Advertisement

Concept of Burden in Evo-Devo

  • Diego Rasskin-Gutman
  • Borja Esteve-Altava
Living reference work entry

Abstract

The concept of burden was developed around the 1970s by Austrian zoologist Rupert Riedl, based on morphological insights rooted in Karl Ernst von Baer’s embryological tradition. Burden’s main tenet is that as a morphological character evolves, it develops more relationships with other characters, becoming more and more interconnected. Through this process, the morphological character acquires more biological “responsibilities” within the organism. Two main consequences of the burden hypothesis are that (1) a character’s evolvability will be limited by these responsibilities and (2) a set of heavily burdened characters could be considered as part of the body plan of a taxonomic group. The concept of burden is intimately related to that of developmental constraint, and as such, it is central to evo-devo.

Keywords

Morphology Philosophy of biology Rupert Riedl Developmental constraints 

Notes

Acknowledgments

DRG funded by MINECO-FEDER BFU2015-70927-R. BE-A is funded by a European Union’s Horizon 2020 Marie Skłodowska-Curie grant No. 654155.

References

  1. Arthur W (2015) Internal factors in evolution: the morphogenetic tree, developmental bias, and some thoughts on the conceptual structure of evo-devo. In: Love A (ed) Conceptual change in biology, Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science, vol 307. Springer, DordrechtGoogle Scholar
  2. Bonner JT (ed) (1982) Evolution and development. Report of the Dahlem workshop on evolution and development Berlin 1981, May 10–15. Springer, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  3. Budd GE (2006) On the origin and evolution of major morphological characters. Biol Rev 81:609–628CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. de Beer GR (1940) Embryos and ancestors. Clarendon Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  5. Erwin DH, Davidson EH (2009) The evolution of hierarchical gene regulatory networks. Nat Rev Genet 10:141–148CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Esteve-Altava B, Botella H, Marugán-Lobón J, Rasskin-Gutman D (2013a) Structural constraints in the evolution of the skull: Williston’s law revisited. Evol Biol 40:209–219CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Esteve-Altava B, Marugán-Lobón J, Botella H, Bastir M, Rasskin-Gutman D (2013b) Grist for Riedl’s mill: a network model perspective on the integration and modularity of the human skull. JEZ Part B Mol Dev Evol 320(8):489–500CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Gilbert S (2013) Developmental biology, 10th edn. Sinauer Associates, Inc., SunderlandGoogle Scholar
  9. Goldschmidt R (1940) The material basis of evolution. Yale University Press, New HavenGoogle Scholar
  10. Goswami A, Polly PD (2010) The influence of modularity on cranial morphological disparity in Carnivora and Primates (Mammalia). PLoS One 5:e9517CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gould SJ (1977) Ontogeny and phylogeny. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  12. Haeckel E (1874) Anthropogenie oder Entwickelungsgeschichte des Menschen. Englemann, LeipzigGoogle Scholar
  13. Jacob E (1977) Evolution and tinkering. Science 196(4295):1161–1166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Maynard Smith J, Burian R, Kauffman S, Alberch P, Campbell J, Goodwin B, Lande R, Raup D, Wolpert L (1985) Developmental constraints and evolution: a perspective from the Mountain Lake conference on development and evolution. Q Rev Biol 60(3):265–287CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Olson EC, Miller RL (1958) Morphological integration. The University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  16. Pavlicev M, Wagner GP (2012) Coming to grips with evolvability. Evo Edu Outreach 5:231–244CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Raff RA (1996) The shape of life: genes, development, and the evolution of animal form. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  18. Rasskin-Gutman D, Esteve-Altava B (2014) Connecting the dots: anatomical network analysis in morphological EvoDevo. Biol Theory 9:178–193CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Riedl R (1978) Order in living organisms: a systems analysis of evolution. Wiley, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  20. Schoch RR (2010) Riedl’s burden and the body plan: selection, constraint, and deep time. J Exp Zool Mol Dev Evol 314B:1–10CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Slack JMW, Holland PW, Graham CF (1993) The zootype and the phylotypic stage. Nature 361:490–492CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Thompson DW (1917) On growth and form. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UKCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. von Baer KE (1828) Entwicklungsgeschichte der Thiere: Beobachtung und Reflexion. Königsberg, BornträgerGoogle Scholar
  24. Waddington CH (1956) Genetic assimilation. Adv Genet 10:257–290Google Scholar
  25. Wagner GP, Laubichler MD (2004) Rupert Riedl and the re-synthesis of evolutionary and developmental biology: body plans and evolvability. J Exp Zool Mol Dev Evol 302B:92–102CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Wimsatt WC (1986) Developmental constraints, generative entrenchment and the innate acquired distinction. In: Bechtel W (ed) Integrating scientific disciplines. Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht, pp 185–208CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Wimsatt WC (2007) Echoes of Haeckel? Reentrenching development in evolution. In: Laubichler MD, Maienschein J (eds) From embryology to evo-devo: a history of developmental evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 309–355Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Theoretical Biology Research Group, Cavanilles Institute of Biodiversity and Evolutionary BiologyUniversity of ValenciaValenciaSpain
  2. 2.Structure and Motion Lab, Department of Comparative Biomedical SciencesThe Royal Veterinary CollegeHatfieldUK

Section editors and affiliations

  • Gerd B. Müller
    • 1
    • 2
  1. 1.The KLI InstituteKlosterneuburgAustria
  2. 2.University of ViennaViennaAustria

Personalised recommendations