Skip to main content

Scientific Progress, Understanding and Unification

  • Chapter
Romanian Studies in Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 313))

Abstract

I review critically several accounts of scientific progress and discuss in some detail the most recent one, which I call the ‘knowledge-accumulation’ account. While I am sympathetic to it, I argue that it leaves out an important component of the notion of progress, namely the role of scientific understanding. A sketch of a complementary account (‘understanding-accumulation’) is offered, which construes understanding in terms of unification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Bird himself alludes to this idea in his (2007, 84): ‘I will however leave a detailed discussion of the important question of what contributions to knowledge contribute most to progress (and in particular the role of understanding) for another occasion—not least because it is a much more difficult question.’

  2. 2.

    To clarify: I shall be drawing on these views here, as I agree with the core idea. However, there are aspects of unificationism which I find problematic, but I can’t discuss them here.

  3. 3.

    Needless to say, I might have missed certain answers; the ones I discuss here are among the most prominent. My presentation and discussion of these accounts of progress, in this section and the next, owes a lot to Niiniluoto (2011) and Bird (2007).

  4. 4.

    For more on this, in the context of a discussion of scientific progress in relation to Thomas Kuhn, see Bird (2000).

  5. 5.

    Note that the proviso here is that the beliefs constituting knowledge are not only justified, but well-justified, or reliably, conclusively justified; that is, justified in such a way as to preclude the famous Gettier-type counterexamples (Gettier 1963).

  6. 6.

    Grimm (2013, forthcoming), Hindricks (2013), Khalifa and Gadomski (2013), Khalifa (2013), Newman (2013), Strevens (forthcoming). Earlier discussions include Trout (2002), de Regt and Dieks (2005), de Regt (2009), Elgin (2009).

  7. 7.

    Not everybody agrees that the main and only way to increase understanding is by resorting to scientific explanations; see, for instance, van Fraassen (1985, 642).

  8. 8.

    W. Salmon’s causal (ontic) conception of scientific explanation (Salmon 1984, 1998) is also motivated by the various failures of DN model. However, Salmon maintains that the core idea of this model (namely that explanations are derivations, or arguments) is inadequate.

  9. 9.

    The difficulties of the DN model are various (and notorious). One of the most important, whose solution was attempted by Friedman in his 1974 paper, stems from the so called ‘conjunction problem’: given two laws L and K, we can formally derive L from L&K but this cannot intuitively count as an explanation of L. Obviously, our understanding as to why L holds is not enhanced by this sort of derivation – explanation.

  10. 10.

    For endorsements and elaborations of unificationism, see for instance Weber (1999), Schurz (1999), Bartelborth (2002).

  11. 11.

    Suggestively, this is the context in which Lord Kelvin’s famously remarked ‘It seems to me that the test of ‘Do we or not understand a particular subject in physics?’ is ‘Can we make a mechanical model of it?’ (Kargon and Achinstein 1987, 3; 111).

  12. 12.

    Pauli says: ‘I, for one, see a basic distinction between Newton’s astronomy and Ptolemy’s. (…) To begin with, Newton posed the whole problem quite differently; he inquired into the causes of planetary motions not into the motions themselves. These causes, he discovered, were forces (…)’ (Heisenberg 1971, 32).

  13. 13.

    Strictly speaking, we derive descriptions of phenomenona, not the phenomena themselves. In this paper I use the word ‘phenomenon’ liberally, referring to any kind of thing explained in science (laws, events, facts, etc.)

  14. 14.

    As Salmon (2002, 94) points out, Friedman is too quick in assuming that counting the number of fundamental laws (what serves as basis of derivation) is possible.

  15. 15.

    Of course, one can reply that the explanans (Y) may be easier to understand, more ‘familiar’ than the phenomenon to be explained (X). Friedman counters this objection by arguing that familiarity (and other related notions) should not to be confused with intelligibility (1974, 10).

  16. 16.

    Friedman’s proposal prompted a number of insightful objections (Kitcher 1976; Barnes 1992b), but none of them will concern me here.

  17. 17.

    Friedman (1974, 14–5) refers to this as a fact (and I followed his usage) although this is not, strictly speaking, a fact; it is rather something that Kitcher (1981, 1989) calls a ‘type of fact’.

  18. 18.

    There is a vast literature criticizing the unificationist approach (part of it mentioned here), but I’m not sure this objection has been advanced before.

  19. 19.

    Note that even if we count the new basic truths added as items of knowledge, diagram (3) is still depicting a more desirable situation than diagrams (1) and (2): in (3) we have three new items of knowledge (U, p and q), as compared to only two (K and t) in (1), or only one (t) in (2).

Bibliography

  • Balzer W (2000) On approximate reduction. In Jonkisz and Koj (2000), pp 153–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes E (1992a) Explanatory unification and scientific understanding. In: Hull D, Forbes M, Okruhlik K (eds) PSA 1992, vol 1. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, pp 3–12

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes E (1992b) Explanatory unification and the problem of asymmetry. Philos Sci 59:558–571

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett JA (2008) Approximate truth and descriptive nesting. Erkenntnis 68:213–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartelborth T (2002) Explanatory unification. Synthese 130:91–107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (2000) Thomas Kuhn. Acumen, Chesham

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (2007) What is scientific progress? Noûs 41:92–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (2008) Scientific progress as accumulation of knowledge: a reply to Rowbottom. Stud Hist Philos Sci 39:279–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bragg W (1936) The progress of physical science. In: Jeans J et al (eds) 1936 scientific progress. George Allen and Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • De Regt HW (2009) Understanding and scientific explanation. In: de Regt HW, Leonelli S, Eigner K (eds) Scientific understanding: philosophical perspectives. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • De Regt HW, Dieks D (2005) A contextual approach to scientific understanding. Synthese 144:137–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dilworth C (1981) Scientific progress: a study concerning the nature of the relation between successive scientific theories. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin C (2009) Exemplification, idealization, and scientific understanding. In: Suarez M (ed) Fictions in sciences: philosophical essays on modeling and idealization. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl H (1970) The ‘orthodox’ view of theories: remarks in defense as well as critique. In: Radner M, Winokur S (eds) Minnesota studies in philosophy of science, vol IV. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P (1962) Explanation, reduction, and empiricism. In: Feigl H, Maxwell G (eds) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol II. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 28–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1974) Explanation and scientific understanding. J Philos 71:5–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1983) Foundations of space-time theories. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Gettier E (1963) Is justified true belied knowledge? Analysis 23:121–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm S (2013) Understanding. In: Pritchard D, Berneker S (eds) The Routledge companion to epistemology. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm S (forthcoming) Understanding as knowledge of causes. In: Fairweather A (ed) Virtue Scientia: essays in philosophy of science and virtue epistemology. Special issue of Synthese

    Google Scholar 

  • Halonen I, Hintikka J (1999) Unification – it’s magnificent but is it explanation? Synthese 120:27–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson P (1963) The concept of the positron. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg W (1971) Physics and beyond. Encounters and conversations. Translation from German by Pomerans AJ. Harper and Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel C (1965) Aspects of scientific explanation. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hindricks F (2013) Explanation, understanding, and unrealistic models. Stud Hist Philos Sci 44(3):523–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howson C (ed) (1976) Method and appraisal in the physical sciences: the critical background to modern science, 1800–1905. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys P (1993) Greater unification equals greater understanding? Analysis 53:183–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonkisz A (2000) On relative progress in science. In: Jonkisz and Koj (2000), pp 199–234

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonkisz A, Koj L (eds) (2000) On comparing and evaluating scientific theories. Rodopi, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Kargon R, Achinstein P (eds) (1987) Kelvin’s Baltimore lectures and modern theoretical physics. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa K (2013) The role of explanation in understanding. Brit J Philos Sci 64(1):161–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa K, Gadomski M (2013) Understanding as explanatory knowledge: the case of bjorken scaling. Stud Hist Philos Sci 44:384–392

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1976) Explanation, conjunction, and unification. J Philos 73:207–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1981) Explanatory unification. Philos Sci 48:507–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1985) Two approaches to explanation. J Philos 82:632–639

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1989) Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In: Kitcher P, Salmon W (eds) Scientific explanation, vol 13, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 410–505

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleiner SA (1993) The logic of discovery: a theory of the rationality of scientific research. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1st ed. 1962)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1977) The essential tension. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) (1970) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L (1977) Progress and its problems: toward a theory of scientific growth. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L et al (1986) Scientific change: philosophical models and historical research. Synthese 69:141–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison M (2000) Unifying scientific theories. Physical concepts and mathematical structures. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newman M (2013) Refining the inferential model of scientific understanding. Int Stud Philos Sci 27:173–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto I (1987) Truthlikeness. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto I (1995) Is there progress in science? In: Stachowiak H (ed) Pragmatik, Handbuch pragmatischen Denkens, Band V. Felix Meiner Verlag, Hamburg, pp 30–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto I (2010) Theory change, truthlikeness, and belief revision. In: Suárez M et al (eds) EPSA epistemology and methodology of science. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 189–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto I (2011) Scientific progress. In: The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition), Zalta EN (ed), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/scientific-progress/

  • Popper K (1959) The logic of scientific discovery. Hutchinson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1963) Conjectures and refutations: the growth of scientific knowledge. Hutchinson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1972) Objective knowledge: an evolutionary approach. Oxford University Press, Oxford. 2nd enlarged ed. 1979

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos S (1999) Scientific realism: how science tracks truth. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher N (1978) Scientific progress: a philosophical essay on the economics of research in natural science. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon W (1984) Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon W (1998) Causality and explanation. University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon W (2002) Scientific explanation: causation and unification. In: Balashov Y, Rosenberg A (eds) Philosophy of science. Contemporary readings. Routledge, London, pp 92–105, First published in Critica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofia, 1990, 22(66): 3–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheibe E (1976) Conditions of progress and comparability of theories. In: Cohen RS et al (eds) Essays on memory of Imre Lakatos. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 547–568

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz G (1999) Explanation as unification. Synthese 120:95–114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller W (1976) The structure and dynamics of theories. Springer, New York/Heidelberg/Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens M (2004) The causal and unification approaches to explanation unified – causally. Nous 38(1):154–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens M (2008) Depth: an account of scientific explanation. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens M (forthcoming) No understanding without explanation. In: Studies in history and philosophy of science Part A

    Google Scholar 

  • Trout JD (2002) Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philos Sci 69:212–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen BC (1985) Salmon on explanation. J Philos 82:639–651

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber E (1999) Unification: what is it, how do we reach it and why do we want it? Synthese 118:479–499

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank the editors for soliciting my contribution, an anonymous referee for suggestions and Alexander Bird for reading an early draft. I presented sections of this paper at Aarhus University and I’m grateful to Sam Schindler, Sara Green and Helge Kragh for comments. All responsibility for possible errors remains mine. I dedicate this paper to the memory of M-R. Solcan.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sorin Bangu .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bangu, S. (2015). Scientific Progress, Understanding and Unification. In: Pȃrvu, I., Sandu, G., Toader, I. (eds) Romanian Studies in Philosophy of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 313. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-16655-1_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics