Skip to main content

The Problems with the Deracialization Argument

  • Chapter
Equality and Transparency
  • 47 Accesses

Abstract

The first category of problems is a function of the apparent contradiction between the requirement of neutrality and universality typical of legal discourse and the content of the sociological judgment underlying the justification for affirmative action that I have been arguing for. Indeed, this judgment involves acknowledging the sui generis nature of the disadvantage experienced by black Americans, a task for which judges are particularly ill equipped.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See generally Jürgen Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Cambridge (Mass.), MIT Press, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See generally Ruth O’Brien, Crippled Justice: The History of Modern Disability Policy in the Workplace, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 2001;

    Google Scholar 

  3. Linda Hamilton Krieger, ed., Backlash against the ADA: Reinterpreting Disability Rights, Ann Harbor, University of Michigan Press, 2003. Broadly speaking, the Americans with Disabilities Act amounts to extending the reach of the Supreme Court’s Griggs decision—construing Tide VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act as prohibiting disparate impact discrimination, whether intentional or not (see supra, pp. 118–124)—to discrimination based on handicap. To consider a most basic example, making it impossible for people to access their workplace other than by a staircase, because this has a (particularly obvious) disparate impact on those who are confined to a wheelchair, is now held to be “discriminatory” under statutory law;

    Google Scholar 

  4. see generally Christine Jolls, “Antidiscrimination and Accommodation,” Harvard Law Review, 115, December 2001, pp. 642–699; Michael Ashldey Stein, “Same Struggle, Different Difference: ADA Accommodations and Antidiscrimination,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 153 (2), 2004, pp. 579–673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Mary Waters, Ethnic Options: Choosing Identities in America, Berkeley, University of California Press, 1990, pp. 157–158.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., pp. 155–164. In this connection, see also John David Skrentny, “Policy-Elite Perceptions and Social Movement Success: Understanding Variations in Group Inclusion in Affirmative Action,” American Journal of Sociology, 111 (6), 2006, especially pp. 1782–1787.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. This example was initially offered by Paul Brest; see Paul Brest, Processes of Constitutional Decision-Making, Boston, Little, Brown, 1975, p. 489.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Andrew Koppelman, Antidiscrimination Law and Social Equality, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1996, pp. 24–27.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Koppelman justifies this project of cultural transformation by emphasizing the permanence of racism, the effects of which are all the more unaffected by antidiscrimination legislation that mem-bers of the dominant group are not necessarily aware of it (pp. 45–46). Yet, while unconscious racism and discrimination are surely at play in many cases (see generally Charles Lawrence III, “The Id, the Ego, and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism,” Stanford Law Review, 39, January 1987, pp. 317–388;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Samuel Bagenstos, “The Structural Turn and the Limits of Antidiscrimination Law,” Califomia Law Review, 94 (1), 2006, pp. 1–47, as well as the “Symposium on Behavioral Realism” published in the Califomia Law Review (94 (4), 2006, pp. 945–1190); for a critique of the unconscious discrimination paradigm, see Gregory Mitchell and Philip E. Tetlock, “Antidiscrimination Law and the Perils of Mindreading,” Ohio State Law Journal, 67 (5), 2006, pp. 1023–1121), one should also pay attention to those “dogmatic belief[s]” discussed by Tocqueville, that are not usually subject to scmtiny and stand as the informational background against which individual actions are carried out. Indeed, “if man were forced to demonstrate to himself all the truths of which he makes daily use, his task would have no end. He would exhaust his strength in preparatory exercises, without advancing beyond them. As, from the shortness of his life, he has no time, nor, from the limits of his intelligence, the capacity, to accomplish this, he is reduced to take upon trust a number of ficts and opinions …; nor is he led to proceed in this man-ner by choice, so much as he is constrained by the inflexible law of his condition” (Tocqueville, Democracy in America, vol. 2, pp. 8–9). These “dogmatic belief[s]” pertaining to racial identities, or a fraction of them, are precisely what affirmative action is meant to transform: as Tocqueville suggests, such beliefs “may change [their] object or [their] form” as a result of some recurring “experience,” which is actually the only way of “shaking the majority in an opinion once conceived” and of “uproot[ing] the prejudices of a democratic people” (pp. 8, 309).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. François Furet, “Préface,” in Alexis de Tocqueville, De la démocratie en Amérique, Paris, Gamier-Flammarion, 1981 [1835–1840], vol. 1, p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  12. On the notion of “role model,” see Adeno Addis, “Role Models and the Politics of Recognition,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 144 (4), 1996, pp. 1377–1468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. See Bernadette Gray-Little and Adam R. Hafdahl, “Factors Influencing Racial Comparisons of Self-Esteem: A Quantitative Review,” Psychological Bulletin, 126 (1), 2000, pp. 26–54;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Jennifer Crocker and Brenda Major, “Social Stigma and Self-Esteem: The Self-Protective Properties of Stigma,” Psychological Review, 96, 1989, pp. 608–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. See Sniderman and Piazza, The Scar of Race, pp. 44–46. Some argue that it is paradoxically the disappearance of official discrimination against blacks that have made them more vulnerable to these rumors of inferiority, since they are now supposedly able to demonstrate their invalidity by dint of their own accomplishments; see Jeff Howard and Ray Hammond, “Rumors of Inferiority,” The New Republic, September 9, 1985, pp. 17–21; see also Brenda Major, Steven Spencer, Toni Schmader, Connie Wolfe, and Jennifer Crocker, “Coping with Negative Stereotypes about Intellectual Performance: The Role of Psychological Disengagement,” Personality and Social Psychological Bulletin, 24 (1), 1998, pp. 34–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. See Samuel Huntington, American Politics: The Promise of Disharmony, Cambridge (Mass.), Harvard University Press, 1981, pp. 33–37.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Jon Elster, Psychologie politique (Veyne, Zinoviev, Tocqueville), Paris, Editions de Minuit, 1990, pp. 78–79.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid.; Elster, Psychologie politique, p. 51 ; Jon Elster, “Is There (or Should There Be) a Right to Work?” in Amy Gutmann, ed., Democracy and the Welfare State, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1988, p. 74.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2007 Daniel Sabbagh

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sabbagh, D. (2007). The Problems with the Deracialization Argument. In: Equality and Transparency. The CERI Series in International Relations and Political Economy. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230607392_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics