Skip to main content
  • 84 Accesses

Abstract

The power of the intellect to grasp concepts and truths intuitively that are neither derivable from sense perception, such as the concept of infinity, nor justifiable by empirical evidence, such as inviolable principles of ethics, has been widely considered a characteristic that sets humans apart from all other earthly creatures. Intuitive knowing is among the intellectual powers we have often ascribed to ourselves, a power first recognized in ancient Greek thought. Plato, Aristotle, and their scientific predecessors have operated on the assumption that “like is known only by like,” and consequently interpret our capacity to grasp general concepts, which admit (in theory) of an infinite number of instances, and to know ultimate truths, to involve a different “faculty” from that by which we sense or imagine the properties of ordinary objects. These ancient thinkers have observed that our apprehension of sensed properties of objects, such as their smell and shape, is shared by many animals that exhibit no evidence of the rational power of grasping the general concepts involved in the truth of an intelligible statement. Until recent times, the classical understanding of human rationality prevailed, but modern evolution is focusing its attention on the continuities between animal and human life, not the differences. The scope of human rationality, and the extent of our rational powers, has never been convincingly fixed. Indeed, whether we could do so is unclear, and the occurrence of intuitive knowing contributes to questions about our ability to establish these limits.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. According to the famous German classicist of a century ago, Erwin Rohde (1966) Psyche: The Cult of Souls and Belief in Immortality among the Greeks, 8th edn, 2 vols. (trans. W. B. Hillis) (New York: Harper & Row), pp. 380–83.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Walter Kaufmann (1968) Philosophic Classics: Volume I: Thales to Ockham, 2nd edn (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall), p. 45.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Francis M. Cornford (ed. and trans.) The Republic of Plato (London: Oxford University Press, 1945), Bk. VI, 508d.

    Google Scholar 

  4. De Anima, Richard McKeon (ed.) The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York: Random House, 1966), Bk. 3, Chapter 4.

    Google Scholar 

  5. St Augustine of Hippo (1982) The Literal Meaning of Genesis (trans. J. H. Taylor) (New York: Newman Press), (“Lit. Gen”. hereafter), vol. 12, passim.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Evelyn Underhill (1930) Mysticism: A Study in the Nature and Development of Man’s Spiritual Consciousness, 12th rev. edn (London: Methuen), p. 283.

    Google Scholar 

  7. This is implied by much earlier writers, such as Titus Lucretius Carus (1951) On the Nature of the Universe (trans. R. E. Latham) (London: Penguin Books), bk. V, 1167–81.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Thomas Aquinas (1948) Summa Theologica (“ST ” hereafter) in Fathers of the English Dominican Province II.I.111 (ST, second part, part I, ques. 111), I.55 (part I, ques. 55), and other passages.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See John of the Cross (1987) Ascent of Mount Carmel (London: SPCK) for extended discussion.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See The Life of Saint Teresa of Avila by Herself (trans. J. M. Cohen) (London: Penguin Books, 1957), and The Interior Castle or The Mansions (trans. K. Kavanaugh, and O. Rodriguez) (London: SPCK, 1979); cf. Phillip H. Wiebe (1999) “The Christic Visions of Teresa of Avila,” Scottish Journal of Religious Studies, 20, 73–87, where I discuss the possibility that some of her experiences were corporeal, in spite of her insistence that she never experienced corporeal vision.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For examples of modern commentators who adopt the Augustinian classification in discussing Julian’s experience, see Paul Molinari (1958) Julian of Norwich: The Teaching of a 14th Century English Mystic (London: Longman, Green & Co.);

    Google Scholar 

  12. Grace Jantzen (1987) Julian of Norwich: Mystic and Theologian (London: SPCK);

    Google Scholar 

  13. Brant Pelfrey (1989) Christ our Mother: Julian of Norwich (London: Darton, Longman and Todd);

    Google Scholar 

  14. Frances Beer (1992) Women and Mystical Experience in the Middle Ages (Woodbridge, UK: Boydell Press);

    Google Scholar 

  15. and Ritamary Bradley (1992) Julian’s Way: A Practical Commentary on Julian of Norwich (London: Harper Collins).

    Google Scholar 

  16. See articles on visions and related phenomena in Charles Herbermann, Edward A. Pace, Conde B. Pallen, Thomas J. Shahan, and John J. Wynne (eds.) (1912) The Catholic Encyclopedia 15 vols (New York: Robert Appleton);

    Google Scholar 

  17. W. J. McDonald (primary ed.) and Catholic University of America (1967) New Catholic Encyclopedia 18 vols (New York: McGraw-Hill);

    Google Scholar 

  18. and Karl Rahner (ed.) (1975) Encyclopedia of Theology: A Concise Sacramentum Mundi (London: Burns & Oates).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Adomnán of Iona (1995) Life of St Columba (trans. Richard Sharpe) (London: Penguin), bk. 1, Chapter 37; my ital.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See the accounts related in C. Bernard Ruffin (1991) Padre Pio: The True Story (Revised and Expanded) (Huntington, IN: Our Sunday Visitor), esp. Chapter 28.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Phillip H Wiebe (1997) Visions of Jesus: Direct Encounters from the New Testament to Today (New York: Oxford University Press), Chapter 3.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Caroline Franks Davis (1989) The Evidential Force of Religious Experience (Oxford: Clarendon), Chapter 1.

    Google Scholar 

  23. William James (1960) The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature (London: Collins), lect. 9 and 10.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Rudolf Otto (1950) The Idea of the Holy: An Inquiry into the Non-Rational Factor in the Idea of the Divine and its Relation to the Rational, 2nd edn (trans. John W. Harvey) (London: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  25. A biography of Otto’s spiritually formative years is given in Gregory Alles (2001) “Toward a Genealogy of the Holy: Rudolf Otto and the Apologetics of Religion,” Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 69, 323–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Davis, The Evidential Force, p. 19. This definition is similar to that found in Simon Blackburn (ed.) (1994) The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press): “a stream of private events, known only to their possessor … [which] makes up the conscious life of the possessor,” p. 130.

    Google Scholar 

  27. I follow Stephen Braude (1986) The Limits of Influence: Psychokinesis and the Philosophy of Science (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul), in placing evidence into three classes.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. Marghanita Laski (1990) Ecstasy in Secular and Religious Experiences (Los Angeles: Jeremy P. Tarcher), Chapter 1, for general discussion of the kinds of experience widely considered ecstatic.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ludwig Wittgenstein (1967) Philosophical Investigations (trans. G. E. M. Anscombe) (Oxford: Blackwell), part. I.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Daniel Pals (1996) Seven Theories of Religion (New York: Oxford University Press), p. 270, based on a study of Sir James Frazer, Sigmund Freud, Emile Durkheim, Mircea Eliade, E. E. Evans-Pritchard, E. B. Tylor, and Clifford Geertz. This definition does not capture the Buddhist understanding of spirituality.

    Google Scholar 

  31. See Jonathan Z. Smith (2010) “Tillich’s Remains … ,” Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 78, 1139–70, for a review of this in American academic culture (and beyond).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Graham Ward (2006) “The Future of Religion,” Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 74, 183.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ann Taves (2009) Religious Experience Reconsidered: A Building-Block Approach to the Study of Religion and Other Special Things (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press), Chapter 1.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ann Taves (2011) “2010 Presidential Address: ‘Religion’ in the Humanities and the Humanities in the University,” Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 79, 287–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Daryl Bem, John Palmer, and Richard S. Broughton (1990) “Updating the Ganzfeld Database: A Victim of Its Own Success?” Journal of Parapsychology, 65, 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Thomas O. Nelson, and Louis Narens (1994) “Why Investigate Metacognition?” in Janet Metcalfe, and Arthur P. Shimamura (eds.) Metacognition: Knowing About Knowing (Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press), p. 18; ital. orig.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See A. Minh Nguyen (2008) “The Authority of Expressive Self-Ascriptions,” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 47, 103–36, for discussion of these two attributes, as well as indubitability and self-intimacy.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. A. C. Miner and L. M. Reder (1994) “Feeling of Knowing and Question Answering,” in Janet Metcalfe, and Arthur P. Shimamura (eds.) Metacognition: Knowing About Knowing (Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press), p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Arthur Shimamura (1994) “The Neuropsychology of Metacognition,” in Janet Metcalfe, and Arthur P. Shimamura (eds.) Metacognition: Knowing About Knowing Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), pp. 253–76.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Edmund Gettier (1963) “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Analysis, 23, 121–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Aquinas ST II.II.45.3, quoting from The Divine Names, in Pseudo-Dionysius AA, The Divine Names and Mystical Theology (trans. J. Jones) (Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press, 1980). Hierotheus, from Athens, was a convert of St. Paul’s.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Jacques Maritain (1966) “Natural Mystical Experience and the Void,” in Joseph W. Evans, and Leo R. Ward (eds.) Jacques Maritain: Challenges and Renewals (South Bend IN: University of Notre Dame Press), p. 80.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Jacques Maritain (1962) A Preface to Metaphysics: Seven Lectures on Being (New York: Mentor Omega, New American Library), p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Jacques Maritain (1961) On the Use of Philosophy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Dom Illtyd Trethowan (1948) Certainty: Philosophical and Theological (Westminster, UK: Dacre Press), p. 43; orig. ital.

    Google Scholar 

  46. St Augustine of Hippo The Trinity, (trans. A. W. Haddan) in Philip Schaff (ed.) A Select Library of the Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers of the Christian Church vol. 3, pp. 1–228, (Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 1956), 9.7.12.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 Phillip H. Wiebe

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wiebe, P.H. (2015). Introduction. In: Intuitive Knowing as Spiritual Experience. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137543585_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics