Skip to main content

Consciousness

  • Living reference work entry
  • First Online:
Book cover Encyclopedia of Animal Cognition and Behavior

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Allen, C. (2004). Animal pain. Noûs, 38, 617–643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C. (2013). Fish cognition and consciousness. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 26, 25–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C., & Trestman, M. “Animal Consciousness”. The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/consciousness-animal/.

  • Allen, C., Fuchs, P., Shriver, A., & Wilson, H. (2005). Deciphering animal pain. In M. Aydede (Ed.), Pain: New essays on the nature of pain and the methodology of its study (pp. 351–366). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen-Hermanson, S. (2005). Morgan’s canon revisited. Philosophy of Science, 72, 608–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen-Hermanson, S. (2018). Animal consciousness. In R. Gennaro (Ed.), Routledge handbook of consciousness (pp. 388–407). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K. “Animal Cognition”. The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/cognition-animal/.

  • Andrews, K., & Beck, J. (Eds.). (2018). The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baars, B. (2005). Subjective experience is probably not limited to humans: The evidence from neurobiology and behavior. Consciousness and Cognition, 14, 7–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balcombe, J. (2016). In praise of fishes: Précis of What a Fish Knows. Animal Sentience, 8(1), 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beran, M., Brandl, J., Perner, J., & Proust, J. (Eds.). (2012). The foundations of metacognition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddock, M. (2017). Should we treat vegetative and minimally conscious patients as persons? Neuroethics, 10, 267–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite, V. (2010). Do fish feel pain? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broom, D. (2016). Fish brains and behaviour indicate capacity for feeling pain. Animal Sentience, 3(4), 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, C. (2015). Fish intelligence, sentience and ethics. Animal Cognition, 18, 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browne, D. (2004). Do dolphins know their own minds? Biology and Philosophy, 19, 633–653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cabanac, M., Cabanac, J., & Paren, A. (2009). The emergence of consciousness in phylogeny. Behavioural Brain Research, 198(2), 267–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calabrese, A., & Woolley, S. (2015). Coding principles of the canonical cortical microcircuit in the avian brain. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112, 3517–3522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2000). Phenomenal consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2005). Consciousness: Essays from a higher-order perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2008). Meta-cognition in animals: A skeptical look. Mind and Language, 23, 58–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2009). How we know our own minds: The relationship between mindreading and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 121–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chandroo, K., Duncan, I., & Moccia, R. (2004). Can fish suffer? Perspectives on sentience, pain, fear and stress. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 86, 225–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N., Bussey, T., & Dickinson, A. (2003). Can animals recall the past and plan for the future? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 685–691.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N., Emery, N., & Dickinson, A. (2006). The rationality of animal memory: Complex caching strategies of western scrub jays. In S. Hurley & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational animals? (pp. 197–216). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A. D. (2009). How do you feel-now? The anterior insula and human awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10, 59–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2009). Self-awareness in animals. In R. Lurz (Ed.), The philosophy of animal minds (pp. 201–217). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1995). Animal consciousness: What matters and why. Social Research, 62, 691–710.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyer, A. G., Neumeyer, C., & Chittka, L. (2005). Honeybee (Apis mellifera) vision can discriminate between and recognise images of human faces. The Journal of Experimental Biology, 208, 4709–4714.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, D., Baars, B., & Seth, A. (2005). Identifying hallmarks of consciousness in non-mammalian species. Consciousness and Cognition, 14, 169–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elwood, R., & Appel, M. (2009). Pain experience in hermit crabs? Animal Behaviour, 77, 1243–1246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elwood, R., Barr, S., & Patterson, L. (2009). Pain and stress in crustaceans. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 118, 128–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emery, N., & Clayton, N. (2001). Effects of experience and social context on prospective caching strategies in scrub jays. Nature, 414, 443–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farah, M. (2008). Neuroethics and the problem of other minds: Implications of neuroscience for the moral status of brain-damaged patients and nonhuman animals. Neuroethics, 1, 9–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, T., & Mallatt, J. (2016). The ancient origins of consciousness: How the brain created experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, S. (2008). Doing away with Morgan’s canon. Mind and Language, 23, 224–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flombaum, J., & Santos, L. (2005). Rhesus monkeys attribute perceptions to others. Current Biology, 15, 447–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro, R. (1996). Consciousness and self-consciousness: A defense of the higher-order thought theory of consciousness. Amsterdam\Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro, R. (1999). Leibniz on consciousness and self-consciousness. In R. Gennaro & C. Huenemann (Eds.), New essays on the rationalists (pp. 353–371). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro, R. (2009). Animals, consciousness, and I-thoughts. In R. Lurz (Ed.), Philosophy of animal minds (pp. 184–200). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro, R. (2012). The consciousness paradox: Consciousness, concepts, and higher-order thoughts. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2013). Cephalopods and the evolution of the mind. Pacific Conservation Biology, 19, 4–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2018). The evolution of consciousness in phylogenetic context. In K. Andrews & J. Beck (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds (pp. 216–226). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D., & Speck, G. (2004). New evidence of animal consciousness. Animal Cognition, 7, 5–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harnad, S. (2016). Animal sentience: The other-minds problem. Animal Sentience, 1(1), 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S., & Nudds, M. (Eds.). (2006). Rational animals? New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, R., & Wilcox, S. (1993). Observations in nature of detouring behavior by Portia Fimbriata, a web-invading aggressive mimic jumping spider from Queensland. Journal of Zoology, 230, 135–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, D. (2018). Animals and ethics, agents and patients. In K. Andrews & J. Beck (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds (pp. 461–468). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Key, B. (2015). Fish do not feel pain and its implications for understanding phenomenal consciousness. Biology and Philosophy, 30, 149–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Key, B. (2016). Why fish do not feel pain. Animal Sentience, 3(1), 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C., & Barron, A. (2016). Insects have the capacity for subjective experience. Animal Sentience, 1(1), 1-19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A. (2007). Metacognition and consciousness. In P. Zelazo, M. Moscovitch, & E. Thomson (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of consciousness (pp. 289–324). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lurz, R. (Ed.). (2009). The philosophy of animal minds. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lurz, R. (2011). Mindreading animals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1996). Consciousness and experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (2001). A simple argument for a higher-order representation theory of consciousness. Analysis, 61, 3–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (2004). The superiority of HOP to HOT. In R. Gennaro (Ed.), Higher-order theories of consciousness: An anthology (pp. 93–113). Philadelphia\Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Maley, C., & Piccinini, G. (2018). The biological evolution of consciousness. In R. Gennaro (Ed.), Routledge handbook of consciousness (pp. 379–387). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mather, J. (2008). Cephalopod consciousness: Behavioural evidence. Consciousness and Cognition, 17, 37–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melnyk, A. (1994). Inference to the best explanation and other minds. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, 482–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendl, M., Paul, E., & Chittka, L. (2011). Animal behaviour: Emotion in invertebrates? Current Biology, 21(12), R463–R465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merker, B. (2005). The liabilities of mobility: A selection pressure for the transition to consciousness in animal evolution. Consciousness and Cognition, 14, 89–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, C. L. (1894). An introduction to comparative psychology. New York: Scribner.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A., & Bartels, A. (2007). Animal minds and the possession of concepts. Philosophical Psychology, 20, 283–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pargetter, R. (1984). The scientific inference to other minds. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62, 158–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perrett, R. (1997). The analogical argument for animal pain. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 14, 49–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. (2000). Folk physics for apes. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prunier, A., Mounier, L., Le Neindre, P., Leterrier, C., Mormède, P., Paulmier, V., Prunet, P., Terlouw, C., & Guatteo, R. (2013). Identifying and monitoring pain in farm animals: A review. Animal, 7, 998–1010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, J. (2002). The neurobehavioral nature of fishes and the question of awareness and pain. Reviews in Fisheries Science, 10, 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, J., Arlinghaus, R., Cooke, S., Diggles, B., Sawynok, W., Stevens, E., & Wynne, C. (2014). Can fish really feel pain? Fish and Fisheries, 15, 97–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (1997). A theory of consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan, & G. Güzeldere (Eds.), The nature of consciousness (pp. 729–753). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2004). Varieties of higher-order theory. In R. Gennaro (Ed.), Higher-order theories of consciousness: An anthology (pp. 17–44). Philadelphia\Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2005). Consciousness and mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos, L., Nissen, A., & Ferrugia, J. (2006). Rhesus monkeys, Macaca mulatta, know what others can and cannot hear. Animal Behaviour, 71, 1175–1181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (2004). A cold look at HOT theory. In R. Gennaro (Ed.), Higher-order theories of consciousness: An anthology (pp. 255–275). Philadelphia\Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A. (2016). Why fish pain cannot and should not be ruled out. Animal Sentience, 3(2), 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A., Baars, B., & Edelman, D. (2005). Criteria for consciousness in humans and other mammals. Consciousness and Cognition, 14, 119–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shriver, A. (2006). Minding mammals. Philosophical Psychology, 19, 433–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shriver, A. (2016). Cortex necessary for pain – But not in sense that matters. Animal Sentience, 3(34), 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shriver, A. (2018). The unpleasantness of pain for nonhuman animals. In K. Andrews & J. Beck (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds (pp. 176–184). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1990). Animal liberation. New York: Avon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. (2005). Studies of uncertainty monitoring and metacognition in animals. In H. S. Terrace & J. Metcalfe (Eds.), The missing link in cognition: Origins of self-reflective consciousness (pp. 242–271). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J., Shields, W., & Washburn, D. (2003). The comparative psychology of uncertainty monitoring and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 317–373.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sneddon, L. (2011). Pain perception in fish: Evidence and implications for the use of fish. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(9–10), 209–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneddon, L., Braithwaite, V., & Gentle, M. (2003). Do fish have nociceptors: Evidence for the evolution of a vertebrate sensory system. Proceedings of the Royal Society London B, 270, 1115–1121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2001). Venetian sea levels, British bread prices, and the principle of the common cause. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 331–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2009). Parsimony and models of animal minds. In R. Lurz (Ed.), The philosophy of animal minds (pp. 237–257). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2012). Anthropomorphism, parsimony, and common ancestry. Mind and Language, 27, 229–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Srinivasan, M. (2010). Honey bees as a model for vision, perception, and cognition. Annual Review of Entomology, 55, 267–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Striedter, G. (2016). Lack of neocortex does not imply fish cannot feel pain. Animal Sentience, 3(21), 1–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Terrace, H., & Metcalfe, J. (Eds.). (2005). The missing link in cognition: Origins of self-reflective consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trestman, M. (2013). The Cambrian explosion and the origins of embodied cognition. Biological Theory, 8, 80–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (2005). Episodic memory and autonoesis: Uniquely human? In H. S. Terrace & J. Metcalfe (Eds.), The missing link in cognition (pp. 3–56). NewYork: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2016). Tense bees and shell-shocked crabs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodruff, M. (2017). Consciousness in teleosts: There is something it feels like to be a fish. Animal Sentience, 2(1), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rocco J. Gennaro .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

Gennaro, R.J. (2018). Consciousness. In: Vonk, J., Shackelford, T. (eds) Encyclopedia of Animal Cognition and Behavior. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-47829-6_1611-1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-47829-6_1611-1

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-47829-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-47829-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Reference Behavioral Science and PsychologyReference Module Humanities and Social SciencesReference Module Business, Economics and Social Sciences

Publish with us

Policies and ethics