Skip to main content

A Suffering God and Post-Holocaust Pragmatism

  • Chapter
  • 58 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter continues the ‘anti-theodicist’ articulation and development of Jamesian pragmatism by introducing some previously unnoticed comparisons between Jamesian pragmatism and Hans Jonas’s approach to ethics and metaphysics, which largely emerges from the need to deal with the Holocaust. For example, James’s and Jonas’s accounts of the ‘finite God’ are examined against this background. Their conceptions of the relation between ethics and metaphysics are strikingly similar but also point toward important differences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. For his explorations of James and pragmatism, see Richard Bernstein, The Pragmatic Turn (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2012)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Hans Jonas, Mortality and Morality: A Search for the Good after Auschwitz, ed. Lawrence Vogel (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1996).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Lawrence Vogel, ‘Editor’s Introduction: Hans Jonas’s Exodus: From German Existentialism to Post-Holocaust Theology,’ in Jonas, Mortality and Morality, pp. 1-40 (here p. 15). Jonas more comprehensively deals with natural existence and the responsibility it yields in some of his previous books (not to be discussed here), including especially Hans Jonas, The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology (New York: Delta, 1966)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  5. On pragmatism and environmental ethics, see Eric Katz and Andrew Light (eds), Environmental Pragmatism (London and New York: Routledge, 1996).

    Google Scholar 

  6. For a pragmatist analysis of the human capacity to construct and use tools, and its philosophical significance, see, for example, John Dewey, Experience and Nature (1929) (Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1986).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 1961).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Douglas Davies, personal communication. Davies’s recent views are available in, for example, Douglas Davies and Hannah Rumble, Natural Burial (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012).

    Google Scholar 

  9. By this phrase we do not have to mean what Levinas means when he regards our ethical duty toward the other as something that is ‘otherwise than being,’ irreducible to ontology. See Emmanuel Levinas, Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence (1969), trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1974).

    Google Scholar 

  10. On James’s debates with Bradley in particular, see T.L.S. Sprigge, James and Bradley: American Truth and British Reality (Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., pp. 139-40. For a helpful comparison of Jonas’s rethinking to some other Jewish proposals to ‘limit’ divine omnipotence, see Berel Lang, ‘Evil, Suffering, and the Holocaust,’ in Lang, Post-Holocaust: Interpretation, Misinterpretation, and the Claims of History (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2005), pp. 32–51.

    Google Scholar 

  12. However, it has been argued by Peter Dews — insightfully invoking Jonas — that it is more difficult to get rid of the theological vocabulary associated with the problem of evil than some secularized thinkers suppose. See Dews, ‘Disenchantment and the Persistence of Evil: Habermas, Jonas, Badiou,’ in Alan D. Schrift (ed.), Modernity and the Problem of Evil (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2005), pp. 51–65.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, trans. Peter Winch (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980), pp. 46

    Google Scholar 

  14. James, ‘The Moral Philosopher and Moral Life,’ in The Will to Believe. See also Ruth Anna Putnam’s discussion of this Jamesian idea, for example, in her ‘The Moral Life of a Pragmatist,’ in Owen Flanagan and Amelie Oksenberg Rorty (eds), Identity, Character and Morality (New York: Brandford Book, 1990), pp. 67–89.

    Google Scholar 

  15. We should, in my view, react with horror to attempts to argue in all philosophical seriousness for such a conclusion, as, for example, in David Benatar, Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  16. Jonas, Mortality and Morality, p. 95. For the concept of natality, see Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2014 Sami Pihlström

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Pihlström, S. (2014). A Suffering God and Post-Holocaust Pragmatism. In: Taking Evil Seriously. Palgrave Pivot, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137412669_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics