Skip to main content

Motion in Renaissance Science

  • Living reference work entry
  • First Online:
Encyclopedia of Renaissance Philosophy
  • 109 Accesses

Abstract

Aristotle’s ideas, and interpretations of them, dominated theorizing about motion during the Middle Ages. However, local motion [motus localis] or locomotion was, according to the “philosopher” and his followers, only one of four types of change. In addition to change in location, the Peripatetics distinguished change in substance, in quality, and in quantity. Within these four domains of change, change always requires the existence of a potentiality which can be actualized. During the late renaissance, however, the peripatetic views on motion were variously criticized, adapted, rejected, and replaced (Bodnar 2016). Generally speaking, the different kinds of change were all reduced to local motion, and one of the key ideas of the new theory of motion was the principle of inertia. First versions of this concept were introduced by Galileo (1564–1642) and later developed by René Descartes (1596–1650) and Isaac Newton (1643–1727). The seeds of this (r)evolution, though, had already been planted by philosophers such as Johannes Buridanus (c. 1300–1358) during the late Middle Ages, who was himself inspired by the work of John Philoponus (c.490–c.570).

In the geocentric cosmos as conceived of by Aristotle (384–322 BC) and Ptolemy (c.100–c.170), there was a strict, ontological distinction between the sublunary world of change and the celestial world of perfect bodies making perfect, circular motions. However, in 1543, Copernicus (1473–1543) published his De revolutionibus which presented a heliocentric model of the universe, supported by Galileo’s telescopic observations. The collapse of the traditional worldview was completed when Newton introduced his notion of universal gravitation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

References

Primary Literature

  • Aristoteles (Edited by Johnathan Barnes). 1984. Complete works. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beeckman, Isaac. 1939–1953. Journal tenu par Isaac Beeckman de 1604 à 1634. The Hague: Nijhoff. http://www.dbnl.org/tekst/beec002jour00_01/. Accessed 15 Feb 2018.

  • Borelli, Giovanni. 1685. De motu animalium. Lugduni in Batavis: apud Danielem à Gaesbeeck, Cornelium Boutesteyn, Iohannem de Vivie & Petrum vander Aa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, Robert [Hunter, M. and Davis, E.B. (Editors]. 1999–2000. The works of Robert Boyle. London, Pickering & Chatto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buridani, Iohannis. 1970. Quaestiones super libris quattuor de caelo et mundo. New York: Kraus Reprint CO.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copernicus, Nicolas. 1978. On the revolutions. Trans. Edward Rosen. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, René. 1897–1910. Œuvres de Descartes. Paris: Léopold Cerf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galileo, Galilei. 1890–1909. Le opere di Galileo Galilei. Edited by Antonio Favaro. Florence: Tipografia Barbèra.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galileo, Galilei. 1960. On motion and on mechanics. Trans. I.E. Drabkin and S. Drake. Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huygens, Christian. 1888–1950. Œuvres Complètes de Christiaan Huygens (Publ. par la Société hollandaise des sciences). La Haye: M. Nijhoff. http://www.dbnl.org/tekst/huyg003oeuv01_01/. Accessed 15 Feb 2018.

  • Huygens, Christiaan. 1986. The pendulum clock or geometrical demonstrations concerning the motion of pendula as applied to clocks. Trans. Richard J. Blackwell. Ames: Iowa State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kepler, Johannes. 1995. Epitome of Copernican Astronomy and Harmonies of the world. Trans. C.G. Wallis. Amherst: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, Isaac. 2016. The Principia: Mathematical principles of natural philosophy. Oakland: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Philoponus, John (trans. Christian Wildberg). 1987. Against Aristotle on the eternity of the world. Trans. Christian Wildberg. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ptolemy, Claudius. 1984. Ptolemy’s almagest. Trans. G.J. Toomer. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevin, S. 1955–1956. The principal works of Simon Stevin. Amsterdam: C.V. Swets & Zeitlinger.

    Google Scholar 

Secondary Literature

  • Bodnar, Istvan. 2016. Aristotle’s natural philosophy. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle-natphil/. Accessed 15 February 2018.

  • Buyse, Filip. 2017. Pendulum clocks in the seventeenth century philosophy. Society and Politics. 11(2). http://socpol.uvvg.ro/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=221&Itemid=238. Acccesed Feb 15 2018.

  • Caffarelli, Roberto Vergara. 2009. Galileo Galilei and motion. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clavelin, M. 1974. Natural philosophy of Galileo: Essays on the origins and formation of classical mechanics. Trans. A.J. Pomerans. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, I. Bernard. 1992. The birth of a new physics. Harmondsworth: Penguin books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, H.F. 2015. The rise of modern science explained: A comparative history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Damerow, Peter. 2011. Exploring the limits of preclassical mechanics: a study of conceptual development in early modern science: free fall and compounded motion in the work of Descartes, Galileo and Beeckman. New York/London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindberg, David C. 2007. The beginnings of Western science: The European scientific tradition in philosophical, religious, and institutional context, 600 B.C. to A.D.1450. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dear, Peter. 2009. Revolutionizing the sciences: European knowledge and its ambitions, 1500–1700. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Des Chene, Dennis. 1996. Physiologia. Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devreese, Jozef T., and Guido Vanden Berghe. 2003. Wonder en is gheen wonder. In De geniale wereld van Simon Stevin 1548–1620. Leuven: Davidsfonds.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dijksterhuis, E.J. 1924. Val en worp: een bijdrage tot de geschiedenis der mechanica van Aristoteles tot Newton. Groningen: Noordhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dijksterhuis, E.J. 2006. De mechanisering van het wereldbeeld. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, Pierre. 1913–1959. Le sytème du monde. Histoire des systems cosmologiques de Platon à Copernic. 10 Vol. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbey, A. 1998. New doctrines of motion. In The Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy, ed. G. Garber and M. Ayers, 649–679. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Dan. 1992. Descartes’ metaphysical physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaukroger, Stephen. 2006. The emergence of a scientific culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heilbron, John. 1982. Elements of early modern physics. Chicago: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heilbron, John. 2015. Physics – A short history. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, John. 2008. The scientific revolution and the origins of modern science. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koyré, Alexandre. 1985. Études d'histoire de la pensée scientifique. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré, Alexandre. 1988. Du monde clos à l'univers infini. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, Ernst. 2017. The Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of Its Development. Charleston: Forgotten Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, Anneliese. 1966. Die Vorläufer Galileis im 14. Jahrhundert. Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura 22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meli, D.B. 2006. Thinking with objects: The transformation of mechanics in the seventeenth century. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, John E., and Edith D. Sylla. 1976. The science of motion. In Science in the middle ages, ed. David C. Lindberg, 206–264. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven. 2018. The scientific revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, Richard. 2010. Philoponus and the rejection of Aristotelian science. London: Institute of Classical Studies, University of London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Berkel, Klaas. 2013. Isaac Beeckman on matter and motion: Mechanical philosophy in the making. Philadelphia: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, Steven. 2015. To explain the world. The discovery of modern science. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westfall, Robert S. 1977. The construction of modern science – Mechanism and mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wisan, W.L. 1974. The new science of motion: A study of Galileo’s De motu locali. Archive for History of Exact Sciences 13: 103–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, Michael. 1978. Geschichte der Impetustheorie. Untersuchungen zum Ursprung der klassischen Mechanik. Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Filip A. A. Buyse .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

Buyse, F.A.A. (2019). Motion in Renaissance Science. In: Sgarbi, M. (eds) Encyclopedia of Renaissance Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-02848-4_953-1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-02848-4_953-1

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-02848-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-02848-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Reference Religion and PhilosophyReference Module Humanities and Social SciencesReference Module Humanities

Publish with us

Policies and ethics