Skip to main content

Possibility and Permission? Intellectual Character, Inquiry, and the Ethics of Belief

  • Chapter
Book cover William James on Religion

Part of the book series: Philosophers in Depth ((PID))

Abstract

David Hollinger points out that

[C]laims about the continuity between [William] James’ ‘The Will to Believe’ [1896] and Varieties of Religious Experience [1902] … are rarely engaged critically because many of the philosophers who address ‘The Will to Believe’ are not much interested in Varieties, and many of the religious studies scholars for whom Varieties is a vital text have relatively little invested in the agendas that drive philosophers’ inter­pretation of ‘The Will to Believe’.2

This already serious problem is compounded if we are specifically trying to understand and evaluate James’ ethics of belief, for as Gregory Pappas rightly notes, ‘the difficulty in reconstructing James’ position in the ethics of belief stems from the fact that there is no place where he explicitly presents it in a comprehensive and systematic way. Rather, it seems, a significant portion of his extensive writing is relevant to its unraveling.’3

In detail all the religious beliefs are illusory or absurd. How hold the dignity of the general function upright in this state of things? … It is a question of life, of living in these gifts or not living, etc. There is a chance todo something strong here, but it is extremely difficult.—James, Manuscript and Essay Notes1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. W. James (1988) Manuscript Essays and Notes (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), #4476, p. 311.

    Google Scholar 

  2. D. Hollinger (2006) ‘Damned for God’s Glory: William James and the Scientific Vindication of Protestant Culture’ in W. Proudfoot (ed.) William James and a Science of Religions ( New York: Columbia University Press ), p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  3. G. Pappas (1994) ‘William James’ Virtuous Believer’, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 30 (1), p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  4. James dedicated Pragmatism to Mill, ‘from whom I first learned the pragmatic openness of mind and whom my fancy likes to picture as our leader were he alive today’. W. James (1975 [1907]) Pragmatism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  5. I. Barbour (2000) When Science Meets Religion: Enemies, Strangers, or Partners? ( San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco ), p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See also H. Jackman (1999) ‘Prudential Arguments, Naturalized Epistemology, and the Will to Believe’, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 35 (1), pp. 1–37.

    Google Scholar 

  7. D. Hollinger (1997) ‘James, Clifford, and the Scientific Conscience’ in R. A. Putnam (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to William James ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press ), p. 80.

    Google Scholar 

  8. J. S. Mill (1859) On Liberty, chapter 3, URL: www.utilitarianism.com/ol/three.html (accessed 11 September, 2012 ).

    Google Scholar 

  9. W. James, ‘The Dilemma of Determinism’ (1979) in F. Burkhardt, F. Bowers, and I. K. Skrupselis (eds.) The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), pp. 117–18. This is quite a contrast to Varieties and still later works like ‘Reason and Faith’, which asserts that ‘the religious question, we agreed, is a question about facts’.

    Google Scholar 

  10. W. James (1927) ‘Reason and Faith’, Journal of Philosophy, 24 (8), p. 199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Gregory Fernando Pappas (1996) ‘ Open- mindedness and Courage: Complementary Virtues of Pragmatism’, p. 78, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 32(2), pp. 316–35. Pappas here quotes

    Google Scholar 

  12. W. James (1978) Essays in Philosophy ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press ), p. 332.

    Google Scholar 

  13. W. James ( 1979 [1896]) The Will to Believe ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), p. xii.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Wernham writes that ‘The ladder is not advocacy but description … If one compares James’ will-to-believe doctrine and the ladder, one finds differences between them and similarities too. The will-to-believe doctrine is advocacy.’ J. C. S. Wernham (1987) James’s Will- To- Believe Doctrine: A Heretical View (Montreal: McGill-Queens University Press; 1st edn).

    Google Scholar 

  15. W. James (1917 [1910]) ‘Faith and the Right to Believe’ in Some Problems of Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), p. 223.

    Google Scholar 

  16. On descriptive fideism and philosophical disputes about it, see also L. Pojman (1986) Religious Belief and the Will ( London: Routledge and Kegan Paul), chapter 9.

    Google Scholar 

  17. W. James (1987) Essays, Comments, Reviews ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press ), p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  18. W. James ( 2002 [1902]) The Varieties of Religious Experience ( New York: Dover Publications ), p. 526.

    Google Scholar 

  19. J. E. Smith (1985) ‘Introduction’ in W. James, The Varieties of Religious Experience ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), p. xlii.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See I. Lakatos (1978) The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. The connections between James and Duhem are historical as well as logical, as Isaac Nevo points out. See Isaac Nevo, ‘Continuing Empiricist Epistemology: Holistic Aspects of William James’s Pragmatism’, The Monist 75 (1992), pp. 458–76. Given the basic correctness of Duhemian confirmation holism, Lakatos concludes that evaluation in science is comparative and historical: ‘But, of course, if falsification depends on the emergence of better theories ... then falsification is not simply a relation between a theory and the empirical basis, but a multiple relation between competing theories, the original “empirical basis”, and the empirical growth resulting from the competition’ (ibid., p. 35).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Other proponents of this sort of moderate fideism might be J. Welchman (2006) ‘William James’s “The Will to Believe” and the Ethics of Self-Experimentation’, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 42 (2), 229–41;

    Google Scholar 

  23. J. Bishop (2007) Belief by Faith: An Essay in the Epistemology and Ethics of Religious Belief ( Oxford: Oxford University Press);

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. and E. Suckiel (1997) Heaven’s Champion: William James’s Philosophy of Religion ( Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press).

    Google Scholar 

  25. R. Pouivet (2010) ‘Moral and Epistemic Virtues: A Thomistic and Analytical Perspective’, Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy, 15 (1), p. 2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. S. Napier (2009) Virtue Epistemology: Motivation and Knowledge ( London: Continuum ), p. 144.

    Google Scholar 

  27. S. Haack (1997) ‘The Ethics of Belief Reconsidered’ in L. Hahn (ed.) The Philosophy of Roderick M. Chisholm ( LaSalle, IL: Open Court ), p. 130.

    Google Scholar 

  28. James, The Will to Believe, p. 8. Compare how close the passage is to late James: ‘Faith thus remains as one of the inalienable birthrights of our mind. Of course it must remain a practical, and not a dogmatical attitude. It must go with toleration of other faiths, with the search for the most probable, and with the full consciousness of responsibilities and risks’ (James, ‘Faith and the Right to Believe’, p. 113). On cognitive risk-taking and personal identity, see Jennifer Welchman’s “William James’s ‘The Will to Believe’ and the Ethics of Self-Experimentation,” Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 42.2 (2006), 229–241.

    Google Scholar 

  29. R. Audi (2008) ‘The Ethics of Belief: Doxastic Self- Control and Intellectual Virtue’, Synthese, 161 (3), p. 416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. R. Audi (2011) ‘The Ethics of Belief and the Morality of Action: Intellectual Responsibility and Rational Disagreement’, Philosophy, 86, p. 28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. R. A. Christian (2009) ‘Restricting the Scope of the Ethics of Belief: Haack’s Alternative to Clifford and James’, Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 77 (3), p. 489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. J. Rawls (1995) Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press), p. 249. We err gravely in trying to reduce ‘reasonable’ people and reasonable ‘disagreement’ to the elusive evidentialist’s notion of synchronic rationality or evidential ‘fit’. If the Overlap Thesis is correct, and helps us, as Haack has argued, to conceptualize the sources of normativity that an ethics of belief draws upon, then reasonable habits of inquiry, proper intellectual motivation and a more holistic account of the relationship between ‘overbeliefs’ and their grounds, is clearly called for.

    Google Scholar 

  33. P. Clayton (1989) Explanation from Physics to Theology: An Essay in Rationality and Religion ( New Haven: Yale University Press ), p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  34. R. Pouivet (2002) ‘Religious Imagination and Virtue Epistemology’, Ars Disputandi, 2, pp. 3–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. M. Moffett (2007) ‘Reasonable Disagreement and Rational Group Inquiry’, Episteme, 4, p. 360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. N. Murphy (1997) Reconciling Theology and Science: A Radical Reformation Perspective (Scottsdale, PA: Pandora Press), p. 18. What James calls ‘intellectual operations’ related to religion (James, Varieties, p. 433) include primarily those of our overbeliefs, those of philosophy, and those of a science of religion.

    Google Scholar 

  37. M. Thune (2010) ‘Religious Belief and the Epistemology of Disagreement’, Philosophy Compass, 5 (8), p. 713.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. G. Pappas (1994) ‘William James’ Virtuous Believer’, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 30 (1), p. 86.

    Google Scholar 

  39. J. Dewey, The Middle Works, Vol. 12: 1899–1924 (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 2008), p. 220. See Pappas, ‘William James’ Virtuous Believer’, for comments. James, of course, also contrasts the evidentialist’s universal ‘veto’ of experiments of living with an alternative personal and social ethic highlighting ‘the spirit of inner tolerance, which is empiricism’s glory’, returning us to the Rawlsian concerns treated above.

    Google Scholar 

  40. G. Gutting (1982) Religious Belief and Religious Skepticism ( West Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press ), pp. 175–6.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2013 Guy Axtell

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Axtell, G. (2013). Possibility and Permission? Intellectual Character, Inquiry, and the Ethics of Belief. In: Rydenfelt, H., Pihlström, S. (eds) William James on Religion. Philosophers in Depth. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137317353_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics