Skip to main content

Working Notions: A Meditation on Husserlian Phenomenological Practice

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Advancing Phenomenology

Part of the book series: Contributions To Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 62))

Abstract

“A lot of strange things go on in the name of phenomenology.” (Van de Pitte 1988, 33)

The present essay was written early in 1992, but was never published at that time; while the text retains substantially the same form, the notes were drafted much more recently. Both the original subtitle (“How to do phenomenological research without falling into foundationalism, essentialism, or irreparable immanence and the metaphysics of presence”) and the secondary literature cited reflect certain aspects of Husserl-reception in the United States during the 1980s. I have made no systematic attempt either to update the bibliographical references or to integrate my own later reflections on phenomenological method, but have added a number of references to volumes of Husserliana that only appeared after this essay was initially drafted. Its place in the present collection can be explained by mentioning that the original bibliography included a reference to an unpublished manuscript by Lester Embree (an early version of Embree 2003/2006) that he kindly shared with me on the occasion of the 1989 SPEP meeting in Pittsburgh.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    All citations in this form refer to Husserliana, cited by volume/page number(s); quotations are from standard English translations where available. The Husserliana Materialien series is cited using the abbreviation HM, followed by volume/page number(s).

  2. 2.

    Cf. also Waldenfels 1992, 17; 19-1/22; 3-1/135; HM4/73f.

  3. 3.

    See Ströker 1997, 32; cf. Kersten 1989, 21f.

  4. 4.

    Here I am setting aside certain disputes in the literature concerning the difference between “epochē” and “reduction” – see, e.g., Spiegelberg 1973/1981; Petit 1973; Spiegelberg 1974.

  5. 5.

    Cf. also, e.g., 25/61; 34/441ff. This approach to critique of presuppositions emphasizes that the “other side” of the “principle of freedom from presuppositions” is the “principle of all principles” expressed in Ideen I – namely, “that every originary presentive intuition is a legitimizing source of cognition, that everything originarily (so to speak, in its ‘personal’ actuality) offered to us in ‘intuition’ is to be accepted simply as what it is presented as being, but also only within the limits in which it is presented there” (3-1/51; cf., e.g., 1/54, and see also Reiner 1959, 139ff.; Laskey 1984, 91ff.). A further deepening of the critique of presuppositions occurs when we take into account historically sedimented apperceptive styles, retrieving them from their anonymity and seeing how they have shaped what we have taken for granted – see, e.g., 34/303, 363, 397ff. Perhaps the most radical philosophical form that Husserl’s critique of presuppositions takes identifies the pregivenness of the world as, so to speak, the prejudice of all prejudices (see, e.g., 34/151, 303), while we as experiencers function, so to speak, as the (phenomenologically justified) presupposition of all presuppositions (see, e.g., 17/282f., 34/429). In this way, “radical freedom from presuppositions” requires inquiring back into our own streaming life of action and affection as “where” presuppositions exercise their efficacy in the first place (see, e.g., HM8/41).

  6. 6.

    The difficulty that Husserl faces here is that of “inhibiting” a performance that has hitherto never been “consciously” or “explicitly” carried out; we have simply taken it as a “trivial matter of course” that things exist “in themselves” and that we merely come along and grasp them in this or that way (24/153), and this is why the attempt to alter the general “thesis” or “positing” of the natural attitude is so radical (see 3-1/61f.): we cannot immediately refrain from something utterly unthematic, but must first reveal it before we can alter or clarify it (cf. also 34/148ff., 464, 466, 486).

  7. 7.

    See Boehm 1959/1968 for a careful account of the various senses of the terms “immanence” and “transcendence” in Husserl’s texts, and cf. also Seebohm 1989b, 350, 365; Behnke 2004, 21f.

  8. 8.

    As Seebohm (1989b, 370, 376f.; 1992, 161, 163, 166) indicates, these sorts of critiques can be met by adopting a strictly epistemic (rather than ontological) understanding of the reduction.

  9. 9.

    See, e.g., 24/227 n. 1 for an example of a passage where Husserl explicitly recognizes the plurivocity of the concept; cf. 24/407 n. 1.

  10. 10.

    See, e.g., Seebohm 1989a; 1989b, 359ff.; 1992, 161ff.

  11. 11.

    See, e.g., Ströker 1978 (= 1997, 45–81), and cf. Sokolowski 1974, 18ff., 108f., for some helpful distinctions and remarks. Note also that the issue of recourse to that which is itself-given must be separated from the issue of using free imaginative variation in eidetic-phenomenological research, where the actually perceived fountain receives the status of one possibility among others (see, e.g., 9/74).

  12. 12.

    On the metaphor of “cashing in” or “redeeming” an empty “promissory note” for the fulfilling evidence, see, e.g., 2/62; 25/32; 20-1/322; 11/22.

  13. 13.

    On pitfalls connected with the term “intuitive,” cf. Behnke 2004, 23f.

  14. 14.

    See, e.g., Landgrebe 1963, 147 (= 1981, 136); cf. Funke 1966/1987, passim, on the implications of this distinction in general.

  15. 15.

    Cf. Larrabee 1990, 195, where phenomenology as a whole is taken as the correlate of phenomenologizing.

  16. 16.

    Thus experience is not something like a window – “an opening through which a world, existing prior to all experience, shines into a room of consciousness” (17/239) – but functions as a streaming nexus of sense-constituting performances whose ongoing style and whose sedimented history are precisely what constitutive investigations are to bring to light (17/240ff., 251f.).

  17. 17.

    See, e.g., Funke 1966, 195, 206f. (= 1987, 144, 151).

  18. 18.

    See 13/246, and cf., e.g., 4/219f.; 11/148ff., 166ff., 272; 34/191, 487; HM8/35f., 47, 52, 183ff., 197, 318ff., 350f.; Cairns 1976, 40, 53, 88.

  19. 19.

    See also Seebohm 1989b, 376f., and 1992, 163, on the difference between epistemic and genetic priority.

  20. 20.

    I have placed these words in quotation marks to acknowledge a resonance with the epigraph to E. M. Forster’s 1910 novel, Howards End: ‘Only connect …’. Cf. also Funke 1966, 90f. (= 1987, 67f.).

  21. 21.

    Here I should emphasize once again that I am not proposing an interpretation that will accurately reflect the way the term “constitution” has actually been used (by Husserl or by anyone else) in each and every passage in which it occurs. Instead, I am suggesting that constitutive analysis – as tracing-out of correlations – is indeed a key tool in phenomenological research, yet working in this way need not entail the historically related, but separable, decision to apply what is revealed in such research to traditional philosophical problems (e.g., the search for a foundational “primacy” that would serve as some sort of ontological ground or “guarantee”).

  22. 22.

    See Mohanty 1980; 1989, 144. Mohanty’s suggestion is confirmed in some of Husserl’s B I 5 manuscripts; see, e.g., 34/317, 453, and cf. xxxvi, 153ff., 240ff. (esp. 246).

  23. 23.

    See 6/72, 152, 371ff.

  24. 24.

    For more nuances, see Mohanty 1959. On the “exemplicating” move that takes something or other as an “example of …” rather than considering it in its own right, see Zaner 1973b, 31ff., 38ff.; 1978, 6ff., 13f., and cf., e.g., HM4/175, 189. Here I am setting aside the various controversies concerning the difference between “eidos” and “type” – see, e.g., Schutz 1959/1966, but cf. also Behnke 2004, 25ff.

  25. 25.

    Cf., e.g., Waldenfels 1980, 13, 82. Note that here too, as with “constitution,” I am proposing a correlational understanding of a phenomenological “working notion” such that eidetic-phenomenological structures are correlates of eidetic-phenomenological investigation and are only given for an appropriately “eingestellt” consciousness – i.e., one that has adopted the appropriate attitude, interest, focus, etc., and is thus not operating within the attitude proper to ontological “essentialism” at all. Cf. also Laskey 1984, 99f.

  26. 26.

    In this way a critical phenomenology “does not detach itself from historical developments; rather, it finds its peculiar field of work within the historical horizons” – Funke 1966, 109 (= 1987, 81).

  27. 27.

    See, e.g., Seebohm 1989b, 364, 374; cf. 1992, 161f.

  28. 28.

    Cf. Waldenfels 1989, 23 n. 7 (= 1990, 96 n. 6).

  29. 29.

    Waldenfels 1975, 70 (= 1980, 85).

  30. 30.

    See Waldenfels 1985, 140f.; 1987, 144f. (= 1996, 90f.); 1989, 20ff. (= 1990, 92ff.).

  31. 31.

    Reeder 2010, 28; cf. 71, 84 n. 2. See also, e.g., 34/169f. on the contrast between the primal streaming – the continual upwelling of an ever-new now – and the acquisition of a “settled” past, persisting as identical, remaining what it was no matter how many times I return to it and examine it (cf. HM8/30f., 44f., 84, 90ff., 95f., 395).

  32. 32.

    Cf., e.g., Waldenfels 1992, 61. What is at stake here is not simply the genetic priority of the natural attitude over the phenomenological attitude (see, e.g., 8/475; 34/175, 461f., and see also n. 21 above), but whether or not the project of phenomenological description per se must always and everywhere be directed to what has already been “settled,” to the abiding, the “fixed.”

  33. 33.

    See, e.g., 11/passim on the entire issue of a determinate world whose future course is somehow decided, in itself, in advance, vs. the ineluctable presumptivity of perception and its continual anticipations; on the general theme of the project of knowing and its dependence on an “integrating” consciousness whose correlates are abiding transtemporal unities/identities available for explication, further determination, etc., see Behnke 2009, 210ff.

  34. 34.

    See the extensive material available at www.focusing.org; cf. A. Zirión’s essay below.

  35. 35.

    See, e.g., Behnke 2009. Here it is not possible to discuss the ways in which the specific areas of research one takes up shape the way in which one appropriates and interprets “phenomenology” in general.

  36. 36.

    Waldenfels 1975, 75 (=1980, 89), and cf. also Behnke 1999; 2004, 32ff.

  37. 37.

    See, e.g., 19-1/22f. (cf. 18/11; Cairns 1976, 27; Reeder 2010, 51, 59), where it is a question of new phenomenological clarifications transforming the way in which we understand our original phenomenological analyses (and cf. 38/4); see also 6/59, where – in the context of reconstructing Galileo’s mathematization of nature – it is a question of moving back and forth between present-day science on the one hand and its origins and development on the other, with clarification of each of these contributing to elucidating the other (cf. also HM8/357). For further zig-zags (e.g., between lived experience and the draft of a description-in-progress, or between theory and practice), see Behnke 1999.

  38. 38.

    See, e.g., 24/387 on the necessity of interrupting one’s current phenomenological work in order to get clear and its sense on method before returning to the work itself; note, however, that any such methodological reflection presupposes the actual experience of putting the method in play (see, e.g., HM8/7).

  39. 39.

    Here one thinks of the poignant anecdote (related in Spiegelberg 1982, 149 n. 2) of Husserl as a child wholly caught up in sharpening a pocket-knife to an ever keener edge while the blade itself got smaller and smaller.

  40. 40.

    Cf., e.g., 24/445ff.; 8/195f., 203; 27/54f., 185, 207, 220f., 238, 240ff.; 6/15ff., 269ff., 334.

  41. 41.

    See not only the title of the Ideen, but also 19-1/6f.; 25/63f.; 35/311.

  42. 42.

    See Larrabee 1990, 201ff.

Selected Bibliography

  • Ballard, Edward G. “On the Method of Phenomenological Reduction, Its Presuppositions, and Its Future.” In Life-World and Consciousness: Essays for Aron Gurwitsch. Ed. Lester E. Embree. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1972, 101–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. “Toward a transformative phenomenology.” Unpublished, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. “On the Dynamization of Phenomenological Concepts: An experimental essay in phenomenological practice.” Focus Pragensis, 4 (2004), 9–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. “Bodily Protentionality.” Husserl Studies 25 (2009), 185–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. “Phenomenologist at work.” Santalka 18 (2010), 6–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bello, Angela Ales. “Phenomenological Archeology as a Tool for Analyzing the Human World.” Trans. Herbert Garrett. In Phänomenologie der Praxis im Dialog zwischen Japan und dem Westen. Ed. Hiroshi Kojima. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 1989, 105–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boehm, Rudolf. “Les ambiguïtés des concepts husserliens d’‘immanence’ et de ‘transcendance.’” Revue philosophique de la France et de l’étranger 84 (1959), 481–526; “Immanenz und Transzendenz.” In his Vom Gesichtspunkt der Phänomenologie. Husserl-Studien. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1968, 141–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boehm, Rudolf. “Basic Reflections on Husserl’s Phenomenological Reduction.” Trans. J. Quentin Lauer. International Philosophical Quarterly 5 (1965), 183–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bossert, Philip J. “The Sense of ‘Epoche’ and ‘Reduction’ in Husserl’s Phenomenology.” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 5 (1974), 243–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bostar, Leo J. “The methodological significance of Husserl’s concept of evidence and its relation to the idea of reason.” Husserl Studies 4 (1987), 143–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cairns, Dorion. Conversations with Husserl and Fink. Ed. Husserl-Archives in Louvain. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delius, Harald. “Descriptive Interpretation.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 13 (1952–53), 305–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. “Husserl on the Ways to the Performance of the Reduction.” Man and World 8 (1975), 47–69; rpt. in Phenomenology: Critical Concepts in Philosophy. Ed. Dermot Moran and Lester E. Embree with Tanja Staehler and Elizabeth A. Behnke. Vol. 1. London: Routledge, 2004, 231–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Embree, Lester. Reflective Analysis: A First Introduction into Phenomenological Investigation / Análisis reflexivo. Una primera introducción a la investigación fenomenológica. Trans. Luis Román Rabanaque. Edición bilingüe. Morelia: Jitanjáfora, 2003; Reflective Analysis: A First Introduction into Phenomenological Investigation. Paper/e-book. Bucharest: Zeta Books, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farber, Marvin. “The Ideal of a Presuppositionless Philosophy.” In Philosophical Essays in Memory of Edmund Husserl. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1940, 44–64; rpt. in Phenomenology: The Philosophy of Edmund Husserl and Its Interpretation. Ed. Joseph J. Kockelmans. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, Anchor Books, 1967, 37–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fink, Eugen. “Das Problem der Phänomenologie Edmund Husserls.” Revue internationale de philosophie 1 (1939), 226–70; “The Problem of the Phenomenology of Edmund Husserl.” Trans. Robert M. Harlan. In Apriori and World: European Contributions to Husserlian Phenomenology. Ed. William McKenna et al. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981, 21–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fink, Eugen. “Operative Begriffe in Husserls Phänomenologie.” Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 11 (1957), 321–37; “Operative Concepts in Husserl’s Phenomenology.” Trans. William McKenna. In Apriori and World: European Contributions to Husserlian Phenomenology. Ed. William McKenna et al. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981, 56–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funke, Gerhard. Phänomenologie—Metaphysik oder Methode? Bonn: H. Bouvier, 1966; Phenomenology: Metaphysics or Method? Trans. David J. Parent. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendlin, Eugene T. “Expressive Meanings.” In An Invitation to Phenomenology: Studies in the Philosophy of Experience. Ed. James M. Edie. Chicago: Quadrangle, 1965, 240–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendlin, Eugene T. “Experiential Explication and Truth.” In The Sources of Existentialism as Philosophy. Ed. Fernando R. Molina. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1969, 196–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendlin, Eugene T. “Two Phenomenologists Do Not Disagree.” In Phenomenology: Dialogues and Bridges. Ed. Ronald Bruzina and Bruce Wilshire. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1982, 321–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendlin, Eugene T. “Thinking Beyond Patterns: Body, Language, and Situations.” In The Presence of Feeling in Thought. Ed. B. den Ouden and M. Moen. New York: Peter Lang, 1991, 21–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, James G. “Constitution and reference in Husserl’s phenomenology of phenomenology.” Husserl Studies 6 (1989), 43–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, Charles W. “A Note on the Existential Foundations of Phenomenological Reduction.” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 17 (1986), 193–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, Klaus, ed. “Einleitung.” In Edmund Husserl, Die phänomenologische Methode. Ausgewählte Texte I. Stuttgart: Philipp Reclam, 1985, 5–51, 271–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilmy, S. Stephen. “The Scope of Husserl’s Notion of Horizon.” The Modern Schoolman 59 (1981), 21–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. Husserliana. Den Haag/Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff/Kluwer Academic Publishers/Springer, 1950ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. Husserliana Materialien. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers/Springer, 2001ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, Don. Experimental Phenomenology: An Introduction. New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, Capricorn Books, 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kern, Iso. “Die drei Wege zur transzendentalphänomenologischen Reduktion in der Philosophie Edmund Husserls.” Tijdschrift voor filosofie 24 (1962), 303–49; “The Three Ways to the Transcendental Phenomenological Reduction in the Philosophy of Edmund Husserl.” Trans. Frederick A. Elliston and Peter McCormick. In Husserl: Expositions and Appraisals. Ed. Frederick A. Elliston and Peter McCormick. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977, 126–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kersten, Fred. “Universals.” Research in Phenomenology 4 (1974), 29–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kersten, Fred. “The Occasion and Novelty of Husserl’s Phenomenology of Essence.” In Phenomenological Perspectives: Historical and Systematic Essays in Honor of Herbert Spiegelberg. [Ed. Philip J. Bossert.] The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1975, 61–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kersten, Fred. Phenomenological Method: Theory and Practice. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koestenbaum, Peter. “Introductory Essay.” In Edmund Husserl, The Paris Lectures. Trans. Peter Koestenbaum. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1964, ix–lxxvi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohák, Erazim. Idea & Experience: Edmund Husserl’s Project of Phenomenology in Ideas I. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kojima, Hiroshi. “Die doppel-einheitliche Struktur des menschlichen Ego und die phänomenologische Reduktion.” In Japanische Beiträge zur Phänomenologie. Ed. Yoshihiro Nitta. Freiburg: Karl Alber, 1984, 143–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Küng, Guido. “The Phenomenological Reduction as Epoché and Explication.” The Monist 59 (1975), 61–80; rpt. in Husserl: Expositions and Appraisals. Ed. Frederick A. Elliston and Peter McCormick. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977, 338–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landgrebe, Ludwig. “Seinsregionen und regionale Ontologien in Husserls Phänomenologie.” In his Der Weg der Phänomenologie. Das Problem einer ursprünglichen Erfahrung. Gütersloh: Gerd Mohn, 1963, 143–62; “Regions of Being and Regional Ontologies in Husserl’s Phenomenology.” Trans. William McKenna. In Apriori and World: European Contributions to Husserlian Phenomenology. Ed. William McKenna et al. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981, 132–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larrabee, Mary Jeanne. “The Contexts of Phenomenology as Theory.” Human Studies 13 (1990), 195–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laskey, Dallas. “Transcendental Consciousness in Edmund Husserl’s Phenomenology.” Analecta Husserliana 17. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1984, 87–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, David M. Reason and Evidence in Husserl’s Phenomenology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, David M. “Husserlian Essences Reconsidered.” In Explorations in Phenomenology. Ed. David Carr and Edward S. Casey. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973, 169–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, David M. “Husserl’s Notion of Self-evidence.” In Phenomenology and Philosophical Understanding. Ed. Edo Pivčević. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1975, 54–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, William R. Husserl’s “Introduction to Phenomenology”: Interpretation and Critique. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Phénoménologie de la perception. Paris: Gallimard, 1945.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. “Individual Fact and Essence in Edmund Husserl’s Philosophy.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 20 (1959), 222–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. “Towards a Phenomenology of Self-Evidence.” In Explorations in Phenomenology. Ed. David Carr and Edward S. Casey. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973, 208–29; rpt. in Mohanty 1985, 83–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. “Intentionality and the Mind/Body Problem.” In Essays in Honor of Hans Jonas: Organism, Medicine, and Metaphysics. Ed. Stuart F. Spicker. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1978, 283–300; rpt. in Mohanty 1985, 121–38; rpt. in Phenomenology: Critical Concepts in Philosophy. Ed. Dermot Moran and Lester E. Embree with Tanja Staehler and Elizabeth A. Behnke. Vol. 2. London: Routledge, 2004, 316–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. “Husserl’s Transcendental Phenomenology and Essentialism.” Review of Metaphysics 32 (1978), 299–321; rpt. in Mohanty 1985, 191–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. “Subject and person: Eastern and Western Modes of Thinking about Man.” International Philosophical Quarterly 20 (1980), 265–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. “Understanding Husserl’s Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introductory Essay.” In Apriori and World: European Contributions to Husserlian Phenomenology. Ed. William McKenna et al. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. “Husserl on ‘possibility.’” Husserl Studies 1 (1984), 13–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. “Philosophical Description and Descriptive Philosophy.” Research in Phenomenology 14 (1984), 35–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. The Possibility of Transcendental Philosophy. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. Transcendental Phenomenology: An Analytic Account. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moneta, Pina C. “The Refinement of the Concept of Constitution.” Research in Phenomenology 4 (1974), 19–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naess, Arne. “Husserl on the Apodictic Evidence of Ideal Laws.” Theoria 20 (1954), 53–64; rpt. in Readings on Edmund Husserl’s Logical Investigations. Ed. J. N. Mohanty. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1977, 67–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Natanson, Maurice. “Descriptive Phenomenology.” In Descriptions. Ed. Don Ihde and Hugh J. Silverman. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1985, 2–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Null, Gilbert T. “Husserl’s Doctrine of Essence.” In Husserl’s Phenomenology: A Textbook. Ed. J. N. Mohanty and William R. McKenna. Washington, DC: Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology/University Press of America, 1989, 69–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patočka, Jan. “La doctrine husserlienne de l’intuition eidétique et ses critiques récents.” Revue internationale de philosophie 71–72 (1965), 17–33; “The Husserlian Doctrine of Eidetic Intuition and Its Recent Critics.” Trans. Frederick A. Elliston and Peter McCormick. In Husserl: Expositions and Appraisals. Ed. Frederick A. Elliston and Peter McCormick. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977, 150–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patzig, Günther. “Kritische Bemerkungen zu Husserls Thesen über das Verhältnis von Wahrheit und Evidenz.” Neue Hefte für Philosophie 1 (1971), 12–32; “Husserl on Truth and Evidence.” Trans. J. N. Mohanty. In Readings on Edmund Husserl’s Logical Investigations. Ed. J. N. Mohanty. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1977, 179–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petit, Philip. “Is the Reduction Necessary for Phenomenology: Husserl’s and Pfänder’s Replies: A Reply to Herbert Spiegelberg.” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 4 (1973), 16–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietersma, Henry. “Husserl’s Views on the Evident and the True.” In Husserl: Expositions and Appraisals. Ed. Frederick A. Elliston and Peter McCormick. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977, 38–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietersma, Henry. “Truth and the Evident.” In Husserl’s Phenomenology: A Textbook. Ed. J. N. Mohanty and William R. McKenna. Washington, DC: Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology/University Press of America, 1989, 213–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeder, Harry P. The Theory and Practice of Husserl’s Phenomenology. Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1986; 2nd rev. ed. Bucharest: Zeta Books, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiner, Hans. “Sinn und Recht der phänomenologischen Methode.” In Edmund Husserl 1859–1959. [Ed. Herman Leo Van Breda and Jacques Taminiaux.] La Haye: Martinus Nijhoff, 1959, 134–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rotenstreich, Nathan. “Ambiguities of Husserl’s Notion of Constitution.” In Phenomenology and Natural Existence. Ed. Dale Riepe. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1973, 151–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rotenstreich, Nathan. “Evidence and the Aim of Cognitive Activity.” Analecta Husserliana 7. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1978, 245–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rovatti, Pier Aldo. “Das Rätsel der Epoché.” Trans. Klaus Held with Caroline Janke. In Phänomenologie im Widerstreit. Zum 50. Todestag Edmund Husserls. Ed. Christoph Jamme and Otto Pöggeler. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1989, 277–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, Richard. “Husserl’s Transcendental-Phenomenological Reduction.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 20 (1959), 238–45; rpt. in Phenomenology: The Philosophy of Edmund Husserl and Its Interpretation. Ed. Joseph J. Kockelmans. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, Anchor Books, 1967, 58–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrag, Calvin O. “The Phenomenological Sociology of George Psathas: Appraisal and Critique.” Phenomenology and the Human Sciences: Journal of Reviews and Commentary 16 (1991), 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz, Alfred. “Type and Eidos in Husserl’s Late Philosophy.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 20 (1959), 147–65; rpt. in his Collected Papers III: Studies in Phenomenological Philosophy. Ed. Ilse Schutz. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1966, 92–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seebohm, Thomas M. “Apodiktizität. Recht und Grenze.” In Husserl-Symposion Mainz: 27.6./4.7.1988. Ed. Gerhard Funke. (Akademie der Wissenschaften und der Literatur. Abhandlungen der Geistes- und Sozialwissenschaftlichen Klasse, 1989 No. 3.) Wiesbaden: Steiner, 1989, 65–99 (= 1989a).

    Google Scholar 

  • Seebohm, Thomas M. “Transcendental Phenomenology.” In Husserl’s Phenomenology: A Textbook. Ed. J. N. Mohanty and William R. McKenna. Washington, DC: Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology/University Press of America, 1989, 345–85 (= 1989b).

    Google Scholar 

  • Seebohm, Thomas M. “The Paradox of Subjectivity and the Idea of Ultimate Grounding in Husserl and Heidegger.” In Phenomenology and Indian Philosophy. Ed. D. P. Chattopadhyaya, Lester Embree, and Jitendranath Mohanty. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1992, 153–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Quentin. “Husserl’s Theory of the Phenomenological Reduction in the Logical Investigations.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 39 (1979), 433–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, Lee Regis. “The Concept of Evidence in Edmund Husserl’s Genealogy of Logic.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 41 (1981), 547–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, Robert. The Formation of Husserl’s Concept of Constitution. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, Robert. Husserlian Meditations: How Words Present Things. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, Robert. “The Theory of Phenomenological Description.” Man and World 16 (1983), 221–32; rpt. in Descriptions. Ed. Don Ihde and Hugh J. Silverman. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1985, 14–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, Herbert. “Phenomenology of Direct Evidence.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 2 (1942), 427–56; rpt. as “Phenomenology of Direct Evidence (Self-Evidence)” in Spiegelberg 1975, 80–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, Herbert. “Toward a Phenomenology of Experience.” American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (1964), 325–32; rpt. in Spiegelberg 1975, 175–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, Herbert. “Is the Reduction Necessary for Phenomenology? Husserl’s and Pfänder’s Replies.” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 4 (1973), 3–15; rev. as “Husserl and Pfänder on the Phenomenological Reduction.” In his The Context of the Phenomenological Movement. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981, 62–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, Herbert. “‘Epoché’ without Reduction: Some Replies to my Critics.” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 5 (1974), 256–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, Herbert. Doing Phenomenology: Essays on and in phenomenology. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, Herbert. The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction. 3rd rev. and enl. ed. with the collaboration of Karl Schuhmann. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, Herbert. “Three types of the given: The encountered, the search-found, and the striking.” Husserl Studies 1 (1984), 69–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, David. “[Review of] Gerhard Funke, Phenomenology—Metaphysics or Method?” Husserl Studies 7 (1991), 145–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ströker, Elisabeth. “Das Problem der εποχή in der Philosophie Edmund Husserls.” Analecta Husserliana 1. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1970 [1971], 170–85; “The Problem of the Epoché in Husserl’s Phenomenology” in Ströker 1997, 107–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ströker, Elisabeth. “Husserls Evidenzprinzip. Sinn und Grenzen einer methodischen Norm der Phänomenologie als Wissenschaft.” Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 32 (1978), 3–30; “Husserl’s Principle of Evidence: The Significance and Limitations of Phenomenology as a Science” in Ströker 1997, 45–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ströker, Elisabeth. The Husserlian Foundations of Science. 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Breda, Herman Leo. “Note sur réduction et authenticité d’après Husserl.” Revue de métaphysique et de morale 56 (1951), 4–5; “A Note on Reduction and Authenticity According to Husserl.” Trans. Frederick A. Elliston and Peter McCormick. In Husserl: Expositions and Appraisals. Ed. Frederick A. Elliston and Peter McCormick. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977, 124–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van de Pitte, Margaret M. “On Bracketing the Epoché.” Dialogue 11 (1972), 535–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van de Pitte, Margaret M. “Is There a Phenomenological Method?” Metaphilosophy 8 (1977), 21–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van de Pitte, Margaret M. “Phenomenology: Vigorous or moribund?” Husserl Studies 5 (1988), 3–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, Bernhard. “Abgeschlossene Wesenserkenntnis und offene Erfahrung.” In Die Münchener Phänomenologie. Ed. Helmut Kuhn, Eberhard Avé-Lallemant, and Reinhold Gladiator. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1975, 63–80; rpt. in Waldenfels 1980, 79–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, Bernhard. Der Spielraum des Verhaltens. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, Bernhard. “Die Herkunft der Normen aus der Lebenswelt.” In his In den Netzen der Lebenswelt. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1985, 129–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, Bernhard. Ordnung im Zwielicht. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1987; Order in the Twilight. Trans. David J. Parent. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, Bernhard. “Der Logos der praktischen Welt.” In Phänomenologie der Praxis im Dialog zwischen Japan und dem Westen. Ed. Hiroshi Kojima. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 1989, 11–29; rpt. in his Der Stachel des Fremden. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1990, 83–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, Bernhard. Einführung in die Phänomenologie. München: Wilhelm Fink, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, Bernhard, ed. Edmund Husserl, Arbeit an den Phänomenen. Ausgewählte Schriften. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. The Way of Phenomenology: Criticism as a Philosophical Discipline. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, Pegasus, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. “The Phenomenology of Epistemic Claims: And Its Bearing on the Essence of Philosophy.” In Phenomenology and Social Reality: Essays in Memory of Alfred Schutz. Ed. Maurice Natanson. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1970, 17–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. “Reflections on Evidence and Criticism in the Theory of Consciousness.” In Life-World and Consciousness: Essays for Aron Gurwitsch. Ed. Lester E. Embree. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1972, 209–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. “The Art of Free Phantasy in Rigorous Phenomenological Science.” In Phenomenology: Continuation and Criticism. Essays in Memory of Dorion Cairns. Ed. F. Kersten and R. Zaner. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973, 192–219 (= 1973a).

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. “Examples and Possibles: A Criticism of Husserl’s Theory of Free-Phantasy Variation.” Research in Phenomenology 3 (1973), 29–43 (= 1973b).

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. “On Phenomenological Method: The Path of Dorion Cairns.” Research in Phenomenology 4 (1974), 13–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. “On the Sense of Method in Phenomenology.” In Phenomenology and Philosophical Understanding. Ed. Edo Pivčević. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1975, 125–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. “Eidos and Science.” In Phenomenology and the Social Sciences: A Dialogue. Ed. Joseph Bien. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1978, 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elizabeth A. Behnke .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Behnke, E.A. (2010). Working Notions: A Meditation on Husserlian Phenomenological Practice. In: Nenon, T., Blosser, P. (eds) Advancing Phenomenology. Contributions To Phenomenology, vol 62. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9286-1_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics