Advertisement

Religious Dissent in Premodern Islam: Political Usage of Heresy and Apostasy in Nizam Al-Mulk and Ibn Taymiyya

  • Bettina Koch
Chapter
  • 150 Downloads
Part of the The New Middle Ages book series (TNMA)

Abstract

Heresy, along with other heterodox beliefs or defiance, is associated with and often understood as an expression of dissent. Religious heterodoxy is of relatively minor political relevance in secular states as compared to states (i.e., any sociopolitical entity with a ruling function) that use religion as a primary foundation of their legitimacy. In a religious state or a state that uses religion as one of its foundations, expressions of heterodox belief create an “otherness,” implying tacit or open dissent. As John B. Henderson points out, the “otherness” that originates within a culture is perceived as more dangerous than a threat that comes from the outside world, whether from a foreign nation or culture.1 In contrast, identifying and affiliating with the orthodox religion “serves also as a mark for political affiliation.”2 Similarly, not being affiliated with the orthodox belief allows for suspicion that a person does not fully accept the political affiliation and is not fully committed to the obedience that the state or other form of political rule might demand. A state’s dependence on religious orthodoxy for legitimacy, however, is double-edged. This association not only demands that citizens or subjects be seen as affiliated with the orthodox belief but for those in leadership positions to do the same. If the orthodoxy of the leaders is questioned, their political legitimacy may be jeopardized.3 Generally speaking, the interaction between orthodoxy and power applies to all religions that are used, in one way or another, to legitimize political power. However, the ways in which orthodoxy can be created and maintained differ depending on the religion that is used as a source of legitimacy.

Keywords

Death Penalty Muslim Community Prominent Scholar Islamic Philosophy Religious Orthodoxy 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 1.
    John B. Henderson, The Construction of Orthodoxy and Heresy: Neo-Confucianism, Islamic, Jewish, and Early Christian Patterns (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998), 1. In this essay, the use of the diacritic symbols for hamza (’) and ‘ayn (‘) follows The Chicago Manual of Style, 16th ed. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2010). However, a number of works referred to and quoted in this chapter follow different conventions. In such cases, accuracy has been given preference over consistency.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Larry Catá Backer, “Theocratic Constitutionalism: An Introduction to a New Global Legal Ordering,” Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 16 (2009), 133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    The connection between religious orthodoxy and legitimacy in premodern times may seem evident. However, this connection remains of some relevance in the twentieth and twenty-first centuries. In 1974, for instance, President Hafiz al-Assad of Syria, a member of the Alawi branch of Islam, was under political pressure because Syrian Islamists asserted that the Alawis were apostates. In the same year, Pakistan’s Prime Minister Zulfikar Ali Bhutto, under pressure from the Sunni ulema, declared the Ahmadiyas to be nonbelievers. See P. R. Kumaraswamy, “Islam and Minorities: Feed for a Liberal Framework,” Mediterranean Quarterly 18 (2007): 108–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 5.
    Omid Safi, The Politics of Knowledge in Pre-modern Islam: Negotiating Ideology and Religious Inquiry (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 2006), 47.Google Scholar
  5. 6.
    Rudolph Peters, “Apostasy in Islam,” Die Welt des Islams 17 (1977): 17. The significance of al-Ghazali for the doctrine on apostasy, however,Google Scholar
  6. has been recently challenged by Ahmad Atif Ahmad, “Al-Gazālī’s Contribution to the Sunnī Juristic Discourses on Apostasy,” Journal of Arabic and Islamic Studies 7 (2007): 50–73.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    See al-Ghazālī, The Incoherence of the Philosophers: A Parallel English-Arabic Text, trans. Michael E. Marmura (Provo: Brigham Young University Press, 2000);Google Scholar
  8. and, Ibn Taymiyya, Against the Greek Logicians, trans. Wael B. Hallaq (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993).Google Scholar
  9. 8.
    Donald P. Little, “Did Ibn Taymiyya Have a Screw Loose?” Studia Islamica 41 (1975): 96.Google Scholar
  10. 9.
    For Ibn Taymiyya as a theologian, see Jon Hoover’s brilliant study Ibn Taymiyya’s Theodicy of Perpetual Optimism: Islamic Philosophy, Theology and Science. Texts and Studies (Leiden: Brill, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 10.
    Emmanuel Sivan, Radical Islam: Medieval Theology and Modern Politics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1990), 99–101, and “Ibn Taymiyya: Father of the Islamic Revolution, Medieval Theology & Modern Politics,” Encounter 60 (1983): 41–4.Google Scholar
  12. 11.
    Alexander Knysh, “‘Orthodoxy’ and ‘Heresy’ in Medieval Islam: An Essay in Reassessment,” The Muslim World 83 (1993): 65–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. 12.
    This development, which finally led to the establishment of Christianity as it was known in late Roman antiquity and medieval times, has been brilliantly outlined, though not without controversy, by Keith Hopkins, A World Full of Gods: The Strange Triumph of Christianity (New York: Free Press, 2000).Google Scholar
  14. 13.
    Malcolm Lambert, Medieval Heresy: Popular Movements from the Gregorian Reform to the Reformation, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992), 3.Google Scholar
  15. 14.
    Larbi Sadiki, The Search for Arab Democracy: Discourses and Counter-Discourses (New York: Columbia University Press, 2004), 9.Google Scholar
  16. 15.
    See, for instance, John L. Esposito, Islam: The Straight Path, updated ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 41–8.Google Scholar
  17. 16.
    Wael B. Hallaq, The Origins and Evolution of Islamic Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 5–6, 179 (italics in the original).Google Scholar
  18. 17.
    For a brief outline of these four schools—the Hanafis, the Mālikis, the Shāfi‘is, and the Hanbalis—see Mawil Izzi Dien, Islamic Law: From Historical Foundations to Contemporary Practice (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2004), 11–31.Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Richard R. Frank, Al-Gazālī and the Ash‘arite School (Durham: Duke University Press, 1994), 99; and, Dien, Islamic Law, 24.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Mohammed S. El-Awa, Punishment in Islamic Law: A Comparative Study (Indianapolis: American Trust Publications, 1982), 43.Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    For a brief overview of these terms, see Abdullah Saeed and Hassan Saeed, Freedom of Religion, Apostasy and Islam (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2004), 35–42.Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    Erik Ohlander, “Enacting Justice, Ensuring Salvation: The Trope of the ‘Just Ruler’ in Some Medieval Islamic Mirrors for Princes,” The Muslim World 99 (2009): 240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. 23.
    The Sea of Precious Virtues (Baḥr a1-Favā’d), A Medieval Islamic Mirror for Princes, ed. and trans. Julie Scott Meisami (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1991), 26.1.343; 26.5.361. All the groups that are listed as “apostates” are different names of the Isma‘ilis or refer to regions with an Isma‘ili populace.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    S. A. Rahman, Punishment of Apostasy in Islam, 2nd reprint (New Delhi: Kitab Bhavan, 2006), 104–13;Google Scholar
  25. Hazrat Mizra Tahir Ahmed, Murder in the Name of Allah, revised ed. (Cambridge: Lutterworth Press, 1990), 74–92; and, Ahmed Mansour, “Penalty of Apostasy: A Historical and Fundamental Study” (http://www.ahl-alquran.com/English/show_article.php?main_id=523), accessed November 5, 2006.Google Scholar
  26. 27.
    Mohamed Charfi, Islam and Liberty: The Historical Misunderstanding (London: Zed Books, 2005), 50.Google Scholar
  27. 29.
    Ahmad Atif Ahmad, Islam, Modernity, Violence, and Everyday Life (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009), 148, even goes so far as to blame Western Orientalists for the invention of the death penalty doctrine, though, again, without providing any evidence and mainly draws on irrelevant texts.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. 30.
    Michael David Bonner, Jihad in Islamic History: Doctrines and Practices (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006), 120.Google Scholar
  29. 31.
    William Montgomery Watt, Islam and the Integration of Society (London: Kegan Paul, 1961), 104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. 32.
    Sālim Ibn Dhakwān, Sīrat Sālim, in Patricia Crone and Fritz Zimmermann. The Epistle of Sālim Ibn Dhakwān (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 3.133.Google Scholar
  31. 33.
    Abū al-Ḥasan al-Māwardī, The Ordinances of Government: Al-Aḥkām al-Sulṭāniyya w’al-Wilāyāt al-Dīniyya, trans. Wafaa H. Wahba (Reading: Garnet, 1996), 5.1 (63).Google Scholar
  32. 34.
    Patricia Crone, God’s Rule: Government and Islam (New York: Columbia University Press, 2004), 222, 234.Google Scholar
  33. 35.
    Shafique N. Virani, The Ismailis in the Middle Ages: A History of Survival, a Search for Salvation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. 36.
    Richard W. Bulliet, “Local Politics in Eastern Iran under the Ghaznavids and Seljuks,” Iranian Studies 11 (1978): 41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. 37.
    W. B. Bartlett, The Assassins: The Story of Medieval Islam’s Secret Sect (Stroud: Sutton, 2001), 46.Google Scholar
  36. 38.
    Neguin Yavari, “Mirrors for Princes or a Hall of Mirrors?: Nizam al Mulk’s Siyar al-muluk Reconsidered,” al-Masāq: Islam and the Medieval Mediterranean 20 (2008): 55. Safi, The Politics of Knowledge in Pre-modern Islam, 74–7, argues in a similar vein by seeing the background to Nizam al-Mulk’s assassination in the growing tension between Sultan Malik-Shah and his grand vizier over the caliphate’s power, which Malik-Shah would have liked to see abolished altogether.Google Scholar
  37. According to Tilman Nagel, Staat und Glaubensgemeinschaft im Islam: Geschichte der politischen Ordnungsvorstellungen der Muslime, vol. 2: Vom Spätmittelalter bis zur Neuzeit (Zürich: Artemis, 1981), 91, Nizam al-Mulk considers the Isma‘ilis influence on the sultan as the main reason why he has fallen in disgrace with Malik-Shah.Google Scholar
  38. 39.
    See, for instance, Salim Mansur, “The Father of All Assassins,” The Globe and Mail (Toronto), October 11, 2001, A21, who, although a well-respected political scientist, treats the “myths” about the Hasan-i Sabbath as facts. Similarly, Hamit Bozarslan, “Le Jihâd: Réceptions et usages d’une injonction Coranique d’hier à aujourd’hui,” Vingtième Siècle: Revue d’histoire 82 (2004): 28, goes so far as to suggest that at some point in the future, al-Qaida may become another religious sect that leaves Islam, similar to the Nizari Isma’ilis of the eleventh century. These comparisons are neither historically nor intellectually sound. For a scholarly and critically sound reassessment of the Nizari myths,Google Scholar
  39. see Farhad Daftary, The Assassin Legends: Myths of the Isma’ilis (London: I. B. Tauris, 1995).Google Scholar
  40. 40.
    Carole Hillenbrand, “The First Crusade: Muslim Perspective,” in The First Crusade: Origins and Impact, ed. Jonathan Phillips (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1997), 132.Google Scholar
  41. 41.
    Farhad Daftary, The Ismā‘īlīs: Their History and Doctrines (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 324.Google Scholar
  42. 43.
    Farhad Daftary, “Ḥasan-i Ṣabbāh and the Origins of the Nizārī Isma‘ili Movement,” in Medieval Isma‘ili History and Thought, ed. Farhad Daftary (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 181 (quotation), 189.Google Scholar
  43. 45.
    Frank Griffel, Apostasie und Toleranz: Die Entwicklung zu al-Gazālīs Urteil gegen die Philosophie und die Reaktion der Philosophen (Leiden: Brill, 2000), 220, 243, 255 (quotation).Google Scholar
  44. 47.
    Frank Griffel, Al- Ghazali’s Philosophical Theology (London: Oxford University Press, 2009), 102–3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. 49.
    Hamid Dabashi, Shi’ism: A Religion of Protest (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011), 70.Google Scholar
  46. 50.
    Marta Simidchieva, “Kingship and Legitimacy in Nizam al-Mulk’s Siyasatnama, Fifth/Eleventh Century,” in Writers and Rulers: Perspectives on Their Relationship from Abbasid to Safavid Times, ed. Beatrice Gruendler and Louise Marlow (Wiesbaden: Reichert, 2004), 99.Google Scholar
  47. 51.
    Niẓām al-Mulk, The Book of Government or Rules for Kings: The Siyāsat-nāma or Siyar al-Mulūk, trans. Hubert Darke (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1960). Chapters are numbered throughout the book. Therefore, references to The Book of Government refer to chapter and paragraph.Google Scholar
  48. 53.
    Herbert Grundmann, “Der Typus des Ketzers in mittelalterlicher Anschauung,” in Ausgewählte Aufsätze, Vol. 1: Religiöse Bewegungen, ed. Herbert Grundmann (Stuttgart: Anton Hirsemann, 1976), 325.Google Scholar
  49. 56.
    Aptin Khanbaghi, The Fire, the Star and the Cross: Minority Religions in Medieval and Early Modern Iran (London: I. B. Tauris, 2006), 23–4.Google Scholar
  50. 58.
    Julie Scott Meisami, Persian Historiography to the End of the Twelfth Century (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1999), 160–1.Google Scholar
  51. 60.
    Kathryn Babayan, Mystics, Monarchs, and Messiahs: Cultural Landscapes of Early Modern Iran (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002), 170.Google Scholar
  52. 63.
    Nizam al-Mulk, The Book of Government, 44.8. A comparison of the picture Nizam al-Mulk draws with that depicted by the famous Persian poet Abolqasem Ferdow (940–1020) shows a stark contrast. In Ferdow’s narrative, written for the princes of the Samanid dynasty (who ruled from 819 to 1005 in Khurasan and Transoxiania), Mazdak “converts” an unjust ruler to justice, though even in Ferdow’s narrative, Mazdak has an unfortunate end. See Abolqasem Ferdowsi, The Shahnameh: The Persian Book of Kings, trans. Dick Davis (New York: Viking, 2006), 679–84.Google Scholar
  53. 74.
    Yossef Rapoport and Shahab Ahmed, “Ibn Taymiyya and his Times,” in Ibn Taymiyya and His Times, ed. Yossef Rapoport and Shahab Ahmed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 13.Google Scholar
  54. 75.
    For an overview of Ibn Taymiyya’s criticism of Shi‘ism, see Thomas F. Michel, “The Theology of Ibn Taymiyya and His Critique of Christianity,” in A Muslim Theologian’s Response to Christianity: Ibn Taymiyya’s Al-Jawab al Sahih, ed. and trans. Tomas F. Michel (Delmare: Caravan Books, 1984), 56–67.Google Scholar
  55. 77.
    W. Mongomery Watt, Islamic Philosophy and Theology (Piscataway, NJ: Aldine Transaction, 2009), 159.Google Scholar
  56. 78.
    Carole Hillenbrand, The Crusades: Islamic Perspectives (New York: Routledge, 2000), 241.Google Scholar
  57. 80.
    Alfred Morabia, “Ibn Taymiyya, les Juifs et la Tora,” Studia lslamica 49 (1979): 92.Google Scholar
  58. 81.
    Reuven Amitai-Preiss, “Ghazan, Islam and Mongol Tradition: A View from the Mamlūk Sultanate,” Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies 59 (1996): 9–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. 84.
    Ibn Taymiyyah, Ibn Taymiyyah Expounds on Islam: Selected Writings of Shaykh al-Islam Taqi ad-Din Ibn Taymiyyah on Islamic Faith, Life, and Society, compiled and trans. Muhammad Abdul-Haqq Ansari (Riyadh: General Administration of Culture and Publication, 2000), 514 [Fatwa 35].Google Scholar
  60. 87.
    Ibid., 555 [Fatwa 3]. In Ibn Tymiyyah, Kitab Al-Iman: Book of Faith, ed. and trans. Salan Hassan Al-Ani and Shadia Ahmad Tel (Bloomington: Iman Publishing House, 2010), 37, he calls all those who refuse to obey Allah ignorant.Google Scholar
  61. 90.
    Other authors argue that jihad should only be fought in defense but do not call for an aggressive interpretation of jihad. For the mentioned political reason but also out of his rather orthodox beliefs, Ibn Taymiyya does not have similar reservations. As Sherman Jackson points out in “Jihad in the Modern World,” in Islam in Transition: Muslim Perspectives, ed. John J. Donohue and John L. Esposito (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 401, with reference to Ibn Rushd, the “ultimate consideration was the security of the Muslims rather than either conquest or conversion.”Google Scholar
  62. 91.
    Rudolph Peters, Jihad in Classical and Modern Islam: Updated Edition with a Section on Jihad in the 21st Century (Princeton: Wiener, 2005), 43.Google Scholar
  63. 96.
    Frank Griffel, “Toleration and Exclusion: Al-Shāfi’ī and al-Ghazālī on the Treatment of Apostates,” Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies 64 (2001): 352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Karen Bollermann, Thomas M. Izbicki, and Cary J. Nederman 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  • Bettina Koch

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations