Skip to main content

Constituents of a Theory

  • Chapter
Book cover Constitutive Justice
  • 92 Accesses

Abstract

Valuable though the insights contained in the transcommunal approaches that we have examined may be, they represent only the beginnings of full-scale theories of constitutive justice. The interdependence model, the eudaemonist-recognition model, the pragmatic-democratic model, and the deconstructionist model all present promising trajectories for developing constructive, systematic frameworks for evaluating prospective rationales for moral and political boundaries around communities of justice, even as they identify problems and lacunae that such frameworks need to address.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. I discuss the notion of reflective equilibrium below in Chapter 7. On the notion of an overlapping consensus, see John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. Erin Kelly (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), pp. 32–38.

    Google Scholar 

  2. On “fit” as an interpretive concept and on the relation between law and the politics of integrity, see Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Although they do not quite effectively thematize the problem of constitutive justice as I have developed it, two valuable recent studies in the comparative ethics of boundaries do give a sense of the range that such theories might take. See David Miller and Sohail H. Hashmi, eds, Boundaries and Justice: Diverse Ethical Perspectives (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001);

    Google Scholar 

  4. Allen Buchanan and Margaret Moore, eds, States, Nations, and Borders: The Ethics of Making Boundaries (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Rogers M. Smith, Stories of Peoplehood: The Politics and Morals of Political Membership (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).

    Google Scholar 

  6. William A. Barbieri Jr., Ethics of Citizenship: Immigration and Group Rights in Germany (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  7. I recognize that this statement might be countered by perspectives, internal to some religious communities, that peoples are shaped by divine fiat or other nonhuman forms of action, such that one might argue, for example, that the answer to the question “Who is a Jew?” can be resolved only with respect to sacred sources of authority. But even such a question admits of hermeneutical dimensions: scripture must be interpreted and applied, with an ineliminable component of human practical reasoning involved. Historically and sociologically, religions are subject to many of the same power-political, structural, and discursive processes of formation as other large-scale social groups: see, for example, Talal Asad, Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003);

    Google Scholar 

  8. Tomoko Masuzawa, The Invention of World Religions: Or, How European Universalism Was Preserved in the Language of Pluralism (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2005). In the case of Judaism, an additional legal-political dimension of agency is introduced through the link binding Israeli citizenship to the Jewish people.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. Marion Smiley, Moral Responsibility and the Boundaries of Community: Power and Accountability from a Pragmatic Point of View (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1992), esp. pp. 179–224.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. See Christopher List and Philip Pettit, Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  11. See Hannah Arendt, “Collective Responsibility,” in James Bernhauer, ed., Amor Mundi (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1987), pp. 43–50.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  12. A useful overview is Larry May, The Morality of Groups: Collective Responsibility, Group-Based Harms, and Corporate Rights (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  13. See also Carol Rovane, The Bounds of Agency: An Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Durkheim developed this conception in several works, beginning with The Division of Labor in Society (1893). See also John Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (New York: Free Press, 1995);

    Google Scholar 

  15. Margaret Gilbert, On Social Facts (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  16. R.G. Collingwood, The New Leviathan: Or Man, Society, Civilization and Barbarism (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1942), pp. 148–60.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Raimo Tuomela, The Philosophy of Sociality: The Shared Point of View (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  18. Axel Honneth and Hans Joas, Social Action and Human Nature, Raymond Mayer, trans. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), is an excellent introduction into this field.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Mary Douglas, How Institutions Think (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1987). Her conclusion is that “[f]or better or worse, individuals really do share their thoughts and they do to some extent harmonize their preferences, and they have no other way to make the big decisions except within the scope of institutions they build” (p. 128).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, Colin Smith, trans. (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962), esp. pp. 387–407.

    Google Scholar 

  21. On this point, see Larry May, Genocide: A Normative Account (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  22. See Scott Straus, The Order of Genocide: Race, Power, and War in Rwanda (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2006).

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Timothy Longman, “Identity Cards, Ethnic Self-Perception, and Genocide in Rwanda,” in Jane Caplan and John Torpey, eds, Documenting Individual Identity: The Development of State Practices in the Modern World (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), pp. 345–58.

    Google Scholar 

  24. On the latter connection, see James Jay Carney, Rwanda Before the Genocide: Catholic Politics and Ethnic Discourse in the Late Colonial Era (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  25. Robin Lovin and Frank Reynolds, Cosmogony and Ethical Order: New Studies in Comparative Ethics (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1985);

    Google Scholar 

  26. Nancey Murphy and George Ellis, On the Moral Nature of the Universe: Theology, Cosmology, and Ethics (Minneapolis: Augsburg Fortress, 1996);

    Google Scholar 

  27. Jerome Bruner, “The Narrative Construction of Reality,” Critical Inquiry 18.1 (August 1991): 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. See, e.g., Martha Nussbaum, Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992);

    Google Scholar 

  29. Robert Coles, The Call of Stories: Teaching and the Moral Imagination (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1990);

    Google Scholar 

  30. Wayne Booth, The Company We Keep: An Ethics of Fiction (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  31. See Stanley Hauerwas, “The Self as Story: Religion and Morality from the Agent’s Perspective,” Journal of Religious Ethics 1.1 (1973): 73–85; and Iris Murdoch, The Sovereignty of Good (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Margaret R. Somers, “The Narrative Constitution of Identity: A Relational and Network Approach,” Theory and Society 23 (1994): 605–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Ricoeur describes the “historiographical operation” as the means by which historians participate in a “circle of interpretation” through which they reassess and narrate the story embodied in the “collective memory” of a group. See his Memory, History, Forgetting, Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer, trans. (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2004). On the manner in which historical sciences are complemented by literary narratives and other modes such as film and architecture, see Homi K. Bhabha, ed., Nation and Narration (London: Routledge, 1990);

    Google Scholar 

  34. Stefan Berger et al., Narrating the Nation: Representations in History, Media, and the Arts (New York: Berghahn Books, 2008).

    Google Scholar 

  35. Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origins and Spread of Nationalism (London: Verso, 1983), p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Charles Tilly, Identities, Boundaries, and Social Ties (London: Paradigm Publishers, 2005), p. 134.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See also Sarah Green, “A Sense of Border: The Story So Far,” in The Blackwell Companion to Border Studies, Thomas M. Wilson and Hastings Donnan, eds (Oxford: Blackwell, 2012), pp. 573–92.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  38. See, e.g., Yasemin Nuhoglu Soysal, The Limits of Citizenship: Migrants and Postnational Citizenship in Europe (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1994);

    Google Scholar 

  39. Linda Bosniak, The Alien and the Citizen: Dilemmas of Contemporary Membership (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  40. On the latter, see Saskia Sassen, The Global City: New York, London, Tokyo (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  41. Saskia Sassen, Territory, Authority, Rights: From Medieval to Global Assemblages (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006), p. 416.

    Google Scholar 

  42. On the relation between nation and people in modern politics, see Bernard Yack, “Popular Sovereignty and Nationalism,” Political Theory 29.4 (2001): 517–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Charles Tilly, “Social Boundary Mechanisms,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34.2 (2004): 211–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. On the latter history, see, e.g., Matthew Pratt Guterl, The Color of Race in America, 1900–1940 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002).

    Google Scholar 

  45. For a quite nuanced overview, see Harrison C. White, Identity and Control: How Social Formations Emerge, 2nd ed. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2008).

    Google Scholar 

  46. Miller and Hashmi, Boundaries and Justice, pp. 95, 103, 106, 210. Religions’ self-definitions can clash with those of the state. On the impact of government policies on religious boundaries in multicultural societies such as Canada and Israel, see Rene Provost, ed., Mapping the Legal Boundaries of Belonging: Religion and Multiculturalism from Israel to Canada (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014).

    Google Scholar 

  47. Edward Said, Orientalism (New York: Pantheon, 1978);

    Google Scholar 

  48. Lionel M. Jensen, Manufacturing Confucianism: Chinese Traditions and Universal Civilization (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  49. See Geoffrey C. Bowker and Susan Leigh Star, Sorting Things Out: Classification and Its Consequences (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999), pp. 195–226.

    Google Scholar 

  50. See, for example, Florin Curta, ed., Borders, Boundaries and Ethnogenesis: Frontiers in Late Antiquity and the Middle Ages (Washington, DC: Brepols Publishers, 2006).

    Google Scholar 

  51. Jan and Aleida Assmann, Schrift und Gedächtnis: Beiträge zur Archäologie der literarischen Kommunikation. (München: Fink, 1987);

    Google Scholar 

  52. Aleida Assmann and Linda Shortt, eds, Memory and Political Change (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011).

    Google Scholar 

  53. For a study that analyzes how the global state system and international relations interact with nation-building, see Harris Mylonas, The Politics of Nation-Building: Making Co-Nationals, Refugees, and Minorities (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  54. Nancy Fraser, “Reframing Justice in a Globalizing World,” New Left Review 36 (2005): 1–19;

    Google Scholar 

  55. Miranda Fricker, Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 147–77.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  56. On this point, see R.E. Ewin, “On Justice and Injustice,” Mind 79. 314 (1970): 200–216;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Eric Heinze, The Concept of Injustice (London: Routledge, 2013).

    Google Scholar 

  58. claine Scarry, On Beauty and Being Just (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  59. Amartya Sen, The Idea of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009).

    Google Scholar 

  60. Philip Alston, “Conjuring Up New Human Rights: A Proposal for Quality Control,” American Journal of International Law 78 (1984): 607–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Pierre Bourdieu et al., The Weight of the World: Social Suffering in Contemporary Society, Priscilla Parkhurst Ferguson, trans. (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  62. Iris Marion Young, “Five Faces of Oppression,” in Lisa Heldke and Peg O’Connor, eds, Oppression, Privilege, and Resistance (Boston, MA: McGraw-Hill, 2004).

    Google Scholar 

  63. D.D. Raphael, Concepts of Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001), p. 243.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Elizabeth Wolgast, The Grammar of Justice (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987). For an argument that “the concept of injustice wears the trousers, so that any satisfactory account of justice must be a negative account,” see Ewin, “On Justice and Injustice,” p. 202.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Cf. Deborah Fitzmaurice, “Justice, Practical Reason and Boundaries,” in Percy B. Lehning and Albert Weale, eds, Citizens, Democracy, and Justice in the New Europe (London: Routledge, 1997), pp. 15–33.

    Google Scholar 

  66. See also the proposal from Bas Schotel, On the Right of Exclusion: Law, Ethics, and Immigration Policy (London: Routledge, 2011).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 William A. Barbieri Jr.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Barbieri, W.A. (2015). Constituents of a Theory. In: Constitutive Justice. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137263254_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics