Advertisement

Maschinenethik und Philosophie

  • Catrin Misselhorn
Living reference work entry
Part of the Springer Reference Geisteswissenschaften book series (SPREFGEIST)

Zusammenfassung

Die Maschinenethik ist ein Forschungsgebiet an der Schnittstelle von Philosophie und Informatik. Dieser Beitrag beschäftigt sich zum einen mit den philosophischen Grundbegriffen und Voraussetzungen der Maschinenethik. Diese sind von besonderer Bedeutung, da sie Fragen aufwerfen, die die Möglichkeit der Maschinenethik teilweise grundsätzlich in Zweifel ziehen. Zum zweiten werden die verschiedenen Rollen der Philosophie auf unterschiedlichen Ebenen innerhalb der Maschinenethik thematisiert und die methodologische Umsetzung dieses interdisziplinären Forschungsprogramms dargelegt.

Schlüsselwörter

Artificial Morality Artificial Moral Agent (AMA) KI Moralisches Handeln Bewusstsein Intentionalität Willensfreiheit Moralimplementation Forschungsprogramm der Maschinenethik Ethische Bewertung der Maschinenethik 

Literatur

  1. Allen, Colin, et al. 2011. Why machine ethics? In Machine ethics, Hrsg. Michael Anderson und Susan Leigh Anderson, 51–61. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Aristoteles. 2004. Topik, übers. u. komm.: Tim Wagner und Christoph Rapp. Ditzingen: Reclam.Google Scholar
  3. Arkin, Ronald. 2009. Governing lethal behavior in autonomous robots. Boca Raton: CRC Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Asimov, Isaac. 2011. Alle Robotergeschichten, versch. Übersetzer, 3. Aufl. Köln: Bastei Lübbe.Google Scholar
  5. Bechtel, William, und Adele Abrahamsen. 2001. Connectionism and the mind, 2. Aufl. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  6. Bendel, Oliver. 2017. LADYBIRD: The animal-friendly robot vacuum cleaner. In The 2017 AAAI spring symposium series. Palo Alto: AAAI Press.Google Scholar
  7. Bermudez, José Luis. 2005. Philosophy of psychology: A contemporary introduction. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  8. Block, Ned. 1995. On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18:227–287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Bratman, Michael E. 1987. Intention, plans, and practical reason. Cambridge: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  10. Breazeal, Cynthia, und Brian Scassellati. 2002. Robots that imitate humans. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6:481–487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Brentano, Franz. 1874. Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.Google Scholar
  12. Brooks, Rodney. 1999. Cambrian intelligence: The early history of the new AI. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Chalmers, David J. 1995. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2:200–219.Google Scholar
  14. Churchland, Paul, und Patricia Smith Churchland. 1990. Could a machine think? Scientific American 262:32–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Clarke, Roger. 2011. Asimov’s laws of robotics: Implications for information technology. In Machine ethics, Hrsg. Michael Anderson und Susan L. Anderson, 254–284. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Cloos, Christopher. 2005. The Utilibot project: An autonomous mobile robot based on utilitarianism. In American Association for Artificial Intelligence. http://www.aaai.org/Papers/Symposia/Fall/2005/FS-05-06/FS05-06-006.pdf. Zugegriffen am 14.12.2017.
  17. Crane, Tim. 2016. The mechanical mind: A philosophical introduction to minds, machines and mental representation, 3. Aufl. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  18. Dancy, Jonathan. 2004. Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Davidson, Donald. 1980. Essays on actions and events. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Dennett, Daniel C. 1987. The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press..Google Scholar
  21. Dennett, Daniel C. 1988. Quining qualia. In Consciousness in contemporary science, Hrsg. Anthony J. Marcel und E. Bisiach, 43–77. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Dretske, Fred. 1995. Explaining behavior. Reasons in a world of causes, 4th printing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Eshleman, Andrew. 2016. Moral responsibility. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Hrsg. Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/moral-responsibility/. Zugegriffen am 14.12.2017.
  24. Floridi, Luciano, und J. Sanders. 2004. On the morality of artificial agents. Minds and Machines 14:349–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Fong, Terrence, et al. 2002. A survey of socially interactive robots: Concepts, design, and applications. Technical report CMU-RI-TR-02-29.Google Scholar
  26. Frankena, William K. 1966. The concept of morality. The Journal of Philosophy 63:688–696.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Frege, Gottlob. 1879. Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle a. S.: Verlag Louis Nebert.Google Scholar
  28. Frege, Gottlob. 1893/1903. Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Bd. I und II. Jena: Verlag Herrmann Pohle.Google Scholar
  29. Froese, Tom, und Ezequiel Di Paolo. 2010. Modelling social interaction as perceptual crossing: An investigation into the dynamics of the interaction process. Connection Science 22:43–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Harnad, Steven. 1989. Minds, machines and Searle. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 1:5–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Harnad, Steven. 2002. Minds, machines, and searle: What’s right and wrong about the Chinese room argument. In Views into the Chinese room: New essays on Searle and artificial intelligence, Hrsg. John Preston und Mark Bishop, 294–307. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Haugeland, John. 1985. Artificial intelligence: The very idea. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  33. Haugeland, John. 2002. Syntax, semantics, physics. In Views into the Chinese room: New essays on Searle and artificial intelligence, Hrsg. John Preston und Mark Bishop, 379–392. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Iida, F., et al. 2004. Embodied artificial intelligence. International seminar, Dagstuhl Castle, Germany, July 7–11, 2003, revised selected papers. Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar
  35. Jackson, Frank. 1982. Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly 32:127–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Jackson, Frank. 1986. What Mary didn’t know. Journal of Philosophy 83:291–229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Kant, Immanuel. 2007. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten mit einem Kommentar, Hrsg. Christoph Horn, Corinna Mieth und Nico Scarano. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  38. Keil, Geert. 2007. Willensfreiheit. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Marr, David. 1982. Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  40. McCulloch, Warren, und Walter Pitts. 1943. A logical calculus of ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 5:115–133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. McLeod, Peter, et al. 1998. Introduction to connectionist modeling of cognitive processes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Minsky, Marvin. 2006. The Emotion Machine. New York: Simon und Schuster.Google Scholar
  43. Misselhorn, Catrin. 2013. Robots as moral agents? In Roboethics, proceedings of the annual conference on ethics of the German Association for Social Science Research on Japan, Hrsg. Frank Roevekamp, 30–42. München: Iudicum.Google Scholar
  44. Misselhorn, Catrin. 2015. Collective agency and cooperation in natural and artificial systems. Philosophical studies series, Bd. 122, 3–25. Wiesbaden: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Misselhorn, Catrin. 2018a. Moralische Maschinen in der Pflege? Grundlagen und eine Roadmap für ein moralisch lernfähiges Altenpflegesystem, erscheint in Roboter in der Gesellschaft: Technische Möglichkeiten und menschliche Verantwortung, Hrsg. Christiane Woopen und Marc Jannes. Wiesbaden: Springer.Google Scholar
  46. Misselhorn, Catrin. 2018b. Maschinenethik und „Artificial Morality“: Können und sollen Maschinen moralisch handeln? Aus Politik und Zeitgeschichte 68:29–33.Google Scholar
  47. Misselhorn, Catrin. 2018c. Artificial morality. Concepts, issues and challenges. Society.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s12115-018-0229-y.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Misselhorn, Catrin. 2018d. Maschinen mit Moral? Grundfragen der Maschinenethik. Stuttgart: Reclam.Google Scholar
  49. Moor, James A. 2006. The nature, importance, and difficulty of machine ethics. IEEE Intelligent Systems 21:18–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Newell, Allen, Simon, Herbert A. 1976. Computer science as empirical inquiry: Symbols and search. Communications of the ACM 19:113–126. http://www.rci.rutgers.edu/∼cfs/472html/AISEARCH/PSS/PSSH1.html. Zugegriffen am 14.12.2017.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Nussbaum, Martha. 1990. Love’s knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  52. Powers, Thomas M. 2011. Prospects for a Kantian machine. In Machine ethics, Hrsg. Michael Anderson und Susan Leigh Anderson, 464–475. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Rao, Anand S., und Michael P. Georgeff. 1991. Modeling rational agents within a BDI-architecture. Proceedings of the 2nd international conference on principles of knowledge representation and reasoning, 473–484.Google Scholar
  54. Rao, Anand S., und Michael P. Georgeff. 1995. BDI-agents: From theory to practice. Proceedings of the first international conference on multiagent systems (ICMAS‘95), 312–319, San Francisco.Google Scholar
  55. Russell, Bertrand, und Alfred North Whitehead. 1925/27. Principia Mathematica, Bds. I, II, III, 2. Aufl. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Scheutz, Matthias. 2011. Architectural roles of affect and how to evaluate them in artificial agents. International Journal of Synthetic Emotions 2:48–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Searle, John. 1980a. Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:417–457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Searle, John. 1980b. Intrinsic intentionality. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:450–456.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Singer, Peter. 1979. Practical ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  60. Sparrow, Robert M. 2007. Killer robots. Journal of Applied Philosophy 24:62–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Tonkens, Ryan. 2009. A challenge for machine ethics. Minds and Machines 19:421–438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Turing, Alan. 1936/37. On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 42:230–265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Turing, Alan. 1950. Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind 49:433–460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Wallach, Wendell, und Colin Allen. 2009. Moral machines: Teaching robots right from wrong. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Wilson, Robert A., und Lucia Foglia. 2017. Embodied cognition. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Hrsg. Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/embodied-cognition/. Zugegriffen am 14.12.2017.

Copyright information

© Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden GmbH, ein Teil von Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Lehrstuhl für Wissenschaftstheorie und TechnikphilosophieInstitut für Philosophie der Universität StuttgartStuttgartDeutschland

Personalised recommendations