Skip to main content

Basic Challenges for Governance in Emergencies

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Justice, Responsibility and Reconciliation in the Wake of Conflict

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life ((BSPR,volume 1))

  • 974 Accesses

Abstract

What are emergencies and why do they matter? In this chapter, I seek to outline the morally significant features of emergencies, and demonstrate how these features generate corresponding first- and second-order challenges and responsibilities for those in a position to do something about them. In the first section, I contend that emergencies are situations in which there is a risk of serious harm and a need to react urgently if that harm is to be averted or minimized. These conceptual features matter morally, since it is precisely to them that those who invoke emergencies to justify otherwise impermissible actions tend to appeal. The basic first-order challenge facing emergency responders is two-fold. It is, first, to identify how these features shape circumstances of action in ways that affect (or do not affect) which reasons for action and which corresponding courses of conduct are justifiably available to them. In situations when emergency responders are compelled to make authoritative determinations due to significant contestability and indeterminacies in the contours or materialization of the said features, their challenge is then also to make these determinations legitimately. In the second section, I argue that second-order challenges having to do with the foreseeability of emergencies, the value of exposure to them, and their preventability further compound the predicament of emergency responders. I conclude by saying a few words about one last morally salient feature shared by many, though not all, emergencies considered in the chapter—namely, their public dimension.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Amongst the many existing studies, useful starting points include Ramraj and Thiruvengadam (2010), Scheppele (2006), and Loveman (1993).

  2. 2.

    Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (European Convention on Human Rights, as amended) s 15(1).

  3. 3.

    Although Schmitt contends that his methodological ambitions are purely descriptive, many passages of his relevant work—such as his assertion that states have a right of self-preservation (Schmitt 2005, 12)—sit awkwardly with this contention.

  4. 4.

    On this broad understanding of morality, see e.g. Raz (2004, 2–3).

  5. 5.

    I defend this claim in Tanguay-Renaud (2012, 30–36). It is true that certain doomsday scenarios threatening the annihilation of human civilization and the subversion of the very foundations of morality may challenge its applicability. The point is that these supreme moral emergencies are the rarest of the rare, the unlikely exception to the exception, and that it is clearly inadvisable to take them as paradigms for the understanding of the relationship between emergencies, morality, and appropriate responses. On this point, see further Tanguay-Renaud (2009, 47–50).

  6. 6.

    On categorical needs—elaborated in terms of the necessity to avoid serious harm and understood in contrast to mere instrumental needs—and the entrenched and non-substitutable character of many such needs, see Wiggins (1987, 1–57). Wiggins’s account of needs remains one of the most insightful to date, despite being lacking in nuance in some notable respects. For example, while he sometimes seems to assume that needs to avoid serious harm must, as a conceptual requirement, be morally compelling, we can easily think of cases where this is not the case. A moral monster like Hitler, afflicted by a fatal though easily curable disease, may well need treatment, while saving him is not a morally compelling goal. Something similar may also be said of the need to rescue the individual in poor health who, after careful and measured deliberation, has decided to end his life.

  7. 7.

    For a remarkably succinct and cogent survey of the theoretical literature on the question of legitimate practical authority, see generally Green (2010).

  8. 8.

    On this point, see Gardner (2010, 83–89).

  9. 9.

    This point is eloquently articulated in Scarry (2011).

  10. 10.

    Note that Gert recognizes that emergencies that are unlikely to be foreseen are only a “kind of emergency situations” and, thus, that emergencies can very well be foreseeable.

  11. 11.

    In fact, as Victor Tadros (2011, 217–240) points out, evidence-relative risks, as opposed to genuine fact-relative or merely belief-relative risks, may sometimes play an even more morally significant role than I allow here.

  12. 12.

    Cf. Rubenstein (2007) on chronic challenges linked to underdevelopment and lack of access to basic resources in some parts of the world. Another oft-cited example is the so-called ever present threat of terrorism. Given the pervasive nature of the phenomenon (however defined), it is often argued that the fight against it is urgent, although likely to be very long and unlikely to be won like a traditional war. Some even argue that it cannot terminate definitively.

  13. 13.

    More recent engagements with just war theory, such as McMahan (2009), go some way towards remedying this methodological defect by focusing on the responsibility of various individual players in wars. Yet, the background unit of evaluation tends to remain whether one is fighting in a just or unjust war, as opposed to more discrete campaigns or missions.

  14. 14.

    A similar type of criticism could be directed at states such as Brunei Darussalam, Swaziland, Israel, Egypt and Syria that claimed for many decades—and in many cases still claim—to be facing perpetual emergencies justifying resort to harsh ‘‘emergency powers’’ to control their populations. See e.g. Reza (2007). The further point to be made, of course, is that unjust regimes treating insurgent movements as emergency threats to their subsistence generally fail to acknowledge that they themselves—qua unjust regimes—can generate prolonged emergencies that may, or should, be resisted (given their more harmful character overall). No doubt, the ‘‘Arab Spring’’ uprisings of 2011 against oppressive dictatorships ruling through ‘‘emergency measures’’ are a sobering reminder of this possibility.

  15. 15.

    Such cases are distinguishable from emergencies characterised by temporally distant, though highly probable harm, in which we know that if we do not act now, harm will likely result at a later point. Consider for example the case of early Canadian settlers who needed to store food in the summer to be able to survive the winter. In so-called meta-emergency cases, it is uncertainty as to the very existence of serious risks that is the operative variable. Note, however, the reservations expressed in the next paragraph.

  16. 16.

    As noted by Suzanne Uniacke (1994, 83–84), “in the case of a hijacker holding hostages who kills in self-defence in a shoot-out with police, it very clearly makes a difference to the normative background that the hijacker has foreseeably and wrongfully created the circumstances in which he is endangered.”

  17. 17.

    This intuition applies to a much broader array of daily situations, such as threats of terrorism for air travelers or risks of rape for women who interact with men. Should airplane users stop flying, and women seek to seclude themselves from men?

  18. 18.

    Sorell “Morality and Emergency” (n 28) 23.

  19. 19.

    On task-efficacy as grounding a duty to govern (and, perhaps, a duty of assistance more generally), see Green (2007).

  20. 20.

    I resort to the admittedly vague and general concept of “realistically unavoidable harm” to prevent any distracting digression into metaphysical debates about ‘‘can’’ and ‘‘could.’’

  21. 21.

    Of course, ‘‘what we want’’ should be read to refer to what we rationally want, as opposed to raw desire.

  22. 22.

    See e.g. Emergencies Act, R.S.C., 1985, c. 22 (4th Supp.) (Canada), online: http://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/PDF/E-4.5.pdf.

  23. 23.

    See e.g. Simester (2008, 299–304).

References

  • Frankfurt HG (1984) Necessity and desire. Philos Phenomenol Res 45:1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner J (2010) Justification under authority. Can J Law Jurisprud 23:71–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Gert B (2004) Common morality: deciding what to do. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Green L (2007) The duty to govern. Legal Theory 13:165–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green L (2010). Legal obligation and authority. In: Zalta EN (ed.) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2010 edn). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/legal-obligation/

  • Kenny AJ (1966) Practical inference. Analysis 26:64–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kunstler JH (2005) The long emergency: surviving the converging catastrophes of the twenty-first century. Atlantic Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Loveman B (1993) The constitution of tyranny: regimes of exception in Spanish America. University of Pittsburg Press, Pittsburg

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (2009) Killing in war. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramraj VV, Thiruvengadam AK (eds) (2010) Emergency powers in Asia: exploring the limits of legality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (2004) Incorporation by law. Legal Theory 10:1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reza S (2007) Endless emergency: the case of Egypt. New Crim Law Rev 10:532–553

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubenstein J (2007) Distribution and emergency. J Polit Philos 15:296–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (1975) Preference and urgency. J Philos 72:655–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarry E (2011) Thinking in an emergency. W.W. Norton & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheppele KL (2006) North American emergencies: the use of emergency powers in Canada and the United States. Int J Const Law 4:213–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt C (2005) Political theology: four chapters on the concept of sovereignty. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Simester AP (2008) Necessity, torture and the rule of law. In: Ramraj VV (ed) Emergencies and the limits of legality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 289–313

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sorell T (2002) Morality and emergency. Proc Aristot Soc 103:21–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tadros V (2011) The ends of harm: the moral foundations of criminal law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tanguay-Renaud F (2009) Making sense of “public” emergencies. Philos Manage 8:31–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanguay-Renaud F (2012) Individual emergencies and the rule of criminal law. In: Tanguay-Renaud F, Stribopoulos J (eds) Rethinking criminal law theory: new Canadian perspectives in the philosophy of domestic, transnational, and international criminal law. Hart Publishing, Oxford, pp 19–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Uniacke S (1994) Permissible killing: the self-defence justification of homicide. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer M (1977) Just and unjust wars: a moral argument with historical illustrations. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins D (1987) Needs, values, truth, 3rd edn. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (2005) In the beginning was the deed. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff J (2006) Risk, fear, blame, shame and the regulation of public safety. Econ Philos 22:409–427

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Special thanks are owed to Kimberley Brownlee, David Enoch, John Gardner, and Alice MacLachlan for comments and discussions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to François Tanguay-Renaud .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tanguay-Renaud, F. (2013). Basic Challenges for Governance in Emergencies. In: MacLachlan, A., Speight, A. (eds) Justice, Responsibility and Reconciliation in the Wake of Conflict. Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5201-6_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics