Skip to main content

Why Seeing is a Problem

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Seeing as Practice

Part of the book series: Performance Philosophy ((PPH))

  • 182 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter elicits the problems that have arisen from splitting seeing into receptivity on the one hand and intellectual spontaneity on the other. It explores possible alternative theoretical approaches. Seeing as a way of disclosing the apparent, perceptible world cannot be explained in purely either physiological or cognitive terms. Specific to the faculty of seeing is its proximity to processes of understanding, thinking and interpreting. When someone notices something in someone else, they are not merely decoding certain sensory signs, but seeing and understanding at the same time. Sight and insight, seeing and ways of seeing are therefore intertwined in a way that needs to be explained against the background of an entirely different theoretical framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Ralf Konersmann (1997, p. 23) has provided a lucid description of the contradictions inherent to both valorisations and devaluations of the faculty of vision: “Although Platonic-biblical thinking visualised the logos, the history of the ocular sense was not triumphal. The consistent intellectualist demand has been to deny acknowledgement to the appearance of the world.”

  2. 2.

    Gérard Simon describes optics since Descartes as “physics of light,” The eyes cease to be the point of issue of an optic ray to become a camera obscura: “A camera obscura whose opening is the pupil, whose membrane is the iris, whose contractible camera lens is the crystal lens and whose screen on which the image appears is the retina” (ibid., p. 19).

  3. 3.

    Gernot Böhme (2000, p. 203ff.) interprets Plato’s theory of perception as a phenomenological. Indications of a correlation theory of perception, in which the entity seen and the entity seeing are mutually determined, can also be found in Plato (Theaetetus 159e-160a).

  4. 4.

    Luce Irigaray. Quoted in M. Jay (1992, p. 493).

  5. 5.

    Very convincing in this respect is Kaja Silverman’s (1997) treatment of the art of Cindy Sherman.

  6. 6.

    A similar line of argumentation is found in D. C. Dennett (1991).

  7. 7.

    Irvin Rock (1985) has explained this in evolutionarily biological terms as the “intelligence of perception.” See also Wolf Singer (2005, p. 148): “Our perceptions are not isomorphic pictures of some reality. They are instead the result of highly complex constructions and interpretation processes that rely heavily on stored knowledge.” Picturesque renditions of the neurobiological wonders of vision are contained in David Hubel’s (1988) compendium.

  8. 8.

    Distinctions such as those made by Jerry Fodor (1990) between sense impressions and cognitively structured perceptions simply defer the problem.

  9. 9.

    See the studies by M. Drechsler (1995) and Lambert Wiesing’s (2002, p. 27ff.) commentary.

  10. 10.

    The British art historian John Ruskin (1858) coined the expression “innocence of the eye” in connection with early modern painting. Ernst Gombrich (1960) has explained in detail, why there can be no such thing as an innocent eye. I will return to this in more detail.

  11. 11.

    Austin (1962) critiques this from a linguistic viewpoint.

  12. 12.

    This claim is made by R. Brandt (1999).

  13. 13.

    Jonathan Crary (1988) made an interesting comment on this, comparing the Cartesian observer to the observer from Goethe’s colour theory.

  14. 14.

    Ralf Konersmann (1995) has cast doubt on this attribution.

  15. 15.

    Strawson’s critique of the correspondence theory of truth seems to refer primarily to talk about perception, not to perception itself.

  16. 16.

    Sellars attack is directed less at the conception of sense data than the validity of arguments based on sense data.

  17. 17.

    See W. Künne’s (1995) sophistic example of a bald man wearing the mask of a bald man in order to conceal a scar. The judgement is correct that the man is bald, although the sense impression involves an illusion.

  18. 18.

    Ralph Schumacher’s (2004) Reconstruction of Berkeley convincingly shows that Berkeley‘s theory of perception is capable of explaining why some perceptions can display such independence from beliefs, despite the fact that perception is fundamentally subject to the influence of experience and habits.

  19. 19.

    Dretske (1969, p. 20) contests that the utterance “that D looks some way to S” also means “for some character C, it looks to S as though (as if) D (or something) were C,” which would imply the existence of a form of non-epistemic seeing. His plea for a distinction between perception, beliefs, opinions etc. is however in large part founded on the contrary claim: “D can look some way to S without it looking to S as though it were C (for any C).”

  20. 20.

    S. Krämer (2003) has commented on this insightfully, also in (Krämer 2001).

  21. 21.

    This aspect of epistemic seeing is also heavily emphasised by R. Chisholm (1957).

  22. 22.

    In that they depend on the performance of an act of seeing. Cf. III.1.a)-c).

  23. 23.

    On the concept of non-propositional cognisance and thought, see G. Gabriel (1997) and C. Schildknecht (1999).

  24. 24.

    Christiane Schildknecht (2003) has argued that because there exist non-conceptual sense impressions, we should make a distinction between content of perception and content of conviction, qualifying the way an object looks as something that is irreducible to propositional content.

  25. 25.

    M. Seel (2004) has pointed out that seeing-something-in-something is not even the same as representative or iconic seeing. Seeing faces in clouds or wall marks does not mean they have been represented there.

  26. 26.

    For an updated version, see E. W. Orth (1992).

  27. 27.

    On Cassirer’s conception of consciousness and the parallels to Husserl’s concept of intentionality, see M. Plümacher (2004).

  28. 28.

    Cassirer occasionally loses sight of his own insight when he disconnects this self-sufficient world of perception from the “world of sense impressions” in which we touch merely the “surface of reality” (ibid., p. 169).

  29. 29.

    See B. Recki (2004, p. 26). Recki reconstructs Cassirer‘s concept of culture as “the medium of our poietic-practical self interpretation.” However, the performativity of this self and world interpretation is receiving increasingly less attention. The emphasis is instead placed on its normative connections to the values and rules of a language community.

  30. 30.

    Oswald Schwemmer’s (1997) work is helpful here in explaining the ethico-aesthetical connection between form-giving and form-becoming. The concept of an interaction between a form formans and a form formata in Cassirer’s posthumous writings could supply an appropriate basis for a reformulation of his ideas in terms of performance theory.

  31. 31.

    Ricoeur seems to me to somewhat uncritically overestimate the role of narration in developing order and founding unity. His classical leading figure is Odysseus on the way to himself and finally arriving. The errors and losses on this journey of self-discovery are generally blocked out.

  32. 32.

    The advantages and disadvantages of this transformation for personal relations to the self are explored by Dieter Thomä (1998). Thomä approaches the subject from the question: What is right living? Narrative is a more appropriate way to develop an adequate image of one’s own life than the traditional projects of self-recognition. Although narrative can never answer the leading question, it can help “to experience, how I am and to construct what is important to me about me” (ibid., p. 15).

  33. 33.

    Taylor develops his argumentation in the confrontation with Harry Frankfurt’s claims about reflexive wishing and second order desires. His examples show the constitutive function of the vocabulary used for evaluative, reflected action and the way self-interpretation and experience are mutually conditioned: “self-interpretations are partly constitutive of our experience” (Taylor 2010, p. 37).

  34. 34.

    Nelson’s suggestion that visuality is to vision what sexuality is to sex (the former socially, the latter biologically) drags soul–body dualism back into the debate. Hal Foster (1988) denounced this split into the nature and culture of seeing back in 1988.

  35. 35.

    In this context, Dieter Hoffman-Axthelm’s (1984) study is also relevant as a visual culture reading.

  36. 36.

    Hans Dieter Huber’s (2004) investigation strikes a good balance between the appropriate consideration of environmental conditions and internal iconic and aesthetic factors.

  37. 37.

    This is not the place to pit the omnipresence of images in our culture against the dominant text paradigm. Such polemic polarisation is superfluous and indeed counter-productive since it is conditioned by what it attempts to resist.

  38. 38.

    Jonathan Crary’s (1992) study, is one such example of an examination of the technical-practical. It shows how, in the nineteenth century, geometrical optics were replaced by physiological optics and explores the effects this technical innovation had on the role of the observer.

References

  • Abel, Günter. 1993. Interpretationswelten. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angehrn, Emil. 2003. Interpretation und Dekonstruktion. Weilerswist: Velbrück.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1959. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, David M. 1961. Perception and the Physical World. London: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, John Langshaw. 1962. Sense and Sensibilia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, Alfred. 1940. The Foundation of Empirical Knowledge. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, George. 1948. The Works of George Berkeley, Vol. 1: Philosophical Commentaries—Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision. London: Nelson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Böhme, Gernot. 2000. Platons theoretische Philosophie. Stuttgart: Metzler.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, Reinhard. 1999. Die Wirklichkeit des Bildes. Munich: Hanser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bryson, Norman, Ann Holly, Michael, and Moxey, Keith (ed.). 1994. Visual Culture: Images and Interpretations. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, Ernst. 1957. The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, Volume Three: The Phenomenology of Knowledge. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, Ernst. 1962. An Essay on Man: An Introduction in the Philosophy of Human Culture. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, Roderick. 1957. Perceiving. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Condillac, Étienne Bonnot de. 1754. Traité des sensations. Paris: De Bure, l’aine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crary, Jonathan. 1988. Modernizing Vision. In Vision and Visuality, ed. Hal Foster, 29–49. Seattle: Bay Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crary, Jonathan. 1992. Techniques of the Observer. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crary, Jonathan. 2001. Suspensions of Perception: Attention, Spectacle, and Modern Culture. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drechsler, Martin. 1995. Sinnesdaten. In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, Bd. 9, Columns 875–882, ed. Joachim Ritter et al. Basel: Schwabe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred. 1969. Seeing and Knowing. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiedler, Konrad. 1991. Schriften zur Kunst. Munich: Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry. 1990. Observation Reconsidered. In A Theory of Content and Other Essays, 231–251. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster, Hal (ed.). 1988. Vision and Visuality. Seattle: Bay Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1995. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabriel, Gottfried. 1997. Logisches und analogisches Denken. In Sprache und Denken, ed. Alex Burri, 370–384. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 2006. Truth and Method. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, Ernst. 1960. Art and Illusion. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Nelson. 1976. Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Nelson. 1978. Ways of Worldmaking. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1957. Meaning. The Philosophical Review 64: 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hauschild, Thomas. 1982. Der Böse Blick. Berlin: Verlag Mensch und Leben.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1996. Being and Time. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman-Axthelm, Dieter. 1984. Sinnesarbeit. Frankfurt am Main: Campus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubel, David. 1988. Eye, Brain, and Vision. New York: W. H. Freeman & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, Hans Dieter. 2004. Bild, Beobachter, Milieu. Ostfildern: Hatje Cantz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irigaray, Luce. 1985. This Sex Which Is Not One. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irigaray, Luce. 1987. Speculum of the Other Woman. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, William. 1950. The Principles of Psychology. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jay, Martin. 1993. Downcast Eyes. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jencks, Christ. 1995. The Centrality of the Eye in Western Culture. In Visual Culture, 1–25. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans. 1954. The nobility of sight. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 14 (4): 507–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, Wolfgang. 1969. The Task of Gestalt Psychology. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kompridis, Nikolas. 1993. Über Welterschließung. Deutsche Zeitschrift Für Philosophie 41 (3): 525–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konersmann, Ralf. 1995. Sehen. In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie Bd. 9, ed. Joachim Ritter et al., columns 121–161, Basel: Schwabe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konersmann, Ralf. 1997. Die Augen der Philosophen. In Kritik des Sehens, 9–47. Leipzig: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krämer, Sybille. 2003. Was tut Austin, indem er über das Performative spricht? In Performativität und Praxis, ed. Jens Kertscher et al., 19–33. Munich: Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krämer, Sybille. 2001. Sprache, Sprechakt, Kommunikation. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Künne, Wolfgang. 1995. Sehen. Eine Sprachanalytische Betrachtung. Logos 2: 103–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, Susanne K. 1979. Philosophy in a New Key: A Study in the Symbolism of Reason, Rite, and Art. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, David (ed.). 1993. Modernity and the Hegemony of Vision. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1975. An essay Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2007. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majetschak, Stefan. 1989. Welt als Begriff und Welt als Kunst. Philosophisches Jahrbuch 96: 276–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1962. Phenomenology of Perception. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mirzoeff, Nicholas (ed.). 1999. An Introduction to Visual Culture. London: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, George Edward. 1953. Some Main Problems of Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, R. (ed.). 2000. Visuality Before and Beyond the Renaissance: Seeing as Others Saw. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orth, Ernst Wolfgang. 1992. Ernst Cassirers Philosophie der symbolischen Formen und ihre Bedeutung für unsere Gegenwart. Deutsche Zeitschrift Für Philosophie 40 (1/2): 119–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plümacher, Martina. 2004. Wahrnehmung, Repräsentation und Wissen. Berlin: Parerga.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1953a. On What There Is. In From a Logical Point of View, 1–19. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1953b. Two Dogmas of Empiricism. In From a Logical Point of View, 21–46. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recki, Birgit. 2004. Kultur als Praxis. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ricœur, Paul. 1984, 1985, 1988. Time and Narrative, 3 vols. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rock, Irvin. 1985. The Logic of Perception. New York: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1989. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1998. Robert Brandom on Social Practices and Representations. In Truth and Progress, Philosophical Papers, Volume 3, 122–137. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruskin, John. 1858. The Elements of Drawing. London: Smith, Elder & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schildknecht, Christiane. 1999. Aspekte des Nichtpropositionalen. Bonn: Bouvier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schildknecht, Christiane. 2003. Anschauungen ohne Begriffe? Deutsche Zeitschrift Für Philosophie 51: 459–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schumacher, Ralph. 2004. Die kognitive Undurchdringbarkeit optischer Täuschungen. George Berkeleys Theorie visueller Wahrnehmung im Kontext neuerer Ansätze. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 58.4: 505–525.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwemmer, Oswald. 1997. Ernst Cassirer. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John. 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Seel, Martin. 2004. Aesthetics of Appearing. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seel, Martin. 2002. Über Richtigkeit und Wahrheit. In Sich bestimmen lassen, 45–67. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, Wilfrid. 1956. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Harvard Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverman, Kaja. 1997. Dem Blickregime begegnen. In Privileg Blick, ed. Christian Kravagna, 41–64. Berlin: Id-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, Gérard. 1992. Der Blick, das Sein und die Erscheinung in der antiken Optik. Munich: Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, Josef, and Stegmaier, Werner (ed.). 1994. Zeichen und Interpretation, 4 Vols. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Wolf. 2005. Das Bild im Kopf – aus neurobiologischer Perspektive. In Sichtweisen, ed. Bernhard Graf et al., 143–160. Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, Peter. 1979. Perception and its Objects. In Perception and Identity, ed. Graham F. Macdonald, 41–60. London: Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1985. Self-Interpreting Animals. In Human Agency and Language, 45–76. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 2010. What Is Agency? In Philosophical Papers: Human Agency and Language, Vol. 1, 15–44. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomä, Dieter. 1998. Erzähle Dich selbst. Munich: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welsch, Wolfgang. 2000. Hegel und die analytische Philosophie. Information Philosophie 1: 7–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiesing, Lambert (ed.). 2002. Philosophie der Wahrnehmung. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Schuermann, E. (2019). Why Seeing is a Problem. In: Seeing as Practice. Performance Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-14507-1_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics