Skip to main content

On When a Disjunction Is Informative

Ambiguous Connectives and a Realist Commitment to Pluralism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Realism-Antirealism Debate in the Age of Alternative Logics

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 23))

  • 823 Accesses

Abstract

In this paper we investigate the topic of ambiguous connectives, as it was recently explored by Paoli (J. Philos. Logic 32:531–548,2003), from an informational perspective. That is, starting from the framework of informational pluralism Allo (Computing, Philosophy, and Cognitive Science.Cambridge Scholars Press, Cambridge,41–52,2007a) Allo (J. Philos. Logic 36:659–694,2007b), we ask what it means for a message of the form ‘A or B’, to be informative. Using these disjunctive messages as an example, we answer three traditional objections to substructural logic and logical pluralism, and eventually show that the linear or relevant logician’s road to unambiguous connectives is consistent with informational pluralism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This accounts differs from Hanson’s own, since he identifies the content of A with the consequence-set of A.

  2. 2.

    Actually, the symmetry of compatibility only requires \(s \sqsubseteq s^{\ast\ast}\) (which enforces double negation introduction) instead of \(s = s^{\ast\ast}\) (the semantic postulate for double negation equivalence).

  3. 3.

    Note that the situated content of A (\(\{s: s\not\Vdash A\}\)) does not express a proposition, and hence is not a persistent kind of content. Namely, it does not hold that if \(s \not\Vdash A\), then \(s' \not\Vdash A\) for all \(s \sqsubseteq s'\). Such issues regarding the non-persistence of properties should be kept in mind.

  4. 4.

    A second, more complicated, aspect of the relevant recapture of DS, namely the admissibility of rule γ, which states that from \(\vdash A \sqcup B\) and \(\vdash \sim A\) we may derive that ⊢ B, is left aside [3, §25].

  5. 5.

    Note, however, that the group-theoretical conjunction equally expresses a choice; namely, the choice the player himself has.

  6. 6.

    Remark in that light that rules (1.10) and (1.11) effectively turn some rules of the game into logical rules.

  7. 7.

    Let \(c = c_1;c_2\) where \(c_1 \in Log\). Assume for reductio that \(c \in Log\) too. By \(c_1 \sqsubseteq_{c_2} c\), we have that \(c_2 \sqsubseteq_{c_1} c\), and since \(c_1 \in Log\) we also have that \(c_2 \sqsubseteq c\). But then, given our assumption that \(c \in Log\), it must at least hold that \(c_2 \sqsubseteq c_2^\ast\). But since c 2 can be any element of S, the latter should not hold in general.

  8. 8.

    Remember that our appeal to multiple agents is itself an artefact we use to account for the real phenomenon under consideration: the distributed nature of information (on that topic, see also [7]).

  9. 9.

    As suggested by Greg Restall (pc), the model of Section 1.4 might in a sense be closer to the approach in his ‘Modelling Truthmaking’ [33].

  10. 10.

    An often-used symbol for the lattice-theoretical constant is ⊤ (top). I prefer to use t and keep ⊤ for the classical truth-constant.

  11. 11.

    If \(s \Vdash 1\) then s is consistent too, that is \(s \sqsubseteq s^\ast\). Consequently, \(s^\ast \Vdash 1\) holds too, and by the same token \(s^\ast \sqsubseteq s^{\ast\ast}\). Since \(s = s^{\ast\ast}\), \(s^\ast \sqsubseteq s\), and hence \(s = s^\ast\).

  12. 12.

    Traditionally, an enthymeme is an argument with an unstated or suppressed assumption. In the relevantist tradition it is common to recapture classical reasoning enthymematically by treating consistency (in some or other form) as an unstated assumption.

  13. 13.

    This paper was originally written in the Summer of 2006, and complements [2]. Both these papers argue for logical and informational pluralism in the same purely model-theoreric fashion; a method I would no longer rely on in the same way as I did. Yet, I’ve chosen not to actualise the present paper to reflect these changes, but to stick to the original version. For the same reason, references to more recent literature on the topic of logical pluralism haven’t been included either.

References

  1. Allo, P. 2007a. “Formalising Semantic Information. Lessons from Logical Pluralism.” In Computing, Philosophy, and Cognitive Science, edited by G. Dodig Crnkovic and S. Stuart, 41–52. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge Scholars Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Allo, P. 2007b. “Logical Pluralism and Semantic Information.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 36:659–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Anderson, A. R., and N. D. Belnap. 1975. Entailment. The Logic of Relevance and Necessity (Vol. I). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Anderson, A. R., N. D. Belnap, and J. M. Dunn. 1992. Entailment. The Logic of Relevance and Necessity (Vol II). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Bar-Hillel, Y., and R. Carnap. 1952. An Outline of a Theory of Semantic Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT, Technical Report 247. Reprinted in: Bar-Hillel, Y. 1964. Language and Information. Selected Essays on Their Theory and Application. London: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Barwise, J. 1997. “Information and Impossibilities.” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38:488–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Barwise, J., and J. Seligman. 1997. Information Flow: The Logic of Distributed Systems. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Beall, J. C., and G. Restall. 2000. “Logical Pluralism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78:475–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Beall, J. C., and G. Restall. 2006. Logical Pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Burgess, J. P. 1981. “Relevance: A Fallacy.” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22:97–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Dretske, F. 1999. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Stanford, CA: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Floridi, L. 2008. “The Method of Levels of Abstraction.” Minds and Machines 18:303–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Gillies, A. S. 2004. “Epistemic Conditionals and Conditional Epistemics.” Noûs 38:585–616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Gillies, A. S. 2006. “What Might Be the Case After a Change in View.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 35:117–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Hanson, W. H. 1980. “First-Degree Entailments and Information.” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 21:659–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Humberstone, I. L. 2005. “Logical Discrimination.” In Logica Universalis, edited by J.-Y. Béziau, 207–28. Basel: Birkhäuser.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  17. Mares, E. 1997. “Relevant Logic and the Theory of Information.” Synthese 109:345–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Mares, E. 2004. Relevant Logic—A Philosophical Interpretation. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. Mares, E. 2006. “Relevant Logic, Probabilistic Information, and Conditionals.” Logique and Analyse 49:399–411.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Mortensen, C. 1983. “The Validity of Disjunctive Syllogism Is Not So Easily Proved.” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24:35–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Mortensen, C. 1986. “Reply to Burgess and Read.” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27:196–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Paoli, F. 2002. Substructural Logics a Primer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Paoli, F. 2003. “Quine and Slater on Paraconsistency and Deviance.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 32:531–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Paoli, F. 2005. “The Ambiguity of Quantifiers.” Philosophical Studies 124:313–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Paoli, F. 2007. “Implicational Paradoxes and the Meaning of Logical Constants.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85:553–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Priest, G., ed. 1997. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38(4). (Special Issue on Impossible Worlds).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Priest, G. 2001b. “Logic: One or Many?” In Logical Consequence: Rival Approaches, edited by J. Woods and B. Brown, 23–38. Stanmore: Hermes.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Read, S. 1981. “What Is Wrong with Disjunctive Syllogism?” Analysis 41:66–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Read, S. 1983. “Burgess on Relevance: A Fallacy Indeed.” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24:473–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Read, S. 1988. Relevant Logic. A Philosophical Examination of Inference. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Read, S. 2006. “Monism: The One True Logic.” In A Logical Approach to Philosophy, edited by D. DeVidi and T. Keynon, 193–209. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  32. Restall, G. 1995. “Information Flow and Relevant Logic.” In Logic, Language and Computation: The 1994 Moraga Proceedings, edited by J. Seligman and D. Westerståhl, 463–77. Stanford: CSLI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Restall, G. 2000. “Modelling Truthmaking.” Logique and Analyse 43:211–30.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Sequoiah-Grayson, S. 2006. “Information Flow and Impossible Situations.” Logique and Analyse 49:371–98.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Allo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Allo, P. (2012). On When a Disjunction Is Informative. In: Rahman, S., Primiero, G., Marion, M. (eds) The Realism-Antirealism Debate in the Age of Alternative Logics. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 23. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1923-1_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics