Critical Theory: Epistemological Content and Method

Living reference work entry

Abstract

Critical theory situates science within the quest for social and political rationality. It indicates that science’s normativity – which answers the question “what should science do?” – orients itself in relation to the a priori potential of society. The latter for critical theory transforms itself into concrete political vindications for science. Adorno’s Gesamtgesehen, which differentiates from any total and, therefore, totalitarian conception of what science is, along with Horkheimer’s dialectical approach to science through interdisciplinarity and Habermas’ notion of communicative rationality (that emphasizes scientific dialogue) in science, finds themselves in marked contrast to the rest of modern epistemology. The chapter traces the epistemology of critical theory of the Frankfurt School through the twentieth and the twenty-first centuries via the concepts of dialectics, critique, reason, interdisciplinarity, communicative action and rationality, and their social and political function and role within modernity. The main aims of twenty-first-century epistemology of critical theory become as follows: formulate a theory of normative rationality, reclaim commitments to rational praxis, and educate the sciences to maintain dialectics as their pivotal scope and method of advance.

Keywords

Critical theory Dialectics Political epistemology Normativity 

References

  1. Adorno TW. Zur Metakritik der Erkenntnistheorie, Drei Studien zu Hegel. Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 5. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp; 1970.Google Scholar
  2. Adorno TW, Albert H, Dahrendorf R, Habermas J, Pilot H, Popper KR. The positivist dispute in German sociology. London: Heinemann; 1976.Google Scholar
  3. Arato A, Gebhardt E, editors. The essential Frankfurt school reader. New York: Continuum; 1998.Google Scholar
  4. Habermas J. Knowledge and human interests. Boston: Beacon Press; 1971.Google Scholar
  5. Habermas J. Theory and practice. London: Heinemann; 1974.Google Scholar
  6. Habermas J. The philosophical discourse of modernity. Cambridge, MA: Polity Press; 1987.Google Scholar
  7. Habermas J. On the logic of the social sciences. Cambridge, MA: Polity Press; 1988.Google Scholar
  8. Habermas J. Political communication in media society: does democracy still enjoy an epistemic dimension? The impact of normative theory on empirical research. Commun Theory. 2006;16:411–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Horkheimer M. Critical theory, selected essays. New York: Herder and Herder; 1972.Google Scholar
  10. Horkheimer M. Gesammelte Schriften, Band 3, Schriften 1931–1936. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag; 1988a.Google Scholar
  11. Horkheimer M. Gesammelte Schriften, Band 4, Schriften 1936–1941. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer; 1988b.Google Scholar
  12. Horkheimer M. Between philosophy and social sciences, selected early writings. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press; 1995.Google Scholar
  13. Marcuse H. Reason and revolution. London: Routledge; 1968.Google Scholar
  14. Marinopoulou A. The concept of the political in Max Horkheimer and Jürgen Habermas. Athens: Nissos Academic Publishing; 2008.Google Scholar
  15. Marinopoulou A. Critical theory and epistemology: the politics of modern thought and science. Manchester: Manchester University Press; 2017.Google Scholar
  16. Schecter D. The critique of instrumental reason from Weber to Habermas. New York: Continuum; 2010.Google Scholar
  17. Schecter D. Critical theory in the twenty-first century. New York/London: Bloomsbury; 2013.Google Scholar
  18. Stockman N. Antipositivist theories of the sciences. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company; 1983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of European StudiesHellenic Open UniversityPatraGreece

Personalised recommendations