Skip to main content

Peripatetic Polemics

  • Chapter
  • 93 Accesses

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy ((PSSP,volume 32))

Abstract

In this chapter we shall examine further the criticism of Stoic cosmology — in particular, the criticism of the Stoic conception of fate — by Alexander of Aphrodisias. We shall also consider what Alexander claims to be “the opinion of the Peripatetic school” concerning fate, as well as several peculiar modal principles evidently accepted by Alexander. I shall suggest that underlying the complex and often obscure disagreement concerning fate between Alexander and the Stoics are two very different conceptions of causal/temporal sequences. While the Stoics developed a conception of causal sequences in which temporally antecedent causes necessitate temporally posterior effect, a conception which is in many ways strikingly “modern,” such a temporal/causal sequence is not the paradigm of a causal sequence for the Peripatetics. Peripatetics such as Alexander ascribe characteristics to such sequences that complicate their anti-Stoic polemics concerning the nature and extent of fate. Nonetheless, I shall suggest, Alexander does have a sort of “empiricist” rejoinder to the Stoic postulation of universal causal necessitation. The Stoic doctrines of “obscure” (adēla) causal factors and of eternal recurrence can be thought of as “metaphysical” responses to such “empiricist” worries about the justifiability of a principle of universal causal necessitation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. A. A. Long, ‘Freedom and Determinism in the Stoic Theory of Human Action’, in Problems in Stoicism(London, 1971), p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cicero, De divinatione 1.55.126.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Alexander, De fato 8, SA 2/2, 173.16–19.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., 4.169.2–3. Alexander, however, also (as at 3.167.12–16 and 5.168.24–26) seems to regard fate as a species of efficient or “productive” (poiētikē) cause, viz., an efficient cause that also has the property of being “for the sake of” something.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ibid., 5.169.13–18.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., 169.18–19.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., 169.25–26.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., 169.28–170.2.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., 22.192.22–24. Cf. Ibid., 15.185.8–9.

    Google Scholar 

  10. In Section E, ‘Aristotle and Determinism’.

    Google Scholar 

  11. The suggestion, which I will not here attempt to support, is that the Newtonian restriction of the notion of a cause to “efficient cause” and the consequent development in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries of a very narrow (and, in many ways, un-Aristotelian) conception of efficient causation yielded this result as a corollary. Cf. G. E. M. Anscombe, ‘Causality and Determination’, reprinted in Causation and Conditionals, ed. E. Sosa (Oxford, 1975), pp. 63–81.

    Google Scholar 

  12. M. A. E. Dummett, ‘Can an Effect Precede its Cause?’, reprinted in Truth and Other Enigmas(Cambridge, Mass., 1978), pp. 320–322.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., p. 322.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Duns Scotus, Opus Oxoniense, I, Dist. II, Q. 1, in Duns Scotus: Philosophical Writings, ed. A. Wolter (Edinburgh, 1962), pp. 40–41.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. Patterson Brown, ‘Infinite Causal Regression’, in Aquinas: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. A. Kenny (Garden City, N.Y., 1969), pp. 214–236.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., pp. 231–236.

    Google Scholar 

  18. An. post. 2.16.98b 1–2.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., 2.12.95a10–15.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Phys. 7.1.242a57–62.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Phys. 8.10.266b28–30.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., 267a2–7.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., 267a9-10: “it comes to an end when the former no longer makes [the latter] to function as a mover (kinoun), but only to be moved (kinoumenon).”

    Google Scholar 

  24. Why, for example, must the ratio between the “motive action” (kinoun) and the “mobile passion” (kinoumenon) reach zero in a finite number of “links” in such a per accidens-ordered causal chain?

    Google Scholar 

  25. An. post. 2.12.95a27–28.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid., 95a30–31.

    Google Scholar 

  27. For example, cf. An. post. 1.4–8 and 2.16–17.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid., 2.12.95b 1–12. Aristotle’s argument for this claim (which, I think, will strike the contemporary reader as rather unintuitive) is obscure; it apparently depends on Aristotle’s understanding of the Greek system of verb aspect. What came-about (to genomenon — aorist aspect) cannot be next to what came-about because to genomenon is considered by A. to be a punctual “accomplishment,” and two points cannot be contiguous. Nor can what has-come-about (to gegenēmenon or to gegenos — perfect aspect, “achieved state”) be next to what is-coming-about (to ginomenon — imperfective, “present” aspect, ongoing process) because the former achieved state supervenes “at a temporal point” but the latter process has no “first” or initiating temporal point (cf. Phys. 6.5.236al0ff.) See also the commentary of J. Barnes: Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics, translated with notes by Jonathan Barnes (Oxford, 1975), pp. 225–227.

    Google Scholar 

  29. An. post. 2.12.95a34–35.

    Google Scholar 

  30. By an “a fronte conditional,” I mean a conditional in which (the event/state of affairs signified by) the antecedent is temporally posterior to (the event/state of affairs signified by) the consequent.

    Google Scholar 

  31. An. post. 2.12.95b35–37.

    Google Scholar 

  32. I quite realize, of course, that the relatively crude semantic mechanism of tense logic can scarcely capture all the semantic subtlety of natural language tense and aspect, particularly in the case of a language such as ancient Greek, in which aspect, rather than tense, dominates with respect to the temporal features of verbs. For more on the doctrines of An. post 2.12, see my ‘Causes as Necessary Conditions: Aristotle, Alexander of Aphrodisias, and J. L. Mackie’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy: Supplementary Volume X (1984), pp. 157–189.

    Google Scholar 

  33. J. L. Mackie, The Cement of the Universe: A Study of Causation (Oxford, 1974), p. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., pp. 37ff.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., p. 53. Mackie there mentions that it is not necessary to conceive of the “laws of working” as “strictly deterministic ones.”

    Google Scholar 

  37. Thus, according to the Stalnaker-Thomason semantic analysis of subjunctive conditionals, the conditional “If X had not occurred, Y would not have occurred” would be false at this (“actual”) world (R. Stalnaker and R. Thomason, ‘A Semantic Analysis of Conditional Logic’, Theoria 36 [1970], pp. 23–42). The objection can also be formulated in the alternative semantics for subjunctive conditionals of David Lewis. For more on this type of objection to the analysis of causation in terms of subjunctive or “counterfactual” conditionals, see my “Causes as Necessary Condition,” pp. 182ff.

    Google Scholar 

  38. There is an underlying point that is crucial to this argument. It can be put in two, roughly equivalent ways. (1) There does not seem to be any compelling independent reason for defining the “similarity” relation on possible worlds in such a way that it satisfies the following condition: for all worlds W and for all events/states of affairs X and Y, if X causes Y in W, then if there is a world W′ not containing X but containing some alternative cause X′ of Y (and thus containing Y), there is a world W″ more similar to W than is W′ that does not contain either X, an alternative cause of Y, or Y. (2) Suppose that in world W, X caused Y; the fact that the most similar world to W not containing X contains some alternative cause of Y does not intuitively seem to constitute a sufficient reason for concluding that the claim that in world W, X caused Y mistaken, i.e., is not true.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Mackie, p. 265.

    Google Scholar 

  40. R. W. Sharples,‘ “If What is Earlier, then of Necessity What is Later?”: Some Ancient Discussions of Aristotle De Generatione et Corruptione 2.11’, BICS 26 (1979), pp. 27–44.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Alexander, Quaestio 3.5, SA 2/2, 88.28–29.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Chapter Four, Section C. Cf. Sorabji, NC&B, p. 86.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Alexander, De fato 14, SA 2/2, 183.9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid., 184.24–185.1.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Chapter Two, Section E, Subsection 3.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Cf., for example, Mackie, p. 31, 265–267.

    Google Scholar 

  47. He seems to have this in mind when he first introduces the qualification at p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  48. For more on this interpretation and the difficulties with it, see White, ‘Causes as Necessary Conditions’, pp. 185ff.

    Google Scholar 

  49. De fato 24, 193.31–194.2.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Ibid., 194.12–15.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ibid., 194.8–12.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Mackie, pp. 40ff.

    Google Scholar 

  53. I do not mean to suggest that Aristotle (or later Peripatetics such as Alexander) explicitly conceived of time as backwards-linear and forwards-branching. Rather, such structures serve as the most natural semantic models in tense logic for a conception of time as past-determinate and future-indeterminate. See, for example, Prior, Past, Present and Future, Ch. VII, pp. 113–136; Rescher and Urquhart, Temporal Logic, Ch. VII, pp. 68–97; Richmond H. Thomason, ‘Indeterminist Time and Truth-Value Gaps’, Theoria 3 (1970), pp$1264–281; M. J. White, ‘Necessity and Unactualized Possibilities in Aristotle’, Philosophical Studies 38 (1980), pp. 287–298.

    Google Scholar 

  54. McTaggart’s A-series conception of time is a conception formulated in terms of the “indexical” tense concepts of “present” or “now,” “past,” and “future”; his B-series conception is formulated in terms of the temporal relations of “at the same time as” or “simultaneous with,” “before,” and “after.” It is usually assumed that propositions formulated in terms of the A-series concepts are not “temporally stable”: e.g., it is, at some times, true that the battle of Waterloo has, in the past, occurred, but not true at other times (“before the fact”). It is usually assumed, however, that relations derived from the B-series concepts are temporally stable, that is, that if it is ever true that the battle of Waterloo temporally precedes (“is before”) the battle of Vicksburg, it is always (or, alternatively, atemporally) true that this relation obtains. This latter assumption can be consistently denied. Its denial will be further explored in the next chapter, section C.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Sharples,‘“If What is Earlier,...,”’p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  56. This is the sort of Stoic view described in section C of the preceding chapter. In general, I subscribe to the view of Sharples, who in discussing J. M. Rist’s account of the Stoic conception of hiemarmenē, comments as follows: “His claim [Stoic Philosophy, pp. 121f.] that fate for the Stoics is to be identified not with what is necessarily going to happen, but only with what will happen, is unacceptable if it is taken as a claim that the Stoics asserted only the logical truism that what will be will be [i.e. the necessitas consequentiae of the conditional “if it will be the case that X, then it will be the case that X”]; for it is clear that the Stoic doctrine of fate did involve the assertion of a deterministic nexus of physical causation” (Sharples, ‘Necessity in the Stoic Doctrine of Fate’, p. 82).

    Google Scholar 

  57. Sharples, ‘“If What is Earlier,...,”’ p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Cf. Alexander, Quaestiones 2.22 and 3.5, SA 2/2, 71–72 and 87–89, respectively; Philoponus, In Aristotelis de generatione et corruptione, CIAG 14/2,308.3–25. See the discussion of these passages (and translation of the relevant sections of Alexander’s Quaestiones) in Sharples, ‘ “If What is Earlier,...,”’

    Google Scholar 

  59. Another possibility would be Y’s continuously-being-true after the instantiation of X. But where “Y” represents a “coming-to-be” rather than a “being” (i.e., an event or developmental process rather than a “static” state of affairs), this does not seem to be a conceptually possible alternative.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Aristotle, De caelo 1.12.283a7–11.

    Google Scholar 

  61. I have in mind the various set-theoretic concepts that figure in the contemporary, Cantorian analysis of infinity, e.g., the distinction between being properly contained in or a proper subset of and having a smaller cardinality. This is not to say that Cantor’s conception is superior to Aristotle’s (as developed, principally, in Phys. 3.4–8), however. In fact, Aristotle’s conception (in contrast to Cantor’s) has recommended itself to a number of contemporary mathematicians, perhaps most notably to “intuitionists” such as L. E. J. Brouwer.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Quaestio 3.5, 88.12–15, as translated by Sharples in ‘“If What is Earlier,...,”’ p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  63. In other words, their temporal relation is “built into” the conceptions of the cause and effect.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Dummett, ‘Can an Effect Precede its Cause?’, p. 320.

    Google Scholar 

  65. For more on this issue, see Ch. VII, Section B. It is, I suspect, a mistake to think of a Peripatetic “final” cause as operating “backwards” in time; it is not clear that temporal relations enter into the Aristotelian notion of final causation in any very significant manner.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Sharples, ‘Aristotelian and Stoic Conceptions of Necessity in the De fato of Alexander of Aphrodisias’, Phronesis 20 (1975), p. 252.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Alexander, De fato 22, 192.22–24.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Sharples, ‘Aristotelian and Stoic Conceptions of Necessity’, p. 260.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Aristotle, Meta., 5.30; Alexander, De fato 8.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Alexander, De fato 8, 173.15–16.

    Google Scholar 

  71. De fato 8,174.2ff.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ibid. 9,175.13–16.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Cf. C. S. Pierce, ‘The Doctrine of Necessity Examined’, The Monist 2/3 (1892), pp. 321–337. Reprinted in Philosophical Writings of Peirce, ed. J. Buchler (New York 1955), pp. 324–338.

    Google Scholar 

  74. M. Beliş, ‘On the Causal Structure of Random Processes’, in Logic, Language, and Probability, ed. R. J. Bogdan and I. Niiniluoto (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Ibid., p. 70.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Ibid., pp. 70–71.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ibid., p. 71. This conclusion depends at least on Bernoulli’s Theorem (see Ch. One). Some would maintain, however, that Bernoulli’s Theorem is a “purely mathematical” theorem not directly applicable to empirical matters. “Von Mises thus concludes that the arithmetical theorem has no bearing on the truth or falsity of Poisson’s proposition which he also called the Law of Large Numbers. That is the empirical proposition whose content is roughly that the relative frequencies of certain empirical events tend towards limiting values as the sequence is extended. This ‘Law of Large Numbers’ is not and cannot be proved mathematically. Rather it is the first postulate of von Mises’s probability theory” (R. Weatherford, Philosophical Foundations of Probability Theory [London, 1982], p. 63).

    Google Scholar 

  78. The schools define time as the “extension” (diastēma) and “measure” of process or motion (kinēsis), respectively; and kinēsis requires some sort of change. For more on this, see the next chapter (Ch. Six).

    Google Scholar 

  79. That is, they will at least differ with respect to the property of occurring at the times at which they, in fact, occur. Whether this need constitute a “real” difference is a complex issue that will be dealt with in greater detail in the next chapter.

    Google Scholar 

  80. This, for example, is the assumption of von Wright, who additionally claims that “the question of whether cause-effect relations hold primarily between events, i.e. changes, or between states, must be answered in favor of the first alternative” (G. H. von Wright, Causality and Determinism [New York and London, 1974 ], p. 79).

    Google Scholar 

  81. The Aristotelian view of causation bears some resemblance to the contemporary attempt to specify a conception of causation “between” the “Humean” (empirical regularity) account and an account in terms of entailment. According to such a conception, causation is to be analyzed in terms of the actualization of the “powers, capacities, and natures of substances” (E. H. Madden, ‘A Third View of Causality’, reprinted in Philosophical Problems of Causation, ed. T. L. Beauchamp [Encino and Belmont, California, 1974], p. 186). And between the “nature” of a substance and its powers and capacities is a relation of nonlogical, causal, or natural necessity. See also E. H. Madden and J. Humber, “Non-logical Necessity and C. J. Ducasse,” ibid., pp. 163–178; R. Harre, Principles of Scientific Thinking (Chicago, 1970); R. Harre and E. H. Madden, Causal Powers (Totoaw, N.J., 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  82. M. Frede, ‘The Original Notion of Cause’, in Doubt and Dogmatism: Studies in Hellenistic Epistemology, ed. M. Schofield, M. Burnyeat, J. Barnes (Oxford, 1980), pp. 217–218.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Ibid., p. 218.

    Google Scholar 

  84. J. H. Randall, Jr., The Career of Philosophy, Vol. 1, p. 607.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Alexander, De fato 3, SA 2/2,167.12–16.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Ibid., 5, 169.2–3. The implication of Defato 3–5 seems to be that “final” causes — or at least some final causes, e.g. fate — are a species of “efficient” (poiētikon) cause. Sharples is not particularly concerned by this, commenting that “Alexander’s concentration on the efficient cause in what follows seems acceptable, in spite of Pack’s complaint (420); that fate is purposive is recognized at V 168.27ff., and though Stoic fate is in some ways analogous to the Aristotelian formal cause ... it is as an active, ‘efficient’ principle that it is so” (R. W. Sharples, Alexander of Aphrodisias On Fate, p. 126).

    Google Scholar 

  87. In general, I think the nunc fluens conception of time is the older view, while the static (or atemporal) relation view is a later development. An exception seems to be the Megarian-Eristic-Dialectical diadochē conception of time — perhaps influenced by earlier Eleatic ideas — which seems to be static-relational. See Chapter Two.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1985 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

White, M.J. (1985). Peripatetic Polemics. In: White, M.J. (eds) Agency and Integrality. Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy, vol 32. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-5339-0_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-5339-0_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-8857-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-5339-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics