Skip to main content

The Propensity Interpretation of Probability

  • Chapter
Dispositions

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 113))

  • 177 Accesses

Abstract

In this paper I intend to put forward some arguments in favour of what I am going to call the propensity interpretation of probability.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See my Logic of Scientific Discovery (1934, 1959), section 48, and appendix* ii

    Google Scholar 

  2. The most characteristic laws of the calculus of probability are (1) the addition theorems, pertaining to the probability of a v b (that is, of a-or-b); (2) the multiplication theorems, pertaining to the probability of ab (that is, of a-and-b); and (3) the complementation theorems, pertaining to the probability of a (that is, of non-a). They may be written (1) p(a v b, c) = p(a, c) + p(b, c) — p(ab, c) (2) p(ab, c) = p(a, bc) p(b, c) (3) p(d, c) = 1 — p(a, c), provided p(c, c) + 1. The form of (3) here given is somehwat unusual: it is characteristic of a probability theory in which (4) p(a, cc) = 1 is a theorem. The first axiom system for a theory of this kind was presented, as far as I know, in BJPS,1955, 6, 56. See also my Logic of Scientific Discovery,appendix* iv, and the appendix to the present paper.

    Google Scholar 

  3. W. C. Kneale said in this discussion: “More recently the difficulties of the frequency interpretation, i.e. the muddles, if not the plain contradictions, which can be found in von Mises, have become well known, and I suppose that these are the considerations which have led Professor Popper to abandon that interpretation of probability.” See Observation and Interpretation,edited by S. Körner, 1957, p. 80. I am not aware of any ‘muddles’ or ‘contradictions’ in the frequency theory which have become well known more recently; on the contrary, I believe that I have discussed all objections of any importance in my Logic of Scientific Discovery when it was first published in 1934, and I do not think that Kneale’s criticism of the frequency theory in his Probability and Induction,1949, presents a correct picture of the situation prevailing at any time since 1934. One objection of Kneale’s (see especially p. 156 of his book) was not discussed in my book—that, in the frequency theory, a probability equal to one does not mean that the event in question will occur without exception (or ‘with certainty’). But this objection is invalid; it can be shown that every adequate theory of probability (if applicable to infinite sets) must lead to the same result.

    Google Scholar 

  4. For the remaining sections 3 to 5, see also my paper ‘The Propensity Interpretation of the Calculus of Probability and The Quantum Theory’, in Observation and Interpretation,edited by S. Körner, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  5. A criticism of the subjective theory of probability will be found in my notes in BJPS,quoted above, and in my paper ‘Probability Magic, or Logic out of Ignorance’, Dialectica,1957, 354-374.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See my ‘Note on Berkeley as a Precursor of Mach’, BJPS,1953, 4, 21 (4).

    Google Scholar 

  7. See my paper ‘Philosophy of Science: A Personal Report’, in British Philosophy in the Mid-Century,edited by C. A. Mace, 1956; the axiom system can be found on p. 191.

    Google Scholar 

  8. As compared with the system of op. cit.,p. 332, the present system combines, in B, A2 with BI and B2. C is the Cs of p. 334.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The following abbreviations are used: ‘(x)’ for ‘for all elements x in S’; ‘(Ex)’ for ‘there is at least one element x in S such that’; ‘... –...: for ‘if... then...’; for ‘if and only if’; ’ for ‘and’.

    Google Scholar 

  10. This is due to the fact that Cd is logically stronger than C since it allows us to replace A by a logically weaker conditional formula; for in the presence of Cd, we may add to A the proviso, ‘provided (Ee) (Ef) p (e, f) $ 0’ (or in words, ‘provided not all probabilities are equal to zero’). The strength of Cd is due to the fact that, with the arrow from right to left only, Cd would be the same as C, while the arrow from left to right allows us, in addition, to deduce that not all probabilities are zero.

    Google Scholar 

  11. It may also be mentioned here that the condition of B, as formulated in the text, may be replaced by the (stronger) condition, ‘(e) p(bc, e) = p(d, e)’. (This replacement corresponds to the transition from formula A2+, on p. 335 of op. cit., to A2 on p. 332.)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1978 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Popper, K.R. (1978). The Propensity Interpretation of Probability. In: Tuomela, R. (eds) Dispositions. Synthese Library, vol 113. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1282-8_15

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1282-8_15

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8347-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1282-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics