Skip to main content

Functions and Causal Roles

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover A Critical Overview of Biological Functions

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Philosophy ((BRIEFSPHILOSC))

  • 545 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter is about the causal role theory of function. According to this view, roughly, a function of a part of a system consists in its contribution to some system-level effect, which effect has been picked out as especially interesting by a group of researchers. I will discuss Robert Cummins’ original formulation of the view, and then present a more sophisticated variation, the mechanistic causal role theory, due to Carl Craver and Paul Sheldon Davies. I then discuss the classic problem of overbreadth, namely, that it seems to attribute functions too liberally. I distinguish two different versions of this problem: the problem of non-functional traits and the problem of dysfunctional traits. I provide a critical assessment of the ways causal role theorists have tried to solve these problems. Many philosophers of biology today have accepted a pluralistic stance, according to which both the selected effects theory, and the causal role theory, capture important elements of biological usage. I distinguish two forms of pluralism. The first (and most popular), between-discipline pluralism, holds that the selected effects theory mainly captures the way evolutionary biologists use the term “function” and the causal role theory mainly captures the way “function” is used in other disciplines. I object to this division of labor and recommend a new form of pluralism, within-discipline pluralism, which emphasizes the co-existence of function concepts within any given discipline.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Aguzzi, A., Sigurdson, C., & Heikenwaelder, M. (2008). Molecular mechanisms of prion pathogenesis. Annual Review of Pathology, 3, 11–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (1995). Biological function, adaptation, and natural design. Philosophy of Science, 62, 609–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R., & Lauder, G. V. (1994). Function without purpose: The uses of causal role function in evolutionary biology. Biology and Philosophy, 9, 443–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bock, W. J., & von Wahlert, G. (1965). Adaptation and the form-function complex. Evolution, 19, 269–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard, F. (2013). How ecosystem evolution strengthens the case for function pluralism. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Function: Selection and mechanisms (pp. 83–95). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. N. (2013). A general case for function pluralism. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Function: Selection and mechanisms (pp. 97–104). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2001). Role functions, mechanisms, and hierarchy. Philosophy of Science, 68, 53–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2013). Functions and mechanisms: A perspectivalist view. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Function: Selection and mechanisms (pp. 133–158). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., & Darden, L. (2013). In Search of mechanisms: Discoveries across the life sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 741–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. S. (2001). Norms of nature: Naturalism and the nature of functions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2011). Selected effects functions and causal role functions in the brain: The case for an etiological approach to neuroscience. Biology and Philosophy, 26, 547–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2012). Function, selection, and construction in the brain. Synthese, 189, 451–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2013). The functional sense of mechanism. Philosophy of Science, 80, 317–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (Submitted for publication). How to be a function pluralist. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.  

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation.Erkenntnis, 44, 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1993). Functions: Consensus without unity. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 74, 196–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (2006). Function, homology, and character individuation. Philosophy of Science, 73, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardcastle, V. G. (1999). Understanding functions: A pragmatic approach. In V. G. Hardcastle (Ed.), Where biology meets psychology: Philosophical essays (pp. 27–43). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardcastle, V. G. (2002). On the normativity of functions. In A. Ariew, R. Cummins, & M. Perlman (Eds.), Functions: New essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology (pp. 144–156). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). The logic of functional analysis. In C. G. Hempel (Ed.), Aspects of scientific explanation (pp. 297–330). New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingsbury, J. (2008). Learning and selection. Biology and Philosophy, 23, 493–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). Function and design. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 18, 379–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maclaurin, J., & Sterelny, K. (2008). What is biodiversity?. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (1988). Biological functions and perceptual content. Journal of Philosophy, 85, 5–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, C. (1993). Functional groups of organisms. In E. Schulze & H. A. Mooney (Eds.), Biodiversity and ecosystem function (pp. 67–96). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. D. (1996). Synaptic economics: Competition and cooperation in synaptic plasticity. Neuron, 17, 371–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1989). In defense of proper functions. Philosophy of Science, 56, 288–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (2002). Biofunctions: Two paradigms. In A. Ariew, R. Cummins, & M. Perlman (Eds.), Functions: New essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology (pp. 113–143). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (1993). Dispositions or etiologies? A comments on Bigelow and Pargetter. Journal of Philosophy, 90, 249–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1991). Functions as selected effects: The conceptual analyst’s defense. Philosophy of Science, 58, 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K., Submitted for publication. The emergence of content: Naturalizing the representational power of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunes-Neto, N., Moreno, A., & El-Hani, C. N. (2014). Functions in ecology: An organizational approach. Biology and Philosophy, 29, 123–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pascual-Leone, A., et al. (2005). The plastic human brain cortex. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 28, 377–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183, 283–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston, B. (1998). Why is a wing like a spoon? A pluralist theory of function. Journal of Philosophy, 95, 215–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, E. (1985). What’s wrong with etiological accounts of biological function? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66, 310–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramiro-Cortés, Y., Hobniss, A. F., & Israely, I. (2014). Synaptic competition in structural plasticity and cognitive function. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 369, 20130157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rauschecker, J. P. (1995). Compensatory plasticity and sensory substitution in the cerebral cortex. Trends in Neurosciences, 18, 36–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (1998). Genetics and reductionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, I. (1959). Thoughts on teleology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 9, 265–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Šustar, P. (2007). Neo-functional analysis: Phylogenetical restrictions on causal role functions. Philosophy of Science, 74, 601–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Šustar, P., & Brzović, Z. (2014). The function debate: Between “cheap tricks” and evolutionary neutrality. Synthese 191, 2653–2671. [Check citation??].

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2005). Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiesel, T. N., & Hubel, D. H. (1963). Single-cell responses in striate cortex of kittens deprived of vision in one eye. Journal of Neurophysiology, 26, 1003–1017.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1976). Reductive explanation: A functional account. In R. S. Cohen & A. Michalos (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1974 meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (pp. 671–710). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1986). Forms of aggregativity. In A. Donagan, A. N. Perovich, & M. V. Wedin (Eds.), Human nature and natural knowledge (pp. 259–291). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Justin Garson .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Garson, J. (2016). Functions and Causal Roles. In: A Critical Overview of Biological Functions. SpringerBriefs in Philosophy(). Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-32020-5_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics