Skip to main content

Anti-Dogmatism as a Defense of Religious Belief

  • Chapter
William James on Religion

Part of the book series: Philosophers in Depth ((PID))

  • 200 Accesses

Abstract

William James asserts that philosophy and science will only have something positive to contribute to determining the objective truth of religious claims when they cease to be dogmatic and become experimental. In this chapter, I focus on how James’ anti-dogmatic approach affects his defense of religious belief and psychical research. I conclude that in his efforts to undermine the dogmatic rejection of the very possibility of genuine religious phenomena by positivistic scientists and naturalist non-believers, James appeals to the pragmatic experimental method but is unable to produce convincing evidence. His version of pragmatic anti-dogmatism is then contrasted with John Dewey’s.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. R. A. McDermott, Introduction to W. James (1986) Essays in Psychical Research ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), p. xix.

    Google Scholar 

  2. W. James (1901) ‘Frederic Myer’s Service to Psychology’ in Essays in Psychical Research, p. 197.

    Google Scholar 

  3. W. James (1984) The Varieties of Religious Experience ( New York: Penguin American Library ), pp. 433, 455–6.

    Google Scholar 

  4. W. James (1975) Pragmatism ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press ), pp. 32–3.

    Google Scholar 

  5. C. H. Seigfried (1990) William James’s Radical Reconstruction of Philosophy ( Albany: State University of New York Press ), pp. 238–9.

    Google Scholar 

  6. W. James (1976) Essays in Radical Empiricism ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press ), p. 81.

    Google Scholar 

  7. W. James (1975) The Meaning of Truth (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), pp. 6–7. James’ claim that relations are directly experienced is defended in

    Google Scholar 

  8. C. H. Seigfried (1978) Chaos and Context: A Study in William James ( Athens, OH: Ohio University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  9. For James’ inability to accept women and other marginalized ethnic and racial groups as fully human, see chapter 6, ‘The Feminine Mystical Threat to the Scientific- Masculine Order’, in C. H. Seigfried (1996) Pragmatism and Feminism: Reweaving the Social Fabric ( Chicago: University of Chicago Press ), pp. 111–41.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See C. H. Seigfried (2000) ‘The Philosopher’s “License”: William James and Common Sense’ in K. Oehler (ed.) William James: Pragmatism (Berlin: Akademie Verlag), pp. 93–110. James always characterizes philosophers as male and takes mysticism as a more typically female experience. See Seigfried, Pragmatism and Feminism, pp. 131–41.

    Google Scholar 

  11. As Sami Pihlström argues, and the preceding pages explain, James’ humanized pragmatism means that no higher perspective on truth and falsity is available to us than our own best, most critical practices. However, it also seems clear that the warrant James seeks would be epistemically as well as religiously convincing. I am arguing that James fails to prove his religious claims according to his own well- founded pragmatist criteria. Pihlström’s recognition of ‘a deep structural analogy between pragmatically reconstructed transcendental arguments and Jamesian will to believe arguments’ seems a promising way to reconstruct James’ position to make it more plausible. S. Pihlström (2008) ‘The Trail of the Human Serpent is Over Everything’: Jamesian Perspectives on Mind, World, and Religion ( Lanham, MD: University Press of America ), pp. 46–7.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Quoted in R. B. Perry (1935) The Thought and Character of William James, Vol. 2 (Boston: Little, Brown ), p. 455.

    Google Scholar 

  13. W. James (1979) The Will to Believe ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press ), p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  14. R. A. Moody, foreword, in M. Morse with P. Perry (1990) Closer to the Light ( New York: Villard Books), p. xii;

    Google Scholar 

  15. M. Morse with P. Perry (1990) Transformed by the Light ( New York: Villard Books), p. ix.

    Google Scholar 

  16. William James (1981 [1890]) The Principles of Psychology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), Vol. 2, pp. 923–4.

    Google Scholar 

  17. W. James ( 1986 [1901]) ‘Frederic Myer’s Service to Psychology’ in Essays in Psychical Research ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press ), pp. 192–201.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Moody, Closer to the Light, p. xi; and H. Smith (2000) Cleansing the Doors of Perception (New York: Jeremy P. Tarcher/Putnam), pp. xvi, 78.

    Google Scholar 

  19. C. S. Peirce (1982) Pragmatism: The Classic Writings, ed. H. S. Thayer (Indianapolis: Hackett ), p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  20. In a companion essay to this one, I question James’ sanguine belief that religious beliefs have nothing to fear from scientific scrutiny. I also argue that Dewey took up James’ naturalistic religious project and exposed his biased assumptions and faulty reasoning, while also missing his own subjective assumptions in regard to science. See C. H. Seigfried (2012) ‘Distinguishing Myth from Reality: Are Pragmatic Tools Sufficient?’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 66 (260), Special issue on William James, pp. 187–205.

    Google Scholar 

  21. J. Dewey (1957 [1922]) Human Nature and Conduct (New York: Modern Library). He does mention religious experience in passing when he criticizes James’ defense of taking moral holidays, pp. 242–3, and, like James, he thinks that institutional religion fosters dogmatism and intolerance, pp. 301–2.

    Google Scholar 

  22. J. Dewey (1988) Experience and Nature, in Later Works, Vol. 1: 1925 ( Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press ), p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2013 Charlene Haddock Seigfried

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Seigfried, C.H. (2013). Anti-Dogmatism as a Defense of Religious Belief. In: Rydenfelt, H., Pihlström, S. (eds) William James on Religion. Philosophers in Depth. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137317353_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics