, C. (2011). Facing the Crisis: Toward a new humanistic synthesis for business. Journal of Business Ethics, 99(1), 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, G., & Gilbertson, D. (1991). Machiavellianism revisited. Journal of Business Ethics, 10(8), 633–639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicole, P. (1999). Essais de morale. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, T. W. (1992). The narcissism and Moral Mazes of corporate life: a Comment on the Writings of Howard Swartz and Robert Jackall. Business Ethics Quarterly, 2(1), 75–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Painter-Morland, M. (2008). Business ethics as practice: ethics as the everyday business of business. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pascal, B. (1958). Pensées, English (W.F. Trotter, Trans.). New-York: Dutton.

  • Pascal, B. (2006). Trois discours sur la condition des grands et six liasses extraites des Pensées, Dossier et Notes réalisés par Katia Genel. Paris: Folio Plus Philosophie, Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricks, J., & Fraedrich, J. (1999). The Paradox of Machiavellianism: Machiavellianism may make a productive sales but poor management reviews. Journal of Business Ethics, 20(3), 197–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosanas, J. M. (2008). Beyond economics criteria : A humanistic approach to organizational survival. Journal of Business Ethics, 78(3), 447–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandelands, L. (2009). The business of business is the human person: Lessons from the catholic social tradition. Journal of Business Studies, 85(1), 93–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soares, C. (2003). Corporate versus individual moral responsibility. Journal of Business Ethics, 46(2), 143–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takala, T., & Pallab, P. (2000). Individual, collective and social responsibility of the firm. Business Ethics: A European Review, 9(2), 109–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. (1986). Collective responsibility and professional roles. Journal of Business Ethics, 5(2), 151–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Maanen, J. (1989). Moral Mazes: The world of corporate managers (pp. 311–315). June: Administrative Science Quarterly.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velamuri, R. S., & Dew, N. (2009). Evolutionary processes, moral luck and the ethical responsabilities of the manager. Journal of Business Ethics, 91(1), 113–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werhane, P. (2002). Moral imagination and systems thinking. Journal of Business Ethics, 38(1/2), 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willmott, H. (1998). Towards a new ethics: the contributions of poststructualism and posthumanism. In M. Parker (Ed.), Ethics and organizations (pp. 76–121). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worden, S. (2009). A genealogy of business ethics: a Nietzsche perspective. Journal of Business Ethics, 84(3), 427–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank his colleagues at EBEN France for their comments at the 2010 annual meeting in Lille when some of the ideas in this article were first communicated. He would also like to thank the three anonymous reviewers for their invaluable suggestions throughout the review process. Finally, he wishes to extend his thanks to Pr. Laroche and Pr. Painter-Morland for their generous support, and to Andrew Beresford and Kenneth Casler for their translation of the paper into English.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ghislain Deslandes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Deslandes, G. In Search of Individual Responsibility: The Dark Side of Organizations in the Light of Jansenist Ethics. J Bus Ethics 101 (Suppl 1), 61–70 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-011-1173-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-011-1173-6

Keywords

Navigation