Identity Politics and the Limits of Moral Pluralism

  • Katherine Smits

Abstract

Identity groups define the essentials of group membership in different ways, not surprisingly, depending on the exigencies of their social situations. Such definitions also change over time, as a group’s social standing comes under new and different pressures relative to other groups. In many cases, groups that emerged with strong claims of shared and deep identity, go on to complicate and qualify their claims to such an extent that some internal critics worry aloud that the claim of commonality has ceased to be meaningful. Feminism offers a good example of this: when the second-wave women’s movement began, feminists argued that women shared a fundamental identity based on sex. Women of color and lesbians first challenged this essential commonality on political grounds; postmodernist feminists have since deconstructed it philosophically. The political claims identity groups make and the bases for them have also differed, depending upon whether groups represent race, ethnicity, nationality, gender, or sexuality (to list some common but hardly nonexhaustive social cleavages). The variations here turn on the impact of membership upon individuals, and the degree of public recognition they seek. Some identity groups claim a determining relationship between group membership and individual identity; some a looser and more complex connection. Some have demanded political autonomy; some, recognition in existing political institutions, such as guaranteed seats in parliament; some, the inclusion of group history and culture in educational curricula.

Keywords

Posit Bors Defend Blindness Verse 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 1.
    Amy Gutmann, Identity in Democracy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003), 30.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Paul Hirst distinguishes these “communities of fate” from voluntary associations in Associative Democracy: New Forms of Economic and Social Governance (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1994), 49–56. I discuss Hirst’s work in detail in chapter 3. I should note here that “fate” in the sense I am using it refers to the fate of ascription—and nothing either more metaphysical or natural. Further, it is not always impossible to leave communities of fate: people can sometimes move between classes, occasionally “pass” as members of another race or ethnic group, conceal a religious identity and even change sex. But exit is not a simple matter of deciding no longer to belong, as it is from voluntary associations.Google Scholar
  3. 4.
    Iris Marion Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990), 44. Young provides an extended definition of the concept of a social group, on which I draw, at 42–5. There does exist nevertheless a closer relationship between social group and associational membership than theorists of each, such as Young and Hirst, admit. I explore the importance of this for liberalism in my conclusion.Google Scholar
  4. 5.
    K. Anthony Appiah, “Race, Culture, Identity: Misunderstood Connections,” Color Conscious: The Political Morality of Race, K. Anthony Appiah and Amy Gutmann (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 30–105.Google Scholar
  5. 6.
    Ian Hacking discusses the process by which types of individuals or groups are brought into existence by our naming of them, which he terms “dynamic nominalism,” in “Making Up People,” in Reconstructing Individualism: Autonomy, Individuality and the Self in Western Thought, ed. Thomas C. Heller, Morton Sosna, and David E. Wellbery (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1986), 222–36.Google Scholar
  6. 7.
    For an exploration of this see: The Making of the Modern Homosexual, ed. Kenneth Plummer (London: Hutchinson, 1981).Google Scholar
  7. 9.
    Two important examples in a large body of work are: Sara Ruddick, Maternal Thinking: Towards a Politics of Peace (Boston: Beacon, 1989)Google Scholar
  8. and Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
  9. 11.
    W.E.B. DuBois, Dusk of Dawn: An Essay Toward an Autobiography of a Race Concept (Milwood: Kraus-Thomson, 1975), 116–17, cited in Appiah, “Race, Culture, Identity,” 75.Google Scholar
  10. 12.
    John D’Emilio, Sexual Politics, Sexual Communities: The Making of a Homosexual Minority in the United States (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983).Google Scholar
  11. 13.
    Stephen Cornell, The Return of the Native: American Indian Political Resurgence (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), 72.Google Scholar
  12. 14.
    Susan Wolf, “Comment,” in Multiculturalism, ed. Amy Gutmann (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), 76.Google Scholar
  13. 15.
    See John C. Turner et al., Rediscovering the Social Group: A Self-Categorization Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987).Google Scholar
  14. 19.
    See e.g., Will Kymlicka: a culture “provides its members with meaningful ways of life across the full range of human activities, including social, educational, religious, recreational and economic life, encompassing both public and private spheres.” Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), 76. Gutmann cites this to support her own distinction between cultural and ascriptive groups in Identity in Democracy, 216, fn. 36.Google Scholar
  15. 22.
    Shane Phelan, “All the Comforts of Home: The Genealogy of Community,” in Revisioning the Political: Feminist Reconstructions of Traditional Concepts in Western Political Theory, ed. Nancy J. Hirschmann and Christine Di Stefano (Boulder: Westview, 1996), 244.Google Scholar
  16. 24.
    Toni Morrison, Playing in the Dark: Whiteness and the Literary Imagination (New York: Vintage, 1993).Google Scholar
  17. 25.
    Andrew Hacker, Two Nations: Black and White, Separate, Hostile, Unequal (New York: Scribner’s, 1992), 32 and chapter 3 in general.Google Scholar
  18. 29.
    See Zillah Eisensteins discussion of the implications of engendering bodies in The Female Body and the Law (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988), 79–91. There is also a discussion of specific group needs in: Nancy Fraser, Unruly Practices (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989).Google Scholar
  19. 31.
    John Locke, A Letter Concerning Toleration, ed. James H. Tully (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983).Google Scholar
  20. 32.
    Phillips, Democracy and Difference (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993), 139.Google Scholar
  21. 33.
    As Charles Larmore points out, moral pluralism may be understood either philosophically or sociologically. In the philosophical sense, assumed by Isaiah Berlin, human ideals are not all compatible, and the fulfillment of some will make others impossible. Both theory and ordinary experience force us to recognize a plurality of values, and to accept that there exists no single set of unified moral truths, nor any “final harmony in which all riddles are solved, all contradictions reconciled.” Because there can be no single correct answer to questions of competing values, Berlin argues that government cannot be justified in prescribing or supporting any one conception of the good. It must instead allow people the “negative freedom” to pursue whichever ends they choose. In the sociological sense, reasonable individuals will inevitably disagree about conceptions of the good, whether or not any unified hierarchy of moral values exists in a philosophical sense. For the purposes of my argument, it is not necessary to decide between these. Whether or not moral pluralism exists ultimately in a philosophical sense, as Larmore points out, most liberal pluralists assume the sociological definition, which ties moral plurality to actually existing social groups. See Charles Larmore, The Morals of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 152–74;CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Isaiah Berlin, “Two Concepts of Liberty,” in Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 167–72. See also, “The Pursuit of the Ideal” and “The Decline of Utopian Ideas in the West,” in Berlin’s The Crooked Timber of Humanity (New York: Knopf, 1991), 20–48. For a detailed discussion of the types and sources of moral pluralism that does not, however, venture much on its implications for liberal political theory, seeGoogle Scholar
  23. Steven Lukes, “Making Sense of Moral Conflict,” in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Rosenblum (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989), 127–42.Google Scholar
  24. 34.
    This term is Rawls’s: Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993). I use it here to refer generally to liberals who argue from moral pluralism.Google Scholar
  25. 35.
    I borrow these terms from Anne Phillips, who points out that the politics of ideas has proved inadequate to dealing with problems of minority group exclusion. Phillips argues that excluded groups must be brought themselves into political debate. See Anne Phillips, “Dealing with Difference: A Politics of Ideas or a Politics of Presence?” Constellations 1, 1 (1994): 74–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. 37.
    See Michael Walzer, “The Communitarian Critique of Liberalism,” Political Theory 18, 1 (February 1990): 6–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. 38.
    See e.g., Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), andGoogle Scholar
  28. Alasdair MacIntyre, Afler Virtue (Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 1984).Google Scholar
  29. 39.
    A crude form of this position is popular amongst conservative opponents of multicultural education. For an instance of its influence on liberal thinkers, see Arthur Schlesinger Jr., The Disuniting of America (New York: Norton, 1992).Google Scholar
  30. 40.
    Charles Taylor remarks that it is only by clarifying ontological issues that the debate between liberals and communitarians can be seen as “the complex, many-leveled affair that it really is.” See Charles Taylor, “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate,” in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy Rosenblum (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), 182.Google Scholar
  31. 43.
    As Kymlicka points out in Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 226.Google Scholar
  32. 44.
    This is also the view elaborated by Ronald Dworkin in his article often taken to be definitional of modern liberalism: “Liberalism,” in Public and Private Morality, ed. Stuart Hampshire (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), 127.Google Scholar
  33. 45.
    Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), 398.Google Scholar
  34. 46.
    William Galston refers to the political liberalisms I examine here as “freestanding monist” approaches to political theory. See Galston, Liberal Pluralism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. 47.
    John Rawls, “Justice as Fairness: Political—Not Metaphysical,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1988): 223–51.Google Scholar
  36. 48.
    John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Belknap Press, 1971).Google Scholar
  37. 65.
    J. Donald Moon, Constructing Community: Moral Pluralism and Tragic Conflicts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
  38. 80.
    Charles E. Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 42–8, 50–5. Larmore distinguishes between moral pluralism and reasonable disagreement in “Pluralism and Reasonable Disagreement,” in Cultural Pluralism and Moral Knowledge, ed. Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr., and Jeffrey Paul (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 61–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. 84.
    See e.g.: Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Post Modernism in Contemporary Ethics (Cambridge: Polity, 1992); Taylor, “Politics of Recognition,” in Multiculturalism, ed. Gutmann.Google Scholar
  40. 88.
    Richard E. Flathman, The Philosophy and Politics of Freedom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 173–4. Stanley Benn argues that we attribute value to autonomy because of our capacity to be autarchic, or to have agency—the minimal capacity for human choice. Autonomy represents thus the ideal human state possible, given agency. SeeGoogle Scholar
  41. Stanley Benn, “Freedom, Autonomy and the Concept of the Person,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76 (1975–1976): 109–30.Google Scholar
  42. 89.
    Loren Lomasky describes agents as “project pursuers” in Persons, Rights and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).Google Scholar
  43. 92.
    David Johnston, The Idea of a Liberal Theory: A Critique and Reconstruction (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), 23.Google Scholar
  44. 93.
    Gerald Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. 98.
    Nancy Rosenblum, Another Liberalism: Romanticism and the Reconstruction of Liberal Thought (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. 105.
    See e.g.: Amy Gutmann, “Communitarian Critics of Liberalism,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14, 3 (Summer 1985), 319.Google Scholar
  47. 108.
    This form of reflection and evaluation would not be strong enough for some liberals. I am not arguing, as John Gray does, that what is involved here is a distancing of the autonomous agent from her social environment and the influence of others. See John Gray, Mill on Liberty: A Defence (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1983), 74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. 111.
    Joshua Cohen, “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus,” in The Idea of Democracy, ed. David Copp, Jean Hampton, and John E. Roemer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 274.Google Scholar
  49. 112.
    See e.g., Fay Ginsburg, Contested Lives: The Abortion Debate in an American Community (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989), conclusion.Google Scholar
  50. 113.
    See e.g., Peter Jones, “Respecting Beliefs and Rebuking Rushdie,” in Liberalism, Multiculturalism and Toleration, ed. John Horton (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1993), 114–38. Charles Taylor also invokes the Rushdie case in “The Politics of Recognition,” in Multiculturalism, 62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Katherine Smits 2005

Authors and Affiliations

  • Katherine Smits

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations