Skip to main content

The Expressive Burden of Reparations: Putting Meaning into Money, Words, and Things

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life ((BSPR,volume 1))

Abstract

I propose a novel account of the essentially expressive nature of reparations. My account is descriptive of new practices of reparations that have emerged in the past half-century, and it provides normative guidance on conditions of success for reparative attempts. My account attributes to reparative attempts a dual expressive function: a communicative function that requires the gesture to carry a vindicatory message to victims; and an exemplifying function that requires the gesture to model the right relationship that was absent or violated in the wrongdoing to which reparations respond. This account is able to explain the breadth and variety of measures now recognized as reparations; how reparative attempts can fail in two distinct ways; and why material compensation is never sufficient and not always necessary to reparations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I speak of those “responsible for wrongs or for their repair,” for theoretical and practical reasons. The current practice of reparations for human rights and humanitarian abuses places upon states responsibility to discharge obligations of repair for such abuses, even if the government that must discharge the obligation is a successor to one who was causally responsible by omission, commission, or complicity. I avoid here defending the claim, now embedded in international standards for redress and reparation, that successor governments are responsible for repair of wrongs even if they were not causally responsible for the wrongs. In addition, I believe that there are communal responsibilities of moral repair, some of which are ever-present and have to do with the unique abilities of communities to address victims, perpetrators, and wrongs in particular ways, and others which need to be taken up by default when the perpetrators of wrongs are unknown, unavailable, unable, or unwilling to engage in repair, including specific measures of reparations. See Walker (2006a, 29–34) on the significance of communal responsibilities of repair.

  2. 2.

    For an interesting discussion of the non-standard sense in which the U.S. government’s compensation plan for victims and survivors of 9/11 may be seen as “reparations”, see Issacharoff and Mansfield (2006). See also Brooks (2003, 107) on distinguishing between reparations that “seek atonement for the commission of an injustice” and settlements “in which the government does not express atonement.” Admittedly, common usage, as in newspaper articles, often calls settlements that terminate a course of litigation pursuing compensation for injustice “reparations.” And there can be a political stake in calling payments reparations even when they are not intended as such, or are denied to be reparations, if this implies that the party making amends is in fact conceding wrongdoing. On one such case, see Jennifer Lind’s discussion of Japanese compensation payments to Korea in the 1960s, in Lind (2008, 47). I do not mean here to deny that the term “reparations” is used in both looser and rhetorically opportunistic ways. I mean, instead, to focus on cases, however various in detail, that are clearly intended as acts of acknowledgment and redress. It is by reference to these central or canonical cases that we can better understand the analogies that underlie non-standard uses.

  3. 3.

    See Boxill (1972, 119).

  4. 4.

    Some who see “backward-looking” attempts at reparative justice as practically troubled or lacking in sufficient justification sometimes argue that essentially “forward-looking” distributive approaches should either supersede reparative demands based on past injury or should replace reparative attempts with robust distributive ones that address inequalities or injustices in the present. A much discussed argument for supersession of historical injustice by forward-looking considerations is Waldron (1992). Recent arguments for the distributive route include Pierik (2006) and Wenar (2006).

  5. 5.

    On this dramatic historical shift, see Falk (2006), Teitel (2000, 119–128), Torpey, “Introduction: Politics and the Past,” in Torpey (2006), Barkan (2003, 95–98). Specifically on the post-World War II German case, see Colonomos and Armstrong (2006). I do not here defend state responsibility for reparations, although I believe it is defensible and it is, in any case, the existing standard.

  6. 6.

    de Greiff (2006a, b) and Verdeja (2007) offer distinctly political rationales for reparation in cases of mass violence and repression.

  7. 7.

    United Nations, Basic Principles and Guidelines on the Right to a Remedy and Reparation for Victims of Gross Violations of International Human Rights Law and Serious Violations of International Humanitarian Law, United Nations Document A/RES/60/147, 21 March 2006.

  8. 8.

    Brooks (2004) calls this approach the “tort model.” Examples include Nozick (1974, 57–58), MacCormick (1977–1978), Nickel (1976), Sher (1980), Coleman (1994), and Winter (2006). On some complexities of compensation, see Goodin (1989).

  9. 9.

    Political conceptions include de Greiff (2006 b) and Verdeja (2007). Brooks (2004) rejects a “tort model” of reparations to African Americans. Roht-Arriaza (2004) argues for collective and symbolic reparations for communities. Thompson (2002) argues for “reparation as reconciliation” within or between communities, rather than “reparation as restoration” of the status quo ante. Satz (2007) explores limitations of compensation as repair for political violence. See also Walker (2006c) for a restorative justice framework as a superior alternative to a corrective justice one for some cases of historical injustice.

  10. 10.

    Hamber (2006) distinguishes “reparations,” the particular measures, from “reparation”, the end or effect desired. For Hamber, a psychologist, this aim is a kind of psychological state. I adopt his distinction, but use “reparation” to cover desired effects not only of psychological but of moral and political kinds. For a fuller discussion of the psychological needs of victims, see Hamber (2009).

  11. 11.

    Herman (1997) is a classic text on the trauma of victims of individual abuse and political violence. See Hamber (2009) and Walker (2006a, b).

  12. 12.

    See note 9 on political conceptions. A defense of the necessity and complementarity in practice of civil litigation and mass political programs is found in Malamud-Goti and Grosman (2006). See also Bernstein (2009).

  13. 13.

    Walker (2006a, 23–28).

  14. 14.

    The recognition of victims and recreation of civic trust are core themes of Pablo de Greiff’s political approach to reparations (and other transitional justice measures) for mass violence and repression in political contexts. See de Greiff (2006 b, 2008, 2012).

  15. 15.

    See Hamber (2009). Based on extensive work with victims of political violence in several ­contexts, Hamber says: “All objects or acts of reparations have a symbolic meaning to individuals – they are never merely acts or objects,” (98). Another common usage in the reparations literature distinguishes between “material” and “moral” reparations. I find this terminology more illuminating, since it allows for the communicative (and in that sense, symbolic) dimension of all reparations while marking the difference between reparations that involve an exchange of monetarily valued goods from those that involve other interpersonal exchanges that convey respect, recognition, compassion, contrition, and so forth. On moral reparations, see United Nations Commission on Human Rights, (1997) “Question of the Impunity of Perpetrators of Human Rights Violations (Civil and Political), Revised Final Report Prepared by Mr. Joinet Pursuant to Sub-Commission Decision 1996/119,” United Nations Document E/CN.4/Sub.2/1997/20/Rev.1, 2 October 1997, paragraph 42. On the conceptual terrain and the established terminology of material and symbolic reparations, see de Greiff (2006b, 452–453).

  16. 16.

    An interview study of 102 victims of human rights abuses in a follow-up study of truth commissions in five countries (Argentina, Chile, El Salvador, Guatemala, and South Africa), finds that symbolic measures are most demanded and valued by victims. See Czitrom (2002) and Hamber (2009).

  17. 17.

    Boxill (1972), for example, argues that reparation cannot be equated with compensation, because reparation requires an acknowledgment that what the bearer of reparations is doing is required of him because of a former injustice he has done, and so involves an assumption of the moral equality of the wronged party and a rejection of the imputation of inferiority in the unjust treatment. Corlett (2001) specifically attributes to reparations an “expressive” function, including disavowal of the wrong and of the wrongdoer, sending “messages to citizens…which seek to build and strengthen social solidarity toward justice and fairness” (237). Hamber (2006) holds that all objects or acts of reparation have two levels of symbolism. They represent or express something to the victims, such as an acknowledgment of their suffering or a focus for their grief or sense of loss, and they represent something about those giving or granting the reparations, such as society’s willingness to deal with the past and the victim’s suffering or an admission of responsibility. Radzik’s (2009) view makes communication and the symbolism involved in a ­tender of material compensation central elements of atonement.

  18. 18.

    Some philosophical accounts of apology that overlap in their main features but are distinguished by more or fewer requirements are found in: Kort (1973), Gill (2000), and Govier and Verwoerd (2002). The most detailed account is Smith (2008). Two thorough and useful nonphilosophical discussions are those of Lazare (2004) and Tavuchis (1991).

  19. 19.

    Hamber explains the psychological functions that memorial objects can have as “bridges” between the inner and outer worlds of victims and survivors, and to “mirror” back the reactions of others (Hamber 2006, 570–71).

  20. 20.

    Minow (1998, 104).

  21. 21.

    The tangled history is summarized in Iida (2004). Some recent developments are reported in Onishi (2007a, b, c, d).

  22. 22.

    See Tsosie (2007) and Barkan (2003).

  23. 23.

    Bernstein (2009) argues that shares in microfinance institutions have unique potential truly to benefit and enhance the agency of women, especially poor women in male-dominated societies. On appropriate and effective reparations for sexual violence, see also Duggan and Jacobson (2009), and on many complexities of the little-explored area of reparations for child victims, see Mazurana and Carlson (2009).

  24. 24.

    Exemplification as a kind of reference was introduced by Goodman (1968). An object exemplifies those among its own qualities that it is used to represent; a fabric sample, for instance, is used to represent color, pattern, weave, content, texture, and quality of a kind of fabric, but its serrated edges, nine-inch-square dimensions, or dirty finger smudges are not part of what is represented. Elgin (1983, 71–95) gives a clear and detailed exposition of exemplificational reference. I here use only the very basic idea that we use a particular instance to exhibit certain properties that are to be found in other instances of a kind of thing.

  25. 25.

    Lira (2006) provides detailed explanation of this complex and protracted process of reparations.

  26. 26.

    Danieli (2007).

  27. 27.

    Rohter (2002) reports on the reactions of victims’ families to the action. See Guembe (2006) for a detailed account of Argentina’s reparations, which resulted partly from litigation and partly by legislative action.

  28. 28.

    Hamber (2009, 103–108).

  29. 29.

    Fisher (2001).

  30. 30.

    Liptak (2009).

  31. 31.

    On the effort, see Minow (1998) and Yamamoto and Ebusugawa (2006).

  32. 32.

    de Greiff (2006a, 10–12).

  33. 33.

    On the potential and dilemma of “transformative” reparations, see Rubio-Marin (2009).

  34. 34.

    On collective reparations, see Roht-Arriaza (2004), and Verdeja (2007) on the ambiguities involved in using development as reparations.

  35. 35.

    Jaspin (2007) and Loewen (2005) explore the history of expulsion and forcible segregation for African-Americans, while Pfaelzer (2007) examines the history of Chinese immigrants to America.

  36. 36.

    See Walker (2006c) on the ways restorative justice processes involving direct engagement can “leverage” responsibilities. On the pressure to reflect on the political ­culture of Australia in the debate about an official apology for the policy of removal from Aboriginal communities of mixed race children, see Celermajer 2006.

References

  • Barkan E (2003) The guilt of nations. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein A (2009) Tort theory, microfinance and gender equality convergent in pecuniary reparations. In: Rubio-Marin R (ed) The gender of reparations. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Boxill B (1972) The morality of reparation. Soc Theor Practice 2:113–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks RL (2003) Reflections on reparations. In: Torpey J (ed) Politics and the past: on repairing historical injustices. Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks RL (2004) Atonement and forgiveness: a new model for black reparations. University of California Press, Berkeley/Los Angeles

    Google Scholar 

  • Celermajer D (2006) The apology in Australia: re-covenanting the national imaginary. In: Barkan E, Karn A (eds) Taking wrongs seriously: apologies and reconciliation. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman J (1994) Corrective justice and property rights. Soc Philos Policy 22:124–138

    Google Scholar 

  • Colonomos A, Armstrong A (2006) German reparartions to the Jews after World War II: a turning point in the history of reparations. In: de Greiff P (ed) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Corlett JA (2001) Reparations to native Americans? In: Jokic A (ed) War crimes and collective wrongdoing. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Czitrom CG (2002) Executive summary of “Truth Commissions: An Uncertain Path?” by Victor Espinoza Cuevas, Maria Luisa Ortiz Rojas, and Paz Rojas Baeza. Association for the Prevention of Torture, Geneva

    Google Scholar 

  • Danieli Y (2007) Conclusion: essential elements of healing after massive trauma: some theory, victims’ voices, and international developments. In: Miller J, Kumar R (eds) Reparations: interdisciplinary inquiries. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • de Greiff P (ed) (2006a) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • de Greiff P (2006b) Justice and reparations. In: de Greiff P (ed) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • de Greiff P (2008) The role of apologies in national reconciliation processes: on making trustworthy institutions trusted. In: Gibney M, Howard-Hassmann RE, Coicaud J-M, Steiner N (eds) The age of apology: facing up to the past. University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • de Greiff P (2012) Theorizing transitional justice. In: Williams M, Nagy R, Elster J (eds) Transitional justice, vol LI, Nomos. New York University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Duggan C, Jacobson R (2009) Reparation of sexual and reproductive violence: moving from codification to implementation. In: Rubio-Marin R (ed) The gender of reparations. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin CZ (1983) With reference to reference. Hackett, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Fackler M, Sang-Hun C (2007) Japanese researchers rebut premier’s denials on sex slavery. In: New York Times, 18 April

    Google Scholar 

  • Falk R (2006) Reparations, international law, and global justice: a new frontier. In: de Greiff P (ed) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher I (2001) At site of massacre, Polish leader asks Jews for forgiveness. In: New York Times, 11 July

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill KA (2000) The moral functions of an apology. Philos Forum 31:11–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin R (1989) Theories of compensation. Oxf J Leg Stud 9:56–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman N (1968) Languages of art. Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier T, Verwoerd W (2002) The promise and pitfalls of apology. J Soc Philos 33:67–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guembe MJ (2006) Economic reparations for grave human rights violations: the argentinian experience. In: de Greiff P (ed) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamber B (2006) Narrowing the micro and macro: a psychological perspective on reparations in societies in transition. In: de Greiff P (ed) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 560–589

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hamber B (2009) Transforming societies after political violence: truth, reconciliation, and mental health. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Herman J (1997) Trauma and recovery: the aftermath of violence – from domestic abuse to political terror. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Iida K (2004) Human rights and sexual abuse: the impact of international human rights law on Japan. Human Rights Quart 26:428–453

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Issacharoff S, Mansfield AM (2006) Compensation for the victims of September 11. In: de Greiff P (ed) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspin E (2007) Buried in the bitter waters: the history of racial cleansing in America. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kort L (1973) What is an apology? Philos Res Arch 1:80–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazare A (2004) On apology. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lind J (2008) Sorry states: apologies in international politics. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Liptak A (2009) Justices limit the reach of apology to Hawaiians. In: New York Times, 1 April

    Google Scholar 

  • Lira E (2006) The reparations policy for human rights violations in Chile. In: de Greiff P (ed) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewen JW (2005) Sundown towns: a hidden dimension of American racism. Touchstone, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick DN (1977–1978) The obligation of reparation. Proc Aristot Soc 78:175–194

    Google Scholar 

  • Malamud-Goti JE, Grosman LS (2006) Reparations and civil litigation: compensation for human rights violations in transitional democracies. In: de Greiff P (ed) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazurana D, Carlson K (2009) Reparations as a means for recognizing and addressing crimes and grave rights violations against girls and boys during situations of armed conflict and under authoritarian and dictatorial regimes. In: Rubio-Marin R (ed) The gender of reparations. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Minow M (1998) Between vengeance and forgiveness. Beacon, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickel JW (1976) Justice in compensation. William and Mary Law Rev 18:379–388

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1974) Anarchy, state, and utopia. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Onishi N (2007a) Abe rejects Japan’s files on war sex. In: New York Times, 2 March

    Google Scholar 

  • Onishi N (2007b) Denial reopens wounds of Japan’s Ex-sex slaves. In: New York Times, 8 March

    Google Scholar 

  • Onishi N (2007c) Japan court rules against sex slaves and laborers. In: New York Times, 28 April

    Google Scholar 

  • Onishi N (2007d) Japan’s ‘Atonement’ to former sex slaves Stirs Anger. In: New York Times, 25 April

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfaelzer J (2007) Driven out: the forgotten war against Chinese Americans. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pierik R (2006) Reparations for luck egalitarians. J Soc Philos 37:423–440

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radzik L (2009) Making amends: atonement in morality, law, and politics. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Roht-Arriaza N (2004) Reparations in the aftermath of repression and mass violence. In: Stover E, Weinstein HM (eds) My neighbor, my enemy: justice and community in the aftermath of mass atrocity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohter L (2002) Argentine default reopens ‘Dirty War’ wounds. In: New York Times, 12 March

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubio-Marin R (2009) The gender of reparations in transitional societies. In: Rubio-Marin R (ed) The gender of reparations: unsettling sexual hierarchies while redressing human rights violations. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Satz D (2007) Countering the wrongs of the past: the role of compensation. In: Miller J, Kumar R (eds) Reparations: interdisciplinary inquiries. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher G (1980) Ancient wrongs and modern rights. Philos Public Aff 10:3–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith N (2008) I was wrong: the meanings of apologies. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Tavuchis N (1991) Mea culpa: a sociology of apology and reconciliation. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Teitel R (2000) Transitional justice. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson J (2002) Taking responsibility for the past: reparation and historical injustice. Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Torpey J (2006) Politics and the past: on repairing historical injustices. Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsosie R (2007) Acknowledging the past to heal the future: the role of reparations for native nations. In: Miller J, Kumar R (eds) Reparations: interdisciplinary inquiries. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Verdeja E (2007) A normative theory of reparations in transitional democracies. In: Card C, Marsoobian AT (eds) Genocide’s aftermath: responsibility and repair. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (1992) Superseding historic injustice. Ethics 103:4–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker MU (2006a) Moral repair: reconstructing moral relations after wrongdoing. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walker MU (2006b) The cycle of violence. J Hum Rights 5:81–105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker MU (2006c) Restorative justice and reparations. J Soc Philos 37:377–395

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenar L (2006) Reparations for the future. J Soc Philos 37:396–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winter S (2006) Uncertain justice: history and reparations. J Soc Philos 37:342–359

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yamamoto EK, Ebusugawa L (2006) Report on redress: the Japanese American internment. In: de Greiff P (ed) The handbook of reparations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Margaret Urban Walker .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Walker, M.U. (2013). The Expressive Burden of Reparations: Putting Meaning into Money, Words, and Things. In: MacLachlan, A., Speight, A. (eds) Justice, Responsibility and Reconciliation in the Wake of Conflict. Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5201-6_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics