Skip to main content

Abstract

Ludwig Wittgenstein, in the attempt to take as far as possible a “naïve” correspondentialist and re presentational ist view on language (Hutto, 2004), had to face a resilient philosophical puzzle on the nature of nonsensical propositions (Wittgenstein, 1921/2001, 4.01): if our knowl- edge of the world is necessarily delimited by its representations, then what should we say about nonsensical expressions that represent nothing at all and that, nonetheless, allow us to relate to what is most valuable in our lives? If non-sense is situated outside the “limits of our language”, which bi-univocally correspond to the articulations of ontology (the “limits of our world”), then why is it the case that our words can capture the very notion of non-sense, allowing us to concur on its meaning? How is it possible that we know how to efficaciously respond to nonsen- sical expressions, and our beliefs seem affected by them in ways that are characteristic and significant?

Don’t for heaven’s sake, be afraid of talking nonsense! Only don’t fail to pay attention to your nonsense.

(Ludwig Wittgenstein, 1998, p. 64)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Barbieri, M. (2006). Life and semiosis: the real nature of information and meaning. Semiotica, 158(1/4), 233–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binswanger, L. (1959). Ìber Martin Heidegger und die Psychiatrie. In Neue Zuercher Zeitung, Beilage, Literatur und Kunst, Sonntag 27. Sept.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camus, A. (1942/1989). The Stranger. (M. Ward, Trans.). New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappuccio, M. L. (2013). Pointing: a gesture that makes us special? Humanamente, 24(1), XI–XV.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappuccio, M., & Shepherd, S. V. (2013). Pointing hand: joint attention and embodied symbols. In Z. Radman (Ed.), The Hand, an Organ of the Mind: What the Manual Tells the Mental (pp. 303–326). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappuccio, M. & Wheeler, M. (2012). Ground-level intelligence: action-oriented representation and the dynamics of the background. In Z. Radman (Ed.), Knowing without Thinking: Mind, Action, Cognition and the Phenomenon of the Background (pp. 13–36). New Directions in Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2006). Cognitive complexity and the sensorimotor frontier. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 80, 43–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2014). The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cosmelli, D., & Thompson, E. (2010). Embodiment or envatment? Reflections on the bodily basis of consciousness. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds), Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science (pp. 361–385). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2007). Participatory sense-making: an enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: values, social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds), Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science (pp. 33–87). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dotov, D. G., Nie, L., & Chemero, A. (2010). A demonstration of the transition from ready-to-hand to unready-to-hand. PLoS ONE, 5(3), e9433. doi: 10.1371/ journal.pone.0009433

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1991). Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2002a). Intelligence without representation — Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2002b). Refocusing the question: can there be skillful coping without propositional representations or brain representations? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 413–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2007). Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing it would require making it more Heideggerian. Philosophical Psychology, 20(2), 247–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. (2012). From adaptive behavior to human cognition: a review of Enaction. Adaptive behavior, 20(3), 209–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. (2013). Altered states and the prehistoric ritualization of the modern-human mind. In C. Adams, A. Waldstein, B. Sessa, D. Luke, & D. King (Eds), Breaking Convention: Essays on Psychedelic Consciousness (pp. 10–21). London, UK: Strange Attractor Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T, & Di Paolo, E. A. (2009). Sociality and the life-mind continuity thesis. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), 439–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., Stanghellini, G., & Bertelli, M. O. (2013). Is it normal to be a principal mindreader? Revising theories of social cognition on the basis of schizophrenia and high functioning autism-spectrum disorders. Research in Developmental Disabilities, 34, 1376–1387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., & Stewart, J. (2010). Life after Ashby: ult rast ability and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Cybernetics & Human Knowing, 17(4), 83–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T, & Stewart, J. (2012). Enactive cognitive science and biology of cognition: a response to Humberto Maturana. Cybernetics & Human Knowing, 19(4), 61–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T, Woodward, A., & Ikegami, T. (2013). Turing instabilities in biology, culture, and consciousness? On the enactive origins of symbolic materia culture. Adaptive behavior, 21(3), 199–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T., & De Jaegher, H. (2009). Enactive intersubjectivity: participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), 465–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2005). Corporealized and disembodied minds: a phenomenological view of the body in melancholia and schizophrenia. Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology, 12, 95–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the Body Shapes the Mind. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008a). Inference or interaction: social cognition without precursors. Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 163–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008b). Are minimal representations still representations? International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 16(3), 351–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. D. (2008). Understanding others through primary interaction and nareative practice. In J. Zlatev, P. Racine, C. Sinha, & E. Itkonen (Eds), The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Inter subjectivity (pp. 17–38). Amsterdam, The Netherlands: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science. London, UK: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R., & Thompson, E. (2003). The mind-body-body problem. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum, 7(1), 23–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1927/1996). Being and Time. (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D.D. (2004). More making sense of nonsense: from logical forms to forms of life. In B. Stocker (Ed.), Post Analytic Tractatus (pp. 127–149). Famham, UK: Ash gate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2013). Exorcising action oriented representations: ridding cognitive science of its Nazgul. Adaptive behavior, 21(3), 142–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds without Content. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. (1959/1997). General Psychopathology. Volumes 1 & 2. (J. Hoenig, & M. W. Hamilton, Trans.). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1992). The burden and blessing of mortality. The Hastings Center Report, 22(1), 34–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, S. D. (2000). Grasping at straws: motor intentionality and the cognitive science of skillful action. In M. A. Wrathall, & J. Malpas (Eds), Heidegger, Coping, and Cognitive Science: Essays in Honor of Hubert L Dreyfus, Volume 2 (pp. 161–177). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, S. D. (2002). Merleau-Ponty on the body: the logic of motor intentional activity, Ratio-New Series, 15(4), 376–391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J., & Wheeler, M. (Eds) (2012). Heidegger and Cognitive Science. New York, NY: Pal grave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, A., & Thompson, E. (2003). Neurophenomenology: integrating subjective experience and brain dynamics in the neuroscience of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10, 31–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R. (2002). Autopoiesis, structural coupling and cognition. Cybernetics & Human Knowing, 9, 5–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F.J. (1980). Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F.J. (1987). The Tree of Knowledge: The Biological Roots of Human Understanding. Boston, MA: Shambhala Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M. (1945/1962) Phenomenology of Perception. (C. Smith, Trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2009). Out of Our Heads: Why You Are Not Your Brain, and Other Lessons from the Biology of Consciousness. New York, NY: Hill and Wang.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2002). Heidegger’s attunement and the neuropsychology of emotion. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 287–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2008). Situated normativity: the normative aspect of embodied cognition in unreflective action, Mind, 117(468), 973–1001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2012). Context-switching and responsiveness to real relevance. In J. Kiverstein, & M. Wheeler (Eds), Heidegger and Cognitive Science. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudrauf, D., Lutz, A., Cosmelli, D., Lachaux, J.-R, & Le Van Quyen, M. (2003). From autopoiesis to neurophenomenology: Francisco Varela’s exploration of the biophysics of being. Biological Research, 36, 27–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1938/2000). Nausea. (R. Baldick, Trans.). London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1943/1962). Camus’ The Outsider. (A. Michels on, Trans.). Literary and Philosophical Essays (pp. 26–44). New York: Collier Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1946/2007). Existentialism is a Humanism. (C. Macomber, Trans.). New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. (2000). From autopoiesis to semantic closure. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 901, 155–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. (2010). Foundational issues in enaction as a paradigm for cognitive science: from the origin of life to consciousness and writing. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds), Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science (pp. 1–31). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1993). Engaged agency and background in Heidegger. In Charles B. Guignon (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger (pp. 317–336). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2004). Life and mind: from autopoiesis to neurophenomenology. A tribute to Francisco Varela. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3, 381–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2005). Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 407–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2011). Reply to commentaries. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(5-6), 176–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torrance, S., & Froese, T. (2011). An inter-enactive approach to agency: participatory sense-making, dynamics, and sociality. Humana. Mente, 15, 21–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. (1991). Organism: a meshwork of selfless selves. In A. I. Tauber (Ed.), Organism and the Origins of Self (pp. 79–107). Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1995). The re-enchantment of the concrete: some biological ingredients for a nouvelle cognitive science. In L. Steels, & R. Brooks (Eds), The Artificial Life Route to Artificial Intelligence (pp. 11–22). Hove, UK: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(4), 330–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1999). The specious present: a neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds), Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science (pp. 266–317). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. G., Maturana, H. R., & Uribe, R. (1974). Autopoiesis: the organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. BioSystems, 5, 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, R J, Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Virgo, N., Egbert, M. D., & Froese, T. (2011). The role of the spatial boundary in autopoiesis. In G. Kampis, I. Karsai, & E. Szathmâry (Eds), Advances in Artificial Life: Darwin Meets von Neumann. 10th European Conference, ECAL 2009 (pp. 234–241). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Uexküll, J. (1934/1957). A stroll through the worlds of animals and men: a picture book of invisible worlds. In C. H. Schiller (Ed.), Instinctive Behavior: The Development of a Modern Concept (pp. 5–80). New York, NY: International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F.J. (2002). Life after Kant: natural purposes and the autopoi-etic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the Cognitive World: The Next Step. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2008). Cognition in context: phenomenology, situated robotics and the frame problem. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 16(3), 323–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M., & Di Paolo E. A. (2011). Existentialism and cognitive science. In F. Joseph, J. Reynolds, & A. Woodward (Eds), The Continuum Companion to Existentialism (pp. 241–259). London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1998). Culture and Value: A Selection from the Posthumous Remains. (G. H. von Wright, Ed., & P. Winch, Trans.). London: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1921/2001). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. 2nd Edition. (B. McGuiness, & D. Pears, Trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953/2009). Philosophical Investigations, 4th Edition. (G. E. M. Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker, & J. Schulte, Trans.). Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2014 Massimiliano Cappuccio and Tom Froese

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cappuccio, M., Froese, T. (2014). Introduction. In: Cappuccio, M., Froese, T. (eds) Enactive Cognition at the Edge of Sense-Making. New Directions in Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137363367_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics