Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 313))

  • 483 Accesses

Abstract

The paper contains a conceptual proposal, its key idea being that the successful functioning of a rule embedding artifact designed to regulate a practice (not pertaining to its use) produces the same result as the successful performance of the rule-invoking non-communicative actions belonging to the practice in case.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Kroes and Meijers 2006, for instance.

  2. 2.

    For a general description of the game, see http://orderchaosonline.com/. A player cannot steal items from another player in the game. Identity thefts may of course happen, but they take place in real life, not within the game.

  3. 3.

    The literature on the normativity of artifacts seems to focus either on the way in which the physical structure of an artifact can incorporate rules for its use, or on evaluations regarding how well does an artifact fulfill its function as an appropriate means for achieving a purpose. See, for instance, Akrich 1992; Radder 2009; Franssen 2009; Vries et al. 2013: 101–169. However, the case of rule embedding artifacts, which regulate actions not pertaining to their use, is a different one. One example given in Latour 1999: 186–190 is closer to the topic discussed here and will be presented in what follows.

  4. 4.

    See, for instance, Dipert 1995: 119 for the idea that artifacts “lose their character or essential nature when considered only as physical objects”. Since my investigation is focused on rule embedding artifacts, I do not wish to enter into the ontological debate about the relation between artifacts and physical objects here (although I tend to agree with Kroes and Vermaaas 2008 and disagree with Thomasson (2007) and Baker (2008) for reasons that should become obvious at the end of my paper).

  5. 5.

    These are similar to the first two conditions figuring in the analysis of speaker meaning in Grice 1957. The third condition is missing, since adding it would make speed bumps indistinguishable from signposts.

  6. 6.

    In discussing the case of speed bumps, Latour talks about “nonhumans” being able to perform actions (see Latour 1999: 188–190). Being responsible for A seems, however, to be a necessary condition for doing A (as an intended action).

  7. 7.

    I am not saying that someone can assume responsibility only for an action. A doctor, for instance, can assume responsibility for an event – the death of a patient – without being able to indicate any action which she assumes responsibility for. She does not have to believe that omissions are also some sort of actions in order to do that.

  8. 8.

    See Anscombe 1963 for the idea that only for an action under a description the question whether it was intentional or not can be raised. An interesting suggestion along the same line (actions have conceptual content) can be found in Austin 1962: 19–20: “a great many of the acts which fall within the province of Ethics are not, as philosophers are too prone to assume, simply in the last resort physical movements: very many of them have the general character, in whole or part, of conventional or ritual acts […]”. In order to be the object of moral evaluations, our actions have to occur in a conventional space. If we take Austin’s conventional space to be a conceptual space and extend the remark to the province of practical reason, we get to a similar conclusion.

  9. 9.

    It could also be noted that the existence of artifacts to be used for the protection of people and objects from burning is another condition for the existence of a “being fireproof” property. Keeping a distance of 1 mile from a fire can protect someone from being burned, but we do not call 1 mile “a fireproof distance”.

  10. 10.

    I am reluctant to talk about “fireproof materials”, since raw materials are not directly used in practical actions, but in productive ones. For instance, I would say that asbestos is resistant to heat (which is a natural property), but not fireproof. This does suggest an analysis of the relation between natural and functional properties, but developing such an analysis would be beyond the aim of my paper.

  11. 11.

    See Grice 1957, 1969.

  12. 12.

    I think Dipert 1993, 1995; Bloom 1996; Hilpinen 2011 are representative for this strategy.

  13. 13.

    In fact, the intentional theorist does not need to talk about functional properties in order to specify the content of a productive intention. Dipert simply talks about “properties”, while Hilpinen 2011 replaces functional predicates by sortal terms. I suspect this is due to their interest in works of art as artifacts. Also, if we make it a necessary condition for being an artifact that the object in case satisfies a sortal, we might have to exclude some respectable artifacts like glue and whisky (the second being Hilpinen’s own example).

  14. 14.

    Besides production, we could also include modification in our analysis, as Dipert 1993, 1995 suggests. It should also be noted that (1) is weaker than Hilpinen’s (DEP) condition (“The existence and some of the properties of an artifact depend on an author’s intention to make an object of certain kind.”).

  15. 15.

    This condition is due to Dipert. Hilpinen 2011 also accepts it as a “plausible condition, since an F-object can presumably be a good F-object only if its potential users recognize it as such”. His critique that “recognizability should not be taken to mean general recognizability” can be answered by my distinction between the users of X and the addressees of X.

  16. 16.

    Here we can define successful production by combining Hilpinen’s conditions (SUC) (“An object is an artifact made by an author only if it satisfies some sortal description included in the author’s productive intention.”) and (ACC) (“An object is an artifact made by an author only if the author accepts it as satisfying some sortal description included in his productive intention.”): X’s production was successful IFF either X has F, or the author(s) of X accept that X has F.

  17. 17.

    Suppose I automatically fold an origami bird while talking on the phone and leave it on a table. Someone else takes it and uses it as a bookmark. The origami bird was not produced with the intention to be used in a certain way and it is not used according to the way in which it is regularly used (as a decoration). Proper intentions (at least as psychological states) seem to be missing from this picture, but my origami bird would still be an artifact (here “my” does not mean that I am the author of the origami bird, but only that I am the cause of its existence).

  18. 18.

    See Wittgenstein 1953: §§201–2.

  19. 19.

    I believe it is safe to assume that conceptual role semantics (see Harman 1982, 1999; Horwich 1994) and inferentialism (see Brandom 1994, 2000, 2007) are such theories.

  20. 20.

    This functional approach to artifacts can be traced back to Skolimowski (1966) and Heidegger (1927), Chap. 3, recent representatives being involved in the Dual nature of Artifacts research project (Kroes and Meijers 2006; also: http://www.dualnature.tudelft.nl/). This last claim is disputable, since Kroes and Meijers invoke Dipert and talk about intentions, although they do not seem to consider intentions as psychological states, so I tend to agree with Vaesen 2011 in this respect. For other representative positions for the functional approach, see Houkes 2006; Vermaas 2006; Vermas and Houkes 2006; Preston 2009. The distinction between intentional and functional approaches to artifacts was suggested to me by Verbeek and Vermaas 2009 (although they put Dipert in a distinct category).

  21. 21.

    We do not want to say that artifacts are like words in all respects, of course. The distinction could be made by pointing out that artifacts are only used in relation to perception and action (and perhaps they can be also involved, in a sense, in practical reasoning, in a different way from the one in which words are involved in practical reasoning).

  22. 22.

    On the Linux operation system, for instance, a bash script would be executed (by the cron daemon) by including the following line in the crontab file:

    00 22 * * * /usr/bin/somedirectory/script.sh

    and it would look like this:

    #!/bin/bash

    if [[ `whoami` == "razvan" ]]; then

    halt

    fi

  23. 23.

    The distinction between rules of action and rules of criticism comes from Sellars 1969. The form of a rule of action is familiar: “If one is in C, one ought to do A” (Sellars 1969: 507; C stands for the particular circumstances under which the rule applies). An example of a rule of criticism is “Clock chimes ought to strike on the quarter hour” (Sellars 1969: 508).

  24. 24.

    I consider ‘refraining from A’ as designating an action.

  25. 25.

    For the starting point of this debate, see Wittgenstein 1953: §§142–202; Kripke 1982; Hacker and Baker 1985.

  26. 26.

    My own arguments for this claim can be found in Ştefanov 2004.

  27. 27.

    I take this suggestion from Anscombe 1963.

  28. 28.

    This is different from saying that rule embedding artifacts are socially constructed (as in Bijker 1995) or “constructed and constructing” (as in Latour 1993), since according to either SCOT or ANT all artifacts are like this.

  29. 29.

    See Searle 2007, for instance.

  30. 30.

    It could also be noted that in the speed bumps example the artifact does not simply reduce the speed of the car. A driver could maintain a high speed when encountering a speed bump, at the risk of damaging her car suspensions. The opponent could of course reply that in this case speed bumps should not be considered “proper rule embedding artifacts”.

  31. 31.

    I have tried to give support to this idea in Ştefanov 2013.

  32. 32.

    To these could be added actions implied (i. e. necessary conditions in a routine) by your action of washing your hands (opening the bathroom door, turning on the water etc.).

  33. 33.

    Someone could be taught to play Hashiwokakero (See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hashiwokakero) only through such actions. It would be at least awkward to say that the rules of the game were communicated to such a learner.

  34. 34.

    A rule embedding artifact can, of course, incorporate some rules pertaining to its proper utilization as well. The addressees of these constitutive rules are its users (the people who place bumper speeds on roads, for instance), which are not the addressees of the regulative rules which the artifact embeds. The distinction between constitutive and regulative rules comes from Searle 1965, although its source can be traced back to Austin 1962.

  35. 35.

    To this one could add that unless we have a convenient way to naturalize concepts like ‘responsibility’ and ‘justification’, talking about rule embedding artifacts in a naturalist vocabulary would prevent us from asking questions like ‘Who is to assume responsibility for the production and use of rule embedding artifacts?’ or ‘How should we justify the rules to be embedded in some artifacts?’.

  36. 36.

    One could of course wonder what should be said about an artifact the practical use of which produces an entirely now practice. I think that such a case would fall outside the scope of what I have called ‘rule embedding artifacts’ here, since the artifact in question could only embed rules for its own use.

Bibliography

  • Akrich M (1992) The De-scription of technical objects. In: Wiebe E. Bijker, John Law (eds) Shaping technology/building society: studies in sociotechnical change. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 205–224

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe GEM (1963) Intention, 2nd edn. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin JL (1962) How to do things with words. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker LR (2008) The shrinking difference between artifacts and natural objects. Am Philos Assoc Newsl Philoso Comput 7(2):2–5

    Google Scholar 

  • Bijker WE (1995) Of bicycles, bakelites and bulbs: toward a theory of sociotechnical change. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom P (1996) Intention, history, and artifact concepts. Cognition 60:1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom RB (1994) Making it explicit. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom RB (2000) Articulating reasons. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom RB (2007) Inferentialism and some of its challenges. Philos Phenomen Res 74(3):651–676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dipert RR (1993) Artifacts, art works, and agency. Temple University Press, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Dipert RR (1995) Some issues in the theory of artifacts: defining “artifact” and related notions. Monist 78:119–135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franssen M (2009) Artefacts and normativity. In: Meijers A (ed) Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 923–952

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grice HP (1957) Meaning. Philos Rev 66:377–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice HP (1969) Utterer’s meaning and intention. Philos Rev 78(2):147–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker PMS, Baker GP (1985) Rules, grammar and necessity: an analytical commentary on the philosophical investigations. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1982) Conceptual role semantics. Notre Dame J Formal Logic 23:242–257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1999) Reasoning, meaning and mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1927) Sein und Zeit. Max Niemeyer Verlag, Tubingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilpinen R (2011) Artifact. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/artifact/

  • Horwich P (1994) What It is like to be a deflationary theory of meaning. In: Villanueva E (ed) Philosophical issues 5: truth and rationality. Ridgeview, Atascadero, pp 133–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Houkes W (2006) Knowledge of artefact functions. Stud Hist Philos Sci 37(1):102–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S (1982) Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroes P, Meijers A (2006) The dual nature of technical artifacts. Stud Hist Philos Sci 37:1–4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kroes P, Vermaaas PE (2008) Interesting differences between artifacts and natural objects. Am Philos Assoc Newsl Philos Comput 08(1):28–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour B (1993) We have never been modern (trans: Porter C). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour B (1999) Pandora’s hope: essays on the reality of science studies. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston B (2009) Philosophical theories of artifact function. In: Meijers A (ed) Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 213–233

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Radder H (2009) Why technologies are inherently normative. In: Meijers AWM (ed) Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 887–921

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1965) What is a speech act? In: Black M (ed) Philosophy in America. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, pp 221–239

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (2007) Social ontology and the philosophy of society. In: Margolis E, Laurence S (eds) Creations of the mind. Theories of artifacts and their representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York, pp 3–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars W (1969) Language as thought and as communication. Philos Phenomen Res 29(4):506–527

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skolimowski H (1966) The structure of thinking in technology. Technol Cult 7(3):371–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ştefanov G (2013) Opposing actions. Transylvanian Rev 22(2):121–131

    Google Scholar 

  • Ştefanov G (2004) How to be a good philosopher? Are there any rules?. Analele Universitatii Bucureşti – Filosofie 53:81–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson AL (2007) Artifacts and human concepts. In: Margolis E, Laurence S (eds) Creations of the mind. Theories of artifacts and their representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York, pp 52–73

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaesen K (2011) The functional bias of the dual nature of technical artefacts program. Stud Hist Philos Sci 42(1):190–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek P-P, Vermaas PE (2009) Technological artifacts. In: Jan Kyrre Berg Olsen Friis, Pedersen SA, Hendricks VF (eds) A companion to the philosophy of technology. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford, pp 165–171

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vermaas PE (2006) The physical connection: engineering function ascriptions to technical artefacts and their components. Stud Hist Philos Sci 37(1):62–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vermaas PE, Houkes W (2006) Technical functions: a drawbridge between the intentional and structural natures of technical artefacts. Stud Hist Philos Sci 37(1):5–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vries MJ, Hansson SO, Meijers A (eds) (2013) Norms in technology. Springer, Dordrecht/Heidelberg/New York/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1953) Philosophische Untersuchungen. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gheorghe Ştefanov .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ştefanov, G. (2015). On Rule Embedding Artifacts. In: Pȃrvu, I., Sandu, G., Toader, I. (eds) Romanian Studies in Philosophy of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 313. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-16655-1_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics